Philosophy Untouched by Science? Zeno’s Runner, Sextus’ Epochē, and More
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Background
1.2. Overview of the Present Work
2. Zeno’s Paradox: Movement and Mathematics
2.1. The Alleged Problem and Its Solution
2.2. Philosophy Untouched?
This infinite summation cannot be carried out directly in the physical world simply because it requires an infinite number of 1/2′s to be actually summed, which is impossible. We know that the Z Summation converges to 1 not because we do the actual summing, but because in our minds, we make the appropriate inferential leap from a finite amount of summing […] to the full infinite summation […] But Achilles, in running from A to B can’t “mentally derive” or “inferentially leap” to B […] Achilles is not doing math, he’s running (or appears to be). […] you are further assuming that Achilles is moving. This latter assumption, and so the former one, beg the question against me.
2.3. The Relevance of Science
3. Skepticism’: Beliefs and Psychology
3.1. The (Alleged) Problem and Its (Alleged) Solution
- If we know that O, then we know that ~T.
- But we do not know that ~T.
- So we do not know that O.
3.2. Philosophy Untouched?
- People evaluate inferential beliefs more harshly than perceptual beliefs.
- People evaluate an inferential belief more harshly when its content is negative.
- If (1) and (2), then the source–content bias exists.
- Therefore, the source–content bias exists.
- The second premise of the skeptical argument is a harsh evaluation of a negative inferential belief.
- If the source–content bias exists and the second premise of the skeptical argument is a harsh evaluation of a negative inferential belief, then the appeal and force of the skeptical argument are a byproduct of our psychology.
- Hence, the appeal and force of the skeptical argument is merely a byproduct of our psychology.
- If the appeal and force of the skeptical argument are a byproduct of our psychology, then skepticism only results from our psychology.
- Therefore, skepticism only results from our psychology.
- Therefore, skepticism (‘the view that we know nothing’: p. 490) is not tenable.
3.3. The Relevance of Science
4. Notes on Artificial Intelligence and on Echolocation
4.1. A Note on the Frame Problem
We can’t do AI without solving the Frame Problem. But we don’t know how to solve the Frame Problem. That in a nutshell, is why, though science works, AI doesn’t.(Jerry Fodor in 1987, approvingly quoted by Dietrich).
4.2. A Note on Nagel’s Bat
5. Discussion and Conclusions
5.1. Philosophy and Science
5.2. Philosophy and Wisdom
5.3. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
Appendix A
1 | Importantly, for Quine, philosophy is continuous with science [2] (p. 232). For example, ‘Descartes’ dualism between mind and body is called metaphysics, but it could as well be reckoned as science, however false’ (Quine, [3], p. 252). It is also important to keep in mind that Quine uses “science” in a wide sense, not restricted to the natural sciences. |
2 | To understand the scare quotes, see, for example, below or Eichorn [10]. |
3 | Please note: I am not knowledgeable enough to know whether this reasoning really holds up, but it, at the very least, does make yet another case for the relevance of science to the philosophical question. A reviewer pointed out that Zeno had another argument for the discrete case. This may or may not help improve Zeno’s overall argument, but that still would mean that science is relevant in showing that the philosophical argument has to be amended (whether the result is a sound argument or not), which is what I am arguing for. |
4 | Turri does not explain to whom this ‘we’ refers. |
5 | It is not, at least in the sense relevant to Dietrich’s argument, see further down in the main text. |
6 | The confusion seems to arise from Turri talking about the negative inferential belief ‘~T’ (which is derived from O), whereas Dietrich focuses on the negative inferential belief ‘~(I can be certain that ~T)’ (which is derived from experiential invariance). Assuming one finds these two inferences equipollent, one finds oneself in a state of epoche, which—pace Dietrich, see main text—is not a form of ‘skepticism’ as understood by Turri and Dietrich. |
7 | Sextus does say that the skeptikos is adoxastos (without doxa), but doxa here means ‘a definite position about how things are, a position that is not adequately supported’ [13]. |
8 | |
9 | I want to emphasize that I am less certain in this case than I am in the previous two since the frame problem is further away from my core competencies. On the other hand, today’s successes of artificial intelligence should give us pause for thought about claims like ‘AI had failed thus far and was going to continue to fail’. Also, in Dietrich’s argument, there is a not exactly undisputed assumption that reasoning rests on mental representations (compare [20] (p. 172, footnote 22). Finally, one would expect a remark on how his argument in this section, which relies crucially on change, squares with Dietrich’s apparent approval of the Parmenidian view that change is an illusion (the ‘perversity of the Way of Opinion’ according to Dietrich, p. 484); and similarly with Sextus’ epoche regarding the existence of motion (PH III.81). |
10 | I believe there are many, but this has to be left for another occasion. |
11 | June 2024. |
12 | |
13 | Quine also observed (and I wholeheartedly agree) that science is refined common sense rather than a substitute for it: ‘science is not a substitute for common sense, but an extension of it. The quest for knowledge is properly an effort to broaden and deepen the knowledge which the man in the street already enjoys, in moderation, in relation to the commonplace things around him’ [29] (p. 229). This also applies to philosophy: ‘He holds that all of our attempts at knowledge are subject to those standards of evidence and justification which are most explicitly displayed, and most successfully implemented, in the natural sciences. This applies to philosophy as well as to other branches of knowledge’ [4]. |
14 | This also shows that there is no incompatibility between the views of Hawking and Quine. If all philosophy was dead, and science is continuous with philosophy, then one may have asked whether this does not imply that science is dead, too—a conclusion that Hawking certainly would not have endorsed. |
15 | I will not discuss the reverse way of arguing for a separation of science and philosophy, namely claiming that science can proceed entirely separate from philosophy. See, for example, De Haro [31]. |
16 | Even though when Plato had Socrates argue for the importance of philosophy in the Theaetetus, he did not present knowledge as a goal in itself but as a means to achieve divine eudaimonia [175e–176e], similarly Aristotle in book X of the Nicomachean Ethics. |
17 | Possibly inspired by ancient philosophy, depending on whether Husserl developed his method of epoche independently or not. |
18 | See my paper [7] for the discussion of an example involving the illicit application of so-called intuitions about Nagel’s bat and McTaggart’s oyster to positive psychology. |
19 | While the paper did not report power, the reported data do allow an approximate calculation: N = 604 over eight conditions (p. 312) means about N = 76 per condition and response rates of about 0.17 and 0.26 (Figure 1 on p. 315) together with the standard threshold of p = 0.05 imply power of 0.316 (one-sided) or 0.212 (two-sided), using the online calculator http://hedwig.mgh.harvard.edu/sample_size/fisher/js/fisher.html accessed on 9 October 2020. |
References
- Hawking, S.; Mlodinow, L. The Grand Design: New Answers to the Ultimate Questions of Life; Bantam Books: London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Hylton, P. Quine; Routledge: London, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Quine, W. Naturalism; or, living within one’s means. Dialectica 1995, 49, 251–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hylton, P.; Kemp, G. Willard Van Orman Quine. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition); Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A. What can philosophy really do? Philos. Mag. 2015, 71, 17–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Alexandrova, A. A Philosophy for the Science of Well-Being; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Mattes, J. Positive Psychology and Philosophy-as-Usual: An Unhappy Match? Philosophies 2022, 7, 52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dietrich, E. When Science Confronts Philosophy: Three Case Studies. Axiomathes 2020, 30, 479–500. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Turri, J. Skeptical Appeal: The Source-Content Bias. Cogn. Sci. 2015, 39, 307–324. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Eichorn, R.E. How (Not) To Read Sextus Empiricus. Anc. Philos. 2014, 34, 121–149. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mattes, J. ACTing as a Pyrrhonist. Int. J. Study Skept. 2022, 12, 101–125. [Google Scholar]
- Fraser, C. Supplement to “School of Names”: Miscellaneous Paradoxes. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 ed.); Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Bett, R. How to Keep an Open Mind: An Ancient Guide to Thinking Like a Skeptic; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Bowden, C. Inquiry, value, and some peculiarities of the Pyrrhonist’s psychology. Synthese 2024, 203, 175. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bueno, O. Skepticism, naturalism, Pyrrhonism. Philos. Issues 2022, 32, 148–163. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Porchat, O. On what appears. Sképsis 2015, 12, 1–32. [Google Scholar]
- Porchat, O. Sobre o que aparece. Discurso 1992, 19, 83–122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moss, J.; Schwab, W. The birth of belief. J. Hist. Philos. 2019, 57, 1–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fields, C. How humans solve the frame problem. J. Exp. Theor. Artif. Intell. 2013, 25, 441–456. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dennett, D. The Intentional Stance; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Allen, C.; Trestman, M. Animal Consciousness. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition); Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, T. What Is It Like to Be a Bat? Philos. Rev. 1974, 83, 435–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stroffregen, T.A.; Pittenger, J.B. Human Echolocation as a Basic Form of Perception and Action. Ecol. Psychol. 1995, 7, 181–216. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schenkman, B.N.; Gidla, V.K. Detection, thresholds of human echolocation in static situations for distance, pitch, loudness and sharpness. Appl. Acoust. 2020, 163, 107214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thaler, L.; De Vos, H.P.J.C.; Kish, D.; Antoniou, M.; Baker, C.J.; Hornikx, M.C.J. Human Click-Based Echolocation of Distance: Superfine Acuity and Dynamic Clicking Behaviour. J. Assoc. Res. Otolaryngol. 2019, 20, 499–510. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Allen-Hermanson, S. Introspection, Anton’s Syndrome, and Human Echolocation. Pac. Philos. Q. 2015, 98, 171–192. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peels, R. The Empirical Case Against Introspection. Philos. Stud. 2016, 173, 2461–2485. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schwitzgebel, E. How Well Do We Know Our Own Conscious Experience? The Case of Human Echolocation. Philos. Top. 2000, 28, 235–246. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Quine, W. The scope and language of science. In The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1997; pp. 228–245. [Google Scholar]
- Dennett, D. From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds; Penguin Books: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- De Haro, S. Science and Philosophy: A Love–Hate Relationship. Found. Sci. 2020, 25, 297–314. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ambury, J.M.; Irani, T.; Wallace, K. Introduction. Special Issue: Philosophy as a Way of Life. Metaphilosophy 2020, 51, 161–165. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sharpe, M.; Ure, M. Philosophy as a Way of Life: History, Dimensions, Directions; Bloomsbury Publishing: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, P. What Is Ancient Philosophy? Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Faustino, M. Philosophy as a way of life today. Metaphilosophy 2020, 51, 357–374. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robertson, D. The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioural Therapy (CBT): Stoic Philosophy as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy; Karnac: London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Kabat-Zinn, J. Some reflections on the origins of MBSR, skillful means, and the trouble with maps. Contemp. Buddhism 2011, 12, 281–306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kabat-Zinn, J. Full Catastrophe Living: How to Cope with Stress, Pain and Illness Using Mindfulness Meditation (Revised and Updated Edition); Piatkus: London, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Ivtzan, I. (Ed.) Handbook of Mindfulness-Based Programmes: Mindfulness Interventions from Education to Health and Therapy; Routledge: London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Cooper, M. Existential Therapies; Sage Publications: London, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Van Deurzen, E.; Craig, E.; Laengle, A.; Schneider, K.J.; Tantam, D.; du Plock, S. (Eds.) The Wiley World Handbook of Existential Therapy; Wiley Blackwell: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Noyon, A.; Heidenreich, T. Existenzielle Perspektiven in Psychotherapie und Beratung; Beltz: Weinheim, Germany, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Machery, E. Philosophy within Its Proper Bounds; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Mates, B. The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s “Outlines of Pyrrhonism”; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Gigerenzer, G. Mindless statistics. J. Socio-Econ. 2004, 33, 587–606. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wasserstein, R.L.; Lazar, N.A. The ASA Statement on p-Values: Context, Process, and Purpose. Am. Stat. 2016, 70, 129–133. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Mattes, J. Philosophy Untouched by Science? Zeno’s Runner, Sextus’ Epochē, and More. Philosophies 2024, 9, 115. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9040115
Mattes J. Philosophy Untouched by Science? Zeno’s Runner, Sextus’ Epochē, and More. Philosophies. 2024; 9(4):115. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9040115
Chicago/Turabian StyleMattes, Josef. 2024. "Philosophy Untouched by Science? Zeno’s Runner, Sextus’ Epochē, and More" Philosophies 9, no. 4: 115. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9040115
APA StyleMattes, J. (2024). Philosophy Untouched by Science? Zeno’s Runner, Sextus’ Epochē, and More. Philosophies, 9(4), 115. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9040115