Sign in to use this feature.

Years

Between: -

Subjects

remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline

Journals

Article Types

Countries / Regions

Search Results (37)

Search Parameters:
Keywords = quantum mechanics of unitary systems

Order results
Result details
Results per page
Select all
Export citation of selected articles as:
14 pages, 1641 KiB  
Article
Measurement-Induced Dynamical Quantum Thermalization
by Marvin Lenk, Sayak Biswas, Anna Posazhennikova and Johann Kroha
Entropy 2025, 27(6), 636; https://doi.org/10.3390/e27060636 - 14 Jun 2025
Viewed by 430
Abstract
One of the fundamental problems of quantum statistical physics is how an ideally isolated quantum system can ever reach thermal equilibrium behavior despite the unitary time evolution of quantum-mechanical systems. Here, we study, via explicit time evolution for the generic model system of [...] Read more.
One of the fundamental problems of quantum statistical physics is how an ideally isolated quantum system can ever reach thermal equilibrium behavior despite the unitary time evolution of quantum-mechanical systems. Here, we study, via explicit time evolution for the generic model system of an interacting, trapped Bose gas with discrete single-particle levels, how the measurement of one or more observables subdivides the system into observed and non-observed Hilbert subspaces and the tracing over the non-measured quantum numbers defines an effective, thermodynamic bath, induces the entanglement of the observed Hilbert subspace with the bath, and leads to a bi-exponential approach of the entanglement entropy and of the measured observables to thermal equilibrium behavior as a function of time. We find this to be more generally fulfilled than in the scenario of the eigenstate thermalization hypothesis (ETH), namely for both local particle occupation numbers and non-local density correlation functions, and independent of the specific initial quantum state of the time evolution. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Non-Equilibrium Dynamics in Ultra-Cold Quantum Gases)
Show Figures

Figure 1

68 pages, 5470 KiB  
Article
Does Quantum Mechanics Breed Larger, More Intricate Quantum Theories? The Case for Experience-Centric Quantum Theory and the Interactome of Quantum Theories
by Alireza Tavanfar, Sahar Alipour and Ali T. Rezakhani
Universe 2025, 11(5), 162; https://doi.org/10.3390/universe11050162 - 16 May 2025
Viewed by 619
Abstract
We pose and address the radical question of whether quantum mechanics, known for its firm internal structure and enormous empirical success, carries in itself the genomes of larger quantum theories that have higher internal intricacy and phenomenological versatility. In other words, we consider, [...] Read more.
We pose and address the radical question of whether quantum mechanics, known for its firm internal structure and enormous empirical success, carries in itself the genomes of larger quantum theories that have higher internal intricacy and phenomenological versatility. In other words, we consider, at the basic level of closed quantum systems and regardless of interpretational aspects, whether standard quantum theory (SQT) harbors quantum theories with context-based deformed principles or structures, having definite predictive power within much broader scopes. We answer this question in the affirmative following complementary evidence and reasoning arising from quantum-computation-based quantum simulation and fundamental, general, and abstract rationales within the frameworks of information theory, fundamental or functional emergence, and participatory agency. In this light, as we show, one is led to the recently proposed experience-centric quantum theory (ECQT), which is a larger and richer theory of quantum behaviors with drastically generalized quantum dynamics. ECQT allows the quantum information of the closed quantum system’s developed state history to continually contribute to defining and updating the many-body interactions, the Hamiltonians, and even the internal elements and “particles” of the total system. Hence, the unitary evolutions are continually impacted and become guidable by the agent system’s experience. The intrinsic interplay of unitarity and non-Markovianity in ECQT brings about a host of diverse behavioral phases, which concurrently infuse closed and open quantum system characteristics, and it even surpasses the theory of open systems in SQT. From a broader perspective, a focus of our investigation is the existence of the quantum interactome—the interactive landscape of all coexisting, independent, context-based quantum theories that emerge from inferential participatory agencies—and its predictive phenomenological utility. Full article
(This article belongs to the Section Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Gravity)
Show Figures

Figure 1

12 pages, 256 KiB  
Article
Mutual Compatibility/Incompatibility of Quasi-Hermitian Quantum Observables
by Miloslav Znojil
Symmetry 2025, 17(5), 708; https://doi.org/10.3390/sym17050708 - 5 May 2025
Viewed by 362
Abstract
In the framework of quasi-Hermitian quantum mechanics, the eligible operators of observables may be non-Hermitian, AjAj, j=1,2,,K. In principle, the standard probabilistic interpretation of the theory can be [...] Read more.
In the framework of quasi-Hermitian quantum mechanics, the eligible operators of observables may be non-Hermitian, AjAj, j=1,2,,K. In principle, the standard probabilistic interpretation of the theory can be re-established via a reconstruction of physical inner-product metric ΘI, guaranteeing the quasi-Hermiticity AjΘ=ΘAj. The task is easy at K=1 because there are many eligible metrics Θ=Θ(A1). In our paper, the next case with K=2 is analyzed. The criteria of the existence of a shared metric, Θ=Θ(A1,A2), are presented and discussed. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Gravity and Cosmology: Exploring the Astroparticle Interface)
24 pages, 1419 KiB  
Article
Measurement-Induced Symmetry Restoration and Quantum Mpemba Effect
by Giuseppe Di Giulio, Xhek Turkeshi and Sara Murciano
Entropy 2025, 27(4), 407; https://doi.org/10.3390/e27040407 - 10 Apr 2025
Cited by 3 | Viewed by 696
Abstract
Monitoring a quantum system can profoundly alter its dynamical properties, leading to non-trivial emergent phenomena. In this work, we demonstrate that dynamical measurements strongly influence the evolution of symmetry in many-body quantum systems. Specifically, we demonstrate that monitored systems governed by non-Hermitian dynamics [...] Read more.
Monitoring a quantum system can profoundly alter its dynamical properties, leading to non-trivial emergent phenomena. In this work, we demonstrate that dynamical measurements strongly influence the evolution of symmetry in many-body quantum systems. Specifically, we demonstrate that monitored systems governed by non-Hermitian dynamics exhibit a quantum Mpemba effect, where systems with stronger initial asymmetry relax faster to a symmetric state. Crucially, this phenomenon is purely measurement-induced: in the absence of measurements, we find states where the corresponding unitary evolution does not display any Mpemba effect. Furthermore, we uncover a novel measurement-induced symmetry restoration mechanism: below a critical measurement rate, the symmetry remains broken, but beyond a threshold, it is fully restored in the thermodynamic limit—along with the emergence of the quantum Mpemba effect. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Entanglement Entropy in Quantum Field Theory)
Show Figures

Figure 1

25 pages, 378 KiB  
Article
The Intrinsic Exceptional Point: A Challenge in Quantum Theory
by Miloslav Znojil
Foundations 2025, 5(1), 8; https://doi.org/10.3390/foundations5010008 - 1 Mar 2025
Viewed by 970
Abstract
In spite of its unbroken PT symmetry, the popular imaginary cubic oscillator Hamiltonian H(IC)=p2+ix3 does not satisfy all of the necessary postulates of quantum mechanics. This failure is due to the “intrinsic [...] Read more.
In spite of its unbroken PT symmetry, the popular imaginary cubic oscillator Hamiltonian H(IC)=p2+ix3 does not satisfy all of the necessary postulates of quantum mechanics. This failure is due to the “intrinsic exceptional point” (IEP) features of H(IC) and, in particular, to the phenomenon of a high-energy asymptotic parallelization of its bound-state-mimicking eigenvectors. In this paper, it is argued that the operator H(IC) (and the like) can only be interpreted as a manifestly unphysical, singular IEP limit of a hypothetical one-parametric family of certain standard quantum Hamiltonians. For explanation, ample use is made of perturbation theory and of multiple analogies between IEPs and conventional Kato’s exceptional points. Full article
(This article belongs to the Section Physical Sciences)
19 pages, 3781 KiB  
Article
Constructing Dynamical Symmetries for Quantum Computing: Applications to Coherent Dynamics in Coupled Quantum Dots
by James R. Hamilton, Raphael D. Levine and Francoise Remacle
Nanomaterials 2024, 14(24), 2056; https://doi.org/10.3390/nano14242056 - 23 Dec 2024
Cited by 2 | Viewed by 860
Abstract
Dynamical symmetries, time-dependent operators that almost commute with the Hamiltonian, extend the role of ordinary symmetries. Motivated by progress in quantum technologies, we illustrate a practical algebraic approach to computing such time-dependent operators. Explicitly we expand them as a linear combination of time-independent [...] Read more.
Dynamical symmetries, time-dependent operators that almost commute with the Hamiltonian, extend the role of ordinary symmetries. Motivated by progress in quantum technologies, we illustrate a practical algebraic approach to computing such time-dependent operators. Explicitly we expand them as a linear combination of time-independent operators with time-dependent coefficients. There are possible applications to the dynamics of systems of coupled coherent two-state systems, such as qubits, pumped by optical excitation and other addressing inputs. Thereby, the interaction of the system with the excitation is bilinear in the coherence between the two states and in the strength of the time-dependent excitation. The total Hamiltonian is a sum of such bilinear terms and of terms linear in the populations. The terms in the Hamiltonian form a basis for Lie algebra, which can be represented as coupled individual two-state systems, each using the population and the coherence between two states. Using the factorization approach of Wei and Norman, we construct a unitary quantum mechanical evolution operator that is a factored contribution of individual two-state systems. By that one can accurately propagate both the wave function and the density matrix with special relevance to quantum computing based on qubit architecture. Explicit examples are derived for the electronic dynamics in coupled semi-conducting nanoparticles that can be used as hardware for quantum technologies. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Computing and Nanomaterial Simulations)
Show Figures

Figure 1

21 pages, 367 KiB  
Article
Features, Paradoxes and Amendments of Perturbative Non-Hermitian Quantum Mechanics
by Miloslav Znojil
Symmetry 2024, 16(5), 629; https://doi.org/10.3390/sym16050629 - 19 May 2024
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 1283
Abstract
Quantum mechanics of unitary systems is considered in quasi-Hermitian representation and in the dynamical regime in which one has to take into account the ubiquitous presence of perturbations, random or specific. In this paper, it is shown that multiple technical obstacles encountered in [...] Read more.
Quantum mechanics of unitary systems is considered in quasi-Hermitian representation and in the dynamical regime in which one has to take into account the ubiquitous presence of perturbations, random or specific. In this paper, it is shown that multiple technical obstacles encountered in such a context can be circumvented via just a mild amendment of the so-called Rayleigh–Schrödinger perturbation–expansion approach. In particular, the quasi-Hermitian formalism characterized by an enhancement of flexibility is shown to remain mathematically tractable while, on the phenomenological side, opening several new model-building horizons. It is emphasized that they include, i.a., the study of generic random perturbations and/or of multiple specific non-Hermitian toy models. In parallel, several paradoxes and open questions are shown to survive. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Mechanics: Concepts, Symmetries, and Recent Developments)
22 pages, 375 KiB  
Article
Anisotropy and Asymptotic Degeneracy of the Physical-Hilbert-Space Inner-Product Metrics in an Exactly Solvable Unitary Quantum Model
by Miloslav Znojil
Symmetry 2024, 16(3), 353; https://doi.org/10.3390/sym16030353 - 14 Mar 2024
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 1249
Abstract
A unitary-evolution process leading to an ultimate collapse and to a complete loss of observability alias quantum phase transition is studied. A specific solvable Nstate model is considered, characterized by a non-stationary non-Hermitian Hamiltonian. Our analysis uses quantum mechanics formulated in [...] Read more.
A unitary-evolution process leading to an ultimate collapse and to a complete loss of observability alias quantum phase transition is studied. A specific solvable Nstate model is considered, characterized by a non-stationary non-Hermitian Hamiltonian. Our analysis uses quantum mechanics formulated in Schrödinger picture in which, in principle, only the knowledge of a complete set of observables (i.e., operators Λj) enables one to guarantee the uniqueness of the related physical Hilbert space (i.e., of its inner-product metric Θ). Nevertheless, for the sake of simplicity, we only assume the knowledge of just a single input observable (viz., of the energy-representing Hamiltonian HΛ1). Then, out of all of the eligible and Hamiltonian-dependent “Hermitizing” inner-product metrics Θ=Θ(H), we pick up just the simplest possible candidate. Naturally, this slightly restricts the scope of the theory, but in our present model, such a restriction is more than compensated for by the possibility of an alternative, phenomenologically better motivated constraint by which the time-dependence of the metric is required to be smooth. This opens a new model-building freedom which, in fact, enables us to force the system to reach the collapse, i.e., a genuine quantum catastrophe as a result of the mere conventional, strictly unitary evolution. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue The Benefits That Physics Derives from the Concept of Symmetry)
Show Figures

Figure 1

33 pages, 4382 KiB  
Article
Weak versus Deterministic Macroscopic Realism, and Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen’s Elements of Reality
by Jesse Fulton, Manushan Thenabadu, Run Yan Teh and Margaret D. Reid
Entropy 2024, 26(1), 11; https://doi.org/10.3390/e26010011 - 21 Dec 2023
Cited by 9 | Viewed by 2280
Abstract
The violation of a Leggett–Garg inequality confirms the incompatibility between quantum mechanics and the combined premises (called macro-realism) of macroscopic realism (MR) and noninvasive measurability (NIM). Arguments can be given that the incompatibility arises because MR fails for systems in a superposition of [...] Read more.
The violation of a Leggett–Garg inequality confirms the incompatibility between quantum mechanics and the combined premises (called macro-realism) of macroscopic realism (MR) and noninvasive measurability (NIM). Arguments can be given that the incompatibility arises because MR fails for systems in a superposition of macroscopically distinct states—or else, that NIM fails. In this paper, we consider a strong negation of macro-realism, involving superpositions of coherent states, where the NIM premise is replaced by Bell’s locality premise. We follow recent work and propose the validity of a subset of Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) and Leggett–Garg premises, referred to as weak macroscopic realism (wMR). In finding consistency with wMR, we identify that the Leggett–Garg inequalities are violated because of failure of both MR and NIM, but also that both are valid in a weaker (less restrictive) sense. Weak MR is distinguished from deterministic macroscopic realism (dMR) by recognizing that a measurement involves a reversible unitary interaction that establishes the measurement setting. Weak MR posits that a predetermined value for the outcome of a measurement can be attributed to the system after the interaction, when the measurement setting is experimentally specified. An extended definition of wMR considers the “element of reality” defined by EPR for system A, where one can predict with certainty the outcome of a measurement on A by performing a measurement on system B. Weak MR posits that this element of reality exists once the unitary interaction determining the measurement setting at B has occurred. We demonstrate compatibility of systems violating Leggett–Garg inequalities with wMR but point out that dMR has been shown to be falsifiable. Other tests of wMR are proposed, the predictions of wMR agreeing with quantum mechanics. Finally, we compare wMR with macro-realism models discussed elsewhere. An argument in favour of wMR is presented: wMR resolves a potential contradiction pointed out by Leggett and Garg between failure of macro-realism and assumptions intrinsic to quantum measurement theory. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Correlations, Contextuality, and Quantum Nonlocality)
Show Figures

Figure 1

36 pages, 2377 KiB  
Article
A Macroscopic Quantum Three-Box Paradox: Finding Consistency with Weak Macroscopic Realism
by Channa Hatharasinghe, Manushan Thenabadu, Peter D. Drummond and Margaret D. Reid
Entropy 2023, 25(12), 1620; https://doi.org/10.3390/e25121620 - 4 Dec 2023
Cited by 5 | Viewed by 2197
Abstract
The quantum three-box paradox considers a ball prepared in a superposition of being in any one of three boxes. Bob makes measurements by opening either box 1 or box 2. After performing some unitary operations (shuffling), Alice can infer with certainty that the [...] Read more.
The quantum three-box paradox considers a ball prepared in a superposition of being in any one of three boxes. Bob makes measurements by opening either box 1 or box 2. After performing some unitary operations (shuffling), Alice can infer with certainty that the ball was detected by Bob, regardless of which box he opened, if she detects the ball after opening box 3. The paradox is that the ball would have been found with certainty by Bob in either box if that box had been opened. Resolutions of the paradox include that Bob’s measurement cannot be made non-invasively or else that realism cannot be assumed at the quantum level. Here, we strengthen the case for the former argument by constructing macroscopic versions of the paradox. Macroscopic realism implies that the ball is in one of the boxes prior to Bob or Alice opening any boxes. We demonstrate the consistency of the paradox with macroscopic realism, if carefully defined (as weak macroscopic realism, wMR) to apply to the system at the times prior to Alice or Bob opening any boxes but after the unitary operations associated with preparation or shuffling. By solving for the dynamics of the unitary operations and comparing with mixed states, we demonstrate agreement between the predictions of wMR and quantum mechanics: the paradox only manifests if Alice’s shuffling combines both local operations (on box 3) and nonlocal operations, on the other boxes. Following previous work, the macroscopic paradox is shown to correspond to a violation of a Leggett–Garg inequality, which implies failure of non-invasive measurability if wMR holds. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Correlations, Contextuality, and Quantum Nonlocality)
Show Figures

Figure 1

31 pages, 13508 KiB  
Article
Quantum Time and Quantum Evolution
by Andrzej Góźdź, Marek Góźdź and Aleksandra Pȩdrak
Universe 2023, 9(6), 256; https://doi.org/10.3390/universe9060256 - 26 May 2023
Cited by 9 | Viewed by 2210
Abstract
The problem of quantum time and evolution of quantum systems, where time is not a parameter, is considered. In our model, following some earlier works, time is represented by a quantum operator. In this paper, similarly to the position operators in the Schrödinger [...] Read more.
The problem of quantum time and evolution of quantum systems, where time is not a parameter, is considered. In our model, following some earlier works, time is represented by a quantum operator. In this paper, similarly to the position operators in the Schrödinger representation of quantum mechanics, this operator is a multiplication-type operator. It can be also represented by an appropriate positive operator-valued measure (POVM) which together with the 3D position operators/measures provide a quantum observable giving a position in the quantum spacetime. The quantum evolution itself is a stochastic process based on Lüder’s projection postulate. In fact, it is a generalization of the unitary evolution. This allows to treat time and generally the spacetime position as a quantum observable, in a consistent and observer-independent way. Full article
(This article belongs to the Section Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Gravity)
Show Figures

Figure 1

8 pages, 276 KiB  
Article
The Open Systems View and the Everett Interpretation
by Michael E. Cuffaro and Stephan Hartmann
Quantum Rep. 2023, 5(2), 418-425; https://doi.org/10.3390/quantum5020027 - 28 Apr 2023
Cited by 6 | Viewed by 2999
Abstract
It is argued that those who defend the Everett, or ‘many-worlds’, interpretation of quantum mechanics should embrace what we call the general quantum theory of open systems (GT) as the proper framework in which to conduct foundational and philosophical investigations in quantum physics. [...] Read more.
It is argued that those who defend the Everett, or ‘many-worlds’, interpretation of quantum mechanics should embrace what we call the general quantum theory of open systems (GT) as the proper framework in which to conduct foundational and philosophical investigations in quantum physics. GT is a wider dynamical framework than its alternative, standard quantum theory (ST). This is true even though GT makes no modifications to the quantum formalism. GT rather takes a different view, what we call the open systems view, of the formalism; i.e., in GT, the dynamics of systems whose physical states are fundamentally represented by density operators are represented as fundamentally open as specified by an in general non-unitary dynamical map. This includes, in principle, the dynamics of the universe as a whole. We argue that the more general dynamics describable in GT can be physically motivated, that there is as much prima facie empirical support for GT as there is for ST, and that GT could be fully in the spirit of the Everett interpretation—that there might, in short, be little reason for an Everettian not to embrace the more general theoretical landscape that GT allows one to explore. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics)
16 pages, 335 KiB  
Article
Non-Stationary Non-Hermitian “Wrong-Sign” Quantum Oscillators and Their Meaningful Physical Interpretation
by Miloslav Znojil
Entropy 2023, 25(4), 692; https://doi.org/10.3390/e25040692 - 19 Apr 2023
Cited by 3 | Viewed by 1730
Abstract
In the framework of quantum mechanics using quasi-Hermitian operators the standard unitary evolution of a non-stationary but still closed quantum system is only properly described in the non-Hermitian interaction picture (NIP). In this formulation of the theory both the states and the observables [...] Read more.
In the framework of quantum mechanics using quasi-Hermitian operators the standard unitary evolution of a non-stationary but still closed quantum system is only properly described in the non-Hermitian interaction picture (NIP). In this formulation of the theory both the states and the observables vary with time. A few aspects of implementation of this picture are illustrated via the “wrong-sign” quartic oscillators. It is shown that in contrast to the widespread belief, both of the related Schrödinger-equation generators G(t) and the Heisenberg-equation generators Σ(t) are just auxiliary concepts. Their spectra are phenomenologically irrelevant and, in general, complex. It is argued that only the sum H(t)=G(t)+Σ(t) of the latter operators retains the standard physical meaning of the instantaneous energy of the unitary quantum system in question. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Dynamics with Non-hermitian Hamiltonians II)
Show Figures

Figure 1

18 pages, 393 KiB  
Article
Composite Quantum Coriolis Forces
by Miloslav Znojil
Mathematics 2023, 11(6), 1375; https://doi.org/10.3390/math11061375 - 12 Mar 2023
Cited by 7 | Viewed by 1583
Abstract
In a consistent quantum theory known as “non-Hermitian interaction picture” (NIP), the standard quantum Coriolis operator Σ(t) emerges whenever the observables of a unitary system are given in their quasi-Hermitian and non-stationary rather than “usual” representations. With [...] Read more.
In a consistent quantum theory known as “non-Hermitian interaction picture” (NIP), the standard quantum Coriolis operator Σ(t) emerges whenever the observables of a unitary system are given in their quasi-Hermitian and non-stationary rather than “usual” representations. With Σ(t) needed, in NIP, in both the Schrödinger-like and Heisenberg-like dynamical evolution equations we show that another, amended and potentially simplified theory can be based on an auxiliary Nterm factorization of the Dyson’s Hermitization map Ω(t). The knowledge of this factorization is shown to lead to a multiplet of alternative eligible Coriolis forces Σn(t) with n=0,1,,N. The related formulae for the measurable predictions constitute a new formalism refered to as “factorization-based non-Hermitian interaction picture” (FNIP). The conventional NIP formalism (where N=1) becomes complemented by an (N1)-plet of its innovative “hybrid” alternatives. Some of the respective ad hoc adaptations of observables may result in an optimal representation of quantum dynamics. Full article
(This article belongs to the Section E4: Mathematical Physics)
9 pages, 366 KiB  
Proceeding Paper
Two Unitary Quantum Process Tomography Algorithms Robust to Systematic Errors
by François Verdeil and Yannick Deville
Phys. Sci. Forum 2022, 5(1), 29; https://doi.org/10.3390/psf2022005029 - 12 Dec 2022
Viewed by 1232
Abstract
Quantum process tomography (QPT) methods aim at identifying a given quantum process. QPT is a major quantum information processing tool, since it especially allows one to characterize the actual behavior of quantum gates, which are the building blocks of quantum computers. The present [...] Read more.
Quantum process tomography (QPT) methods aim at identifying a given quantum process. QPT is a major quantum information processing tool, since it especially allows one to characterize the actual behavior of quantum gates, which are the building blocks of quantum computers. The present paper focuses on the estimation of a unitary process. This class is of particular interest because quantum mechanics postulates that the evolution of any closed quantum system is described by a unitary transformation. Unitary processes have significantly fewer parameters than general quantum processes (22nqb vs. 24nqb22nqb real independent parameters for nqb qubits). By assuming that the process is unitary we develop two methods that scale better with the size of the system. In the present paper, we stay as close as possible to the standard setup of QPT: the operator has to prepare copies of different input states. The properties those states have to satisfy in order for our method to achieve QPT are very mild. Therefore, we choose to operate with copies of 2nqb initially unknown pure input states. In order to perform QPT without knowing the input states, we perform measurements on half the copies of each state, and let the other half be transformed by the system before measuring them (each copy is only measured once). This setup has the advantage of removing the issue of systematic (i.e., same on all the copies of a state) errors entirely because it does not require the process input to take predefined values. We develop a straightforward analytical solution that first estimates the states from the averaged measurements and then finds the unitary matrix (representing the process) coherent with those estimates by using our analytical solution to an extended version of Wahba’s problem. This estimate may then be used as an initial point for a fine tuning algorithm that maximizes the likelihood of the measurements. Simulation results show the effectiveness of the proposed methods. Full article
Show Figures

Figure 1

Back to TopTop