Next Issue
Volume 1, June
 
 

Games, Volume 1, Issue 1 (March 2010) – 5 articles , Pages 1-65

  • Issues are regarded as officially published after their release is announced to the table of contents alert mailing list.
  • You may sign up for e-mail alerts to receive table of contents of newly released issues.
  • PDF is the official format for papers published in both, html and pdf forms. To view the papers in pdf format, click on the "PDF Full-text" link, and use the free Adobe Reader to open them.
Order results
Result details
Section
Select all
Export citation of selected articles as:
188 KiB  
Article
(Un)Bounded Rationality in Decision Making and Game Theory – Back to Square One?
by Werner Güth and Hartmut Kliemt
Games 2010, 1(1), 53-65; https://doi.org/10.3390/g1010053 - 23 Mar 2010
Cited by 2 | Viewed by 8122
Abstract
Game and decision theory start from rather strong premises. Preferences, represented by utilities, beliefs represented by probabilities, common knowledge and symmetric rationality as background assumptions are treated as “given.” A richer language enabling us to capture the process leading to what is “given” [...] Read more.
Game and decision theory start from rather strong premises. Preferences, represented by utilities, beliefs represented by probabilities, common knowledge and symmetric rationality as background assumptions are treated as “given.” A richer language enabling us to capture the process leading to what is “given” seems superior to the stenography of decision making in terms of utility cum probability. However, similar to traditional rational choice modeling, boundedly rational choice modeling, as outlined here, is far from being a “global” theory with empirical content; rather it serves as a tool to formulate “local” theories with empirical content. Full article
366 KiB  
Article
The Influence of Priming on Reference States
by Astrid Matthey
Games 2010, 1(1), 34-52; https://doi.org/10.3390/g1010034 - 16 Mar 2010
Cited by 6 | Viewed by 9969
Abstract
Experimental and empirical evidence shows that the utility an individual derives from a certain state depends on the reference state she compares it to. According to economic theory, the reference state is determined by past, present and future outcomes of either the individual [...] Read more.
Experimental and empirical evidence shows that the utility an individual derives from a certain state depends on the reference state she compares it to. According to economic theory, the reference state is determined by past, present and future outcomes of either the individual herself or her reference group. The experiment described in this paper suggests that, in addition, reference states depend to a significant degree on environmental factors not relevant for outcomes. It indicates that reference states - and hence utility - can relatively easily be influenced without changing people’s outcomes, e.g., through priming. Full article
Show Figures

Figure 1

271 KiB  
Article
Punishment, Cooperation, and Cheater Detection in “Noisy” Social Exchange
by Gary Bornstein and Ori Weisel
Games 2010, 1(1), 18-33; https://doi.org/10.3390/g1010018 - 15 Mar 2010
Cited by 28 | Viewed by 11476
Abstract
Explaining human cooperation in large groups of non-kin is a major challenge to both rational choice theory and the theory of evolution. Recent research suggests that group cooperation can be explained by positing that cooperators can punish non-cooperators or cheaters. The experimental evidence [...] Read more.
Explaining human cooperation in large groups of non-kin is a major challenge to both rational choice theory and the theory of evolution. Recent research suggests that group cooperation can be explained by positing that cooperators can punish non-cooperators or cheaters. The experimental evidence comes from public goods games in which group members are fully informed about the behavior of all others and cheating occurs in full view. We demonstrate that under more realistic information conditions, where cheating is less obvious, punishment is much less effective in enforcing cooperation. Evidently, the explanatory power of punishment is constrained by the visibility of cheating. Full article
Show Figures

Graphical abstract

284 KiB  
Article
Pairwise Comparison Dynamics and Evolutionary Foundations for Nash Equilibrium
by William H. Sandholm
Games 2010, 1(1), 3-17; https://doi.org/10.3390/g1010003 - 1 Dec 2009
Cited by 56 | Viewed by 10697
Abstract
We introduce a class of evolutionary game dynamics — pairwise comparison dynamics — under which revising agents choose a candidate strategy at random, switching to it with positive probability if and only if its payoff is higher than the agent’s current strategy. We [...] Read more.
We introduce a class of evolutionary game dynamics — pairwise comparison dynamics — under which revising agents choose a candidate strategy at random, switching to it with positive probability if and only if its payoff is higher than the agent’s current strategy. We prove that all such dynamics satisfy Nash stationarity: the set of rest points of these dynamics is always identical to the set of Nash equilibria of the underlying game. We also show how one can modify the replicator dynamic and other imitative dynamics to ensure Nash stationarity without increasing the informational demands placed on the agents. These results provide an interpretation of Nash equilibrium that relies on large numbers arguments and weak requirements on payoff observations rather than on strong equilibrium knowledge assumptions. Full article
21 KiB  
Editorial
Games: An Interdisciplinary Open Access Journal
by Carlos Alós-Ferrer
Games 2010, 1(1), 1-2; https://doi.org/10.3390/g1010001 - 30 Sep 2009
Viewed by 6376
Abstract
Over the last fifty years, game theory has evolved from a mathematical theory of optimal behaviour in stylized situations (“games”) to a general theory of human behaviour, be it actually observed or normatively desirable. Its scope includes both the mathematical modelling and analysis [...] Read more.
Over the last fifty years, game theory has evolved from a mathematical theory of optimal behaviour in stylized situations (“games”) to a general theory of human behaviour, be it actually observed or normatively desirable. Its scope includes both the mathematical modelling and analysis of competition and conflict and the study of human behaviour in strategic contexts and its determinants. Nowadays, game theory has become the language of economics and is increasingly becoming one of the main methods of analysis in several social sciences. Its theoretical underpinnings can be viewed as a mathematical subdiscipline, while its more behavioural offshoots benefit from cross-fertilization with psychology. Game theory has grown within economics but is, by its very nature, interdisciplinary, to the extent that no game theorist can or should define him or herself in disciplinary terms anymore. [...] Full article
Next Issue
Back to TopTop