Durand of Saint-Pourçain’s Refutation of Concurrentism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Problem of Evil and Durand’s Refutation of Concurrentism on a Moral Basis
- (1)
- the act is defective because of the agent (not because of a material defect, as in Aquinas’ claudication example);
- (2)
- the agent has the power to avoid the act;
- (3)
- the act is not the consequence of some invincible ignorance.
3. Durand’s Refutation of Concurrentism on a Metaphysical Basis
3.1. Aquinas’ Concurrence Theory
3.1.1. The Instrumental Causality Paradigm
3.1.2. Application to God’s Causal Concurrence
- (a)
- Every change in the world results in the actualization of a form, be it a substantial form in the processes of generation, or an accidental form in other kinds of change. Since it is through forms that existence (esse), the act of being (actus essendi), is provided, the actualization of a form amounts to the actualization of an esse, whether substantial or accidental. A compound of either substantial form and matter, or accidental form and substance comes into existence.38
- (b)
- However, only God can give existence.
- (c)
- Therefore, creatures cannot be the sufficient causes of any of the natural processes, and God’s cooperation is always required as the immediate cause39 that gives existence to the effect of a given action, even if it is only to heat water, for example.
- The order among effects reflects the order among causes: a subordinate effect comes from a subordinate cause, and a principial effect comes from a principial cause (and vice versa, a subordinate cause engenders a subordinate effect, and a principial cause a principial effect).41
- But existence is an effect that presupposes no other, and, on the contrary, is presupposed by all the others, for any effect can only be an effect if it exists.
- Existence is therefore the very first effect in the order among conditions.
- Consequently, existence must be produced by the First Cause only.42
3.2. Durand’s Objections
3.2.1. Durand’s Objections to Aquinas
“A creature can be the cause of those beings that are produced through motion and generation, either in such a way that it exerts causality over an entire species, as the sun is cause in the generation of humans or lions, or in such a way that it exerts causality on only one individual of the same species, as a man generates a man, and fire generates fire. However, God is also the cause of these same beings, operating in them more in depth than the other causes, which operate through motion, because it is God who gives existence to things. The other causes only delimit that existence, so to speak (sunt quasi determinantes illud esse). [a] No thing’s existence entirely originates from a creature, since matter is from God alone. [b] Existence, however, is in all things deeper [magis intimum] than the characteristics by which existence is delimitated [determinatur] in them. Hence, mere existence remains even when these characteristics have been removed, as The Book of Causes says. Therefore, the Creator’s operation reaches out more into the depths of a thing [magis pertingit ad intima rei] than the operation of the secondary causes. And thus, the fact that something is caused by another creature, does not preclude that God operate as an immediate cause in all things (…)”.67
3.2.2. Durand’s Objections to Giles
3.2.3. Durand’s Objections to the Very Possibility of Concurrence
- (A)
- It cannot be the same for the two following reasons:
- (1)
- Assuming that a secondary cause is maintained in existence by God with its nature and powers, it can produce its effect without any additional intervention by God, for an action that does not exceed the power of a certain specific nature needs nothing else than that specific nature to be carried out; consequently, God’s action would be superfluous and assumed in vain.94 Durand can argue in this manner because he has previously refuted the explanation given by Aquinas and Giles, according to which God, in giving esse, acts on the same effect as the secondary causes, but does so at a deeper level, that of existence.95 Since being and living are only conceptually distinct and are in fact the same act, the thing that causes life can also cause existence; there is no need for God to act underhandedly to give the effect what the secondary cause cannot give. Durand has thus undermined the model of instrumental causality that Aquinas used to justify the need for divine assistance, and that is based on the idea that the primary cause makes the secondary cause do something that it cannot do on its own. This is why Durand can say that an action that corresponds to the capacities of a nature (such as the communication of life) does not require any additional cause. Consequently, a simultaneous action by God would be superfluous.
- (2)
- The general conditions for two or more agents to be involved in the same action do not hold when one of the agents is God and the other is a creature. This is because there are only three ways in which the same action can be performed by multiple agents.96
- It may happen that several agents each perfectly perform an action that is numerically the same, but, in this case, this action is produced directly by one, and mediately by the others. For example, the same action that is performed by a proximate cause is performed by a remote cause, but mediately, insofar as it gives the proximate cause its power and/or applies it. This is the case with God, but concurrentism requires in addition that he be a proximate cause too.97
- It may also happen that several agents are at the same time the direct causes of a single action, but, in this case, none is a perfect cause. For example, instead of a single and sufficient cause, two limited causes cooperate, like when two men pull a ship: each is an immediate but partial cause.98 This cannot be the case for God.
- Several agents can perform the same action numerically in such a way that they are each its immediate and complete cause if, and only if, there is a single power (virtus) numerically within these agents. For example, in the Trinity, the Holy Spirit proceeds from both the Father and the Son, each of whom is the Spirit’s immediate and complete cause because there is one and the same power of spiration in both of them. But the same power numerically cannot be in God and in creatures. Consequently, it is impossible for both God and a creature to be direct and complete causes of the same action.
- (B)
- Nor can they be different, Durand continues, opening up a new dilemma, for either one of these actions would produce the effect before the other, or it would not.
4. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See for instance Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Summa contra Gentiles [=ScG] lib. III, cap. 67: “Sicut autem Deus non solum dedit esse rebus cum primo esse incoeperunt, sed quandiu sunt, esse in eis causat, res in esse conservans, ut ostensum est, ita non solum cum primo res conditae sunt eis virtutes operativas dedit, sed semper eas in rebus causat. Unde, cessante influentia divina, omnis operatio cessaret. Omnis igitur rei operatio in ipsum reducitur sicut in causam”. |
2 | |
3 | Suárez (1866, Disp. XXII, sectio 1, § 6, p. 803a): “(…) Deum per se et immediate agere in omni actione creaturae, atque hunc influxum ejus simpliciter necessarium est, ut creatura aliquid efficiat (…) [p]robatur primo ex communi consensu Scholasticorum, qui ita sentiunt de hac veritate, et de Catholico dogmate (…)”. |
4 | He is however neither the only one nor the first one to do so: he was preceded by Peter of John Olivi (see Frost 2014). But due to historical circumstances, Olivi’s work was far less known than Durand’s. In the later Middle Ages, the Renaissance and the modern era, Durand was singled out as the typical representative of this minority position. |
5 | |
6 | See Malebranche (1976, XVe Éclaircissement, p. 243); Bayle (1731, pp. 489–90 and 493); Bernier (1685, p. 116) (in favor of Durand); Leibniz (2008, Ière Partie, § 27, p. 118). For a broader view of the relation between Leibniz and Durand (including the future contingents problem), see Piro (2009). |
7 | So far Durand’s view has been studied in some aspects, but not in its entirety as I will attempt here. See (Stufler 1935; Freddoso 1994; Flasch 2013, chap. 43; Toth 2020; Tuttle 2022). |
8 | See for instance Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.89.5: “Deus non solum dat rebus virtutes, sed etiam nulla res potest propria virtute agere nisi agat in virtute ipsius, ut supra ostensum est. Ergo homo non potest virtute voluntatis sibi data uti nisi inquantum agit in virtute Dei. Illud autem in cuius virtute agens agit, est causa non solum virtutis, sed etiam actus. (…) Deus igitur est causa nobis non solum voluntatis, sed etiam volendi”; Quaestiones Disputatae de Potentia Dei [=De pot.] q. 3, a. 7: “(…) ipse in quolibet operante immediate operetur, non exclusa operatione voluntatis et naturae”. |
9 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019) Scriptum super libros Sententiarum [=Sent.] l. II, dist. 37, q. 2, a. 2, c.: “(…) cum actio etiam peccati sit ens quoddam…secundum quod res in genere existentes entia sunt, eo quod et ipsae actiones in genere ordinantur, sequeretur, si actiones peccati a Deo non sunt, quod aliquod ens essentiam habens a Deo non esset; et ita Deus non esset universalis causa omnium entium, quod est contra perfectionem primi entis”; Summa theologiae [=STh] IaIIae p., q. 79, a. 2, c.: “(…) actus peccati et est ens, et est actus; et ex utroque habet quod sit a Deo. Omne enim ens, quocumque modo sit, oportet quod derivetur a primo ente; ut patet per Dionysium, V cap. de Div. Nom. Omnis autem actio causatur ab aliquo existente in actu, quia nihil agit nisi secundum quod est actu, omne autem ens actu reducitur in primum actum, scilicet Deum, sicut in causam, qui est per suam essentiam actus. Unde relinquitur quod Deus sit causa omnis actionis, inquantum est actio”. Cf. Albertus Magnus (1893, 35.1.7, p. 575). |
10 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. II.44.1.1.c.: “In actu autem peccati sunt duo, scilicet substantia actus, et deformitas vel defectus debitarum circumstantiarum. Unde oportet quod etiam in ipsa potentia peccandi duo attendantur: scilicet ipsa potentia, quae est principium actus; et haec est eadem quae est principium actus ordinati et inordinati: et haec a Deo est. Consideratur etiam in ea defectus quidam, secundum quem actum deficientem producere possit. (…) Sic ergo potentia peccandi, quantum ad id quod potentiae est, a Deo est; sed quantum ad defectum qui implicatur, non est a Deo”. |
11 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.71: “Ex his autem apparet quod divina providentia, qua res gubernat, non impedit quin corruptio et defectus et malum in rebus inveniatur. Divina enim gubernatio, qua Deus operatur in rebus, non excludit operationem causarum secundarum, sicut iam ostensum est. Contingit autem provenire defectum in effectu propter defectum causae secundae agentis, absque eo quod sit defectus in primo agente: sicut cum in effectu artificis habentis perfecte artem, contingit aliquis defectus propter instrumenti defectum; et sicut hominem cuius vis motiva est fortis, contingit claudicare, non propter defectum virtutis motivae, sed propter tibiae curvitatem. Contingit igitur in his quae aguntur et gubernantur a Deo, aliquem defectum et al.iquod malum inveniri, propter defectum agentium secundorum, licet in ipso Deo nullus sit defectus”; STh I-II.79.2.c.: “Defectus autem ille est ex causa creata, scilicet libero arbitrio, inquantum deficit ab ordine primi agentis, scilicet Dei. Unde defectus iste non reducitur in Deum sicut in causam, sed in liberum arbitrium, sicut defectus claudicationis reducitur in tibiam curvam sicut in causam, non autem in virtutem motivam, a qua tamen causatur quidquid est motionis in claudicatione. Et secundum hoc, Deus est causa actus peccati, non tamen est causa peccati, quia non est causa huius, quod actus sit cum defectu”. |
12 | Another way is to adopt a restricted version of concurrentism: human free will as a cause is an exception to the rule of God’s required co-action. John Duns Scotus seems to have maintained this view at the end of his career. See Frost (2009) and Wolter (1994). Henry of Ghent endorses it more explicitly (Henricus de Gandavo 1983, q. 5, pp. 120–21; 1987, q. 26, pp. 155–56). |
13 | |
14 | There are three different versions of Durand’s Commentary, conventionally labelled A, B, and C. The first version was probably written before 1308. Given that in it he was often criticizing Thomas Aquinas, Durand would have been barred by the Dominican order from getting a professorial chair in Paris and had to issue a new version, version B, probably written before 1312, in which he generally waters down his opposition to Aquinas. After he became a bishop in 1317 and was free from the Dominicans’ jurisdiction, he went back to working on his Commentary, which led to the third and final version, C, in which he often returns to his earlier positions (on Durand’s carreer and the history of his Sentences Commentary, see Speer et al. (2014, pp. 13–169). Despite the general trend of version B that I have pointed out, I will use here that version, which as far as q. 1 of book II, dist. 37 is concerned, is more complete and makes very clear the link with dist. 1, q. 4 (q. 5 in version C) of book II, where Durand refutes the arguments in favor of the concurrentist theory, as we’ll see below. In fact, in version B Durand has eliminated entirely II.1.4 (probably for the reason just given) but has moved to II.37.1 one of his objections against concurrentism (see Durandus de Sancto Porciano 2012, dist. 1, q. 4, § A12, p. 54, for the passage included in the rewrite of dist. 37; and Durandus de Sancto Porciano 2013, dist. 37, q. 1, § A6, p. 259, § B6, pp. 259–60, for the argument moved from II.4.1, and §§ A8–B8, p. 262, for another reference to II.1.4). |
15 | Leibniz (2008, I, § 27, pp. 118–19). Olivi’s rationale for his criticism of concurrentism is identical (Petrus Iohannis Olivi 1926, q. 116, pp. 333–47; see Frost 2014). Same reason for Bernier. |
16 | |
17 | Quoted by Sleigh (1996, p. 485). |
18 | Quoted by Sleigh, ibid. |
19 | In the 1680s Leibniz changed his mind about privation and tried to integrate it into his system as the original limitation of creatures, their constitutive negation, as Newlands (2014, pp. 290–92), shows. |
20 | |
21 | |
22 | |
23 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Quaestiones disputatae de potentia [=De pot.] q. 3, a. 7, c.: “Sed quia nulla res per se ipsam movet vel agit nisi sit movens non motum, tertio modo dicitur una res esse causa actionis alterius in quantum movet eam ad agendum; in quo non intelligitur collatio aut conservatio virtutis activae, sed applicatio virtutis ad actionem; sicut homo est causa incisionis cultelli ex hoc ipso quod applicat acumen cultelli ad incidendum movendo ipsum”. |
24 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG II.21.4: “Est ratio instrumenti quod sit movens motum”; STh III.63.5.ad2: “Ratio instrumenti consistit in hoc quod ab alio moveatur, non autem in hoc quod ipsum se moveat”; STh III.72.3.ad2: “Instrumentum movetur a principali agente ad effectum”. |
25 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh I-II.109.1.c.: “Videmus autem in corporalibus quod ad motum non solum requiritur ipsa forma quae est principium motus vel actionis; sed etiam requiritur motio primi moventis. Primum autem movens in ordine corporalium est corpus caeleste. Unde quantumcumque ignis habeat perfectum calorem, non alteraret nisi per motionem caelestis corporis. Manifestum est autem quod, sicut omnes motus corporales reducuntur in motum caelestis corporis sicut in primum movens corporale, ita omnes motus tam corporales quam spirituales reducuntur in primum movens simpliciter, quod est Deus. Et ideo quantumcumque natura aliqua corporalis vel spiritualis ponatur perfecta, non potest in suum actum procedere nisi moveatur a Deo. (…) Unaquaeque autem forma indita rebus creatis a Deo, habet efficaciam respectu alicuius actus determinati, in quem potest secundum suam proprietatem, ultra autem non potest nisi per aliquam formam superadditam, sicut aqua non potest calefacere nisi calefacta ab igne”. |
26 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Et quia natura inferiora agens non agit nisi mota eo quod huiusmodi corpora inferiora sunt alterantia alterata, caelum autem est alterans non alteratum et tamen non est movens nisi motum, et hoc non cessat quousque perveniatur ad Deum, sequitur de necessitate quod Deus sit causa actionis cuiuslibet rei naturalis ut movens et applicans virtutem ad agendum”. |
27 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.67.4: “Quicquid applicat virtutem activam ad agendum, dicitur esse causa illius actionis: artifex enim applicans virtutem rei naturalis ad aliquam actionem, dicitur esse causa illius actionis, sicut coquus decoctionis, quae est per ignem. Sed omnis applicatio virtutis ad operationem est principaliter et primo a Deo. Applicantur enim virtutes operativae ad proprias operationes per aliquem motum vel corporis, vel animae. Primum autem principium utriusque motus est Deus. Est enim primum movens omnino immobile, ut supra ostensum est”. |
28 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh I.115.5.c.: “(…) si sint multa agentia ordinate, semper secundum agens agit in virtute primi; nam primum agens movet secundum ad agendum. Et secundum hoc, omnia agunt in virtute ipsius Dei; et ita ipse est causa actionum omnium agentium”. |
29 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sententia libri Metaphysicae V.2: “Adjuvans dicitur causa, secundum quod operatur ad principalem effectum. In hoc tamen differt ab agente principali, quia principale agens agit ad finem proprium, adjuvans autem ad finem alienum; sicut, qui adjuvat regem in bello, operatur ad finem regis”. |
30 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.4.c: “(…) causa secunda duplicem actionem habere potest: unam ex propria natura, aliam ex virtutis prioris causae”; STh III.62.1.ad2: “Dicendum quod instrumentum habet duas actiones: unam instrumentalem secundum quam operatur non in virtute propria sed in virtute principalis agentis; aliam autem habet actionem propriam quae competit ei secundum propriam formam”. Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Quaestiones disputatae de veritate [=De Ver.] 27.4.ad2: “(…) sacramenta novae legis non sunt causa gratiae principalis, quasi per se agentia, sed causa instrumentalis. Et secundum modum aliorum instrumentorum habent duplicem actionem: unam quae excedit formam propriam, sed est ex virtute formae principalis agentis, scilicet Dei: quae est iustificare; et al.iam quam exercet secundum formam propriam, sicut abluere vel ungere (…)”. |
31 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh I.45.5.c.: “Contingit autem quod aliquid participet actionem propriam alicuius alterius, non virtute propria, sed instrumentaliter, inquantum agit in virtute alterius; sicut aer per virtutem ignis habet calefacere et ignire”; STh I-II.122.1.ad1: “Instrumentum non agit actionem agentis principalis propria virtute, sed virtute principalis agentis”; Sent. IV.1.1.1.4.ad1: “(…) sacramentum est causa et signum. Est quidem causa instrumentalis; et ideo virtus agentis principalis occulte in ipso operatur, sicut virtus artis vel artificis in serra”; Sent. IV.1.1.4.3.c.: “(…) instrumentum praedicto modo virtutem non accipit nisi secundum quod principali agenti continuatur, ut virtus ejus quodammodo in instrumentum transfundatur”. |
32 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. IV.1.1.4.1.c.: “(…) sciendum, quod actio instrumenti quandoque pertingit ad ultimam perfectionem, quam principale agens inducit, aliquando autem non. Semper tamen pertingit ad aliquid ultra id quod competit sibi secundum suam naturam, sive illud sit ultima forma, sive dispositio, alias non ageret ut instrumentum”. |
33 | See Aristotle, De anima II.4, 416b 28–29. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. IV.1.1.4.1.c.: “Instrumento autem competit duplex actio: una quam habet ex propria natura, alia quam habet prout est motum a primo agente; sicut calor ignis, qui est instrumentum virtutis nutritivae, ut dicitur in 2 de anima, ex natura propria habet dissolvere, et consumere, et hujusmodi effectus: sed inquantum est instrumentum animae vegetabilis, generat carnem”; De Pot. 3.8.ad13: “(…) forma accidentalis agit in virtute formae substantialis quasi instrumentum eius; sicut etiam in II de anima calor ignis dicitur esse instrumentum virtutis nutritivae; et ideo non est inconveniens, si actio formae accidentalis ad formam substantialem terminetur”. |
34 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. IV.1.1.4.1.c.: “(…) omne instrumentum agendo actionem naturalem, quae competit sibi inquantum est res quaedam, pertingit ad effectum qui competit sibi inquantum est instrumentum, sicut dolabrum dividendo suo acumine pertingit instrumentaliter ad formam scamni”; ScG II.21.7: “Omne agens instrumentale exequitur actionem principalis agentis per aliquam actionem propriam et connaturalem sibi: sicut calor naturalis generat carnem dissolvendo et digerendo, et serra operatur ad perfectionem scamni secando”; STh I.45.5.c.: “(…) securis, scindendo lignum, quod habet ex proprietate suae formae, producit scamni formam, quae est effectus proprius principalis agentis”; STh III.62.1.ad2: “(…) securi competit scindere ratione suae acuitatis, facere autem lectum inquantum est instrumentum artis. Non autem perficit actionem instrumentalem nisi exercendo actionem propriam; scindendo enim facit lectum”. |
35 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh I.45.5.c.: “causa secunda instrumentalis non participat actionem causae superioris, nisi inquantum per aliquid sibi proprium dispositive operatur ad effectum principalis agentis. Si igitur nihil ibi ageret secundum illud quod est sibi proprium, frustra adhiberetur ad agendum, nec oporteret esse determinata instrumenta determinatarum actionum”. |
36 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh III.19.1.ad2: “Actio instrumenti, in quantum est instrumentum, non est alia ab actione principalis agentis. Potest tamen habere aliam actionem prout est res aliqua”. Cf. STh I-II.14.3.ad4: “Agens principale et instrumentale sunt quasi una causa, cum unum agat per alterum”. |
37 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.66.3: “Quando aliqua agentia diversa sub uno agente ordinantur, necesse est quod effectus qui ab eis communiter fit, sit eorum secundum quod uniuntur in participando motum et virtutem illius agentis: non enim plura faciunt unum nisi inquantum unum sunt”; ScG III.70.5: “Sicut igitur non est inconveniens quod una actio producatur ex aliquo agente et eius virtute, ita non est inconveniens quod producatur idem effectus ab inferiori agente et Deo: ab utroque immediate, licet alio et al.io modo”. |
38 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. I.17.1.1: “Constat enim quod omne esse a forma aliqua inhaerente est, sicut esse album ab albedine, et esse substantiale a forma substantiali”. |
39 | See Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c: If we consider the subjects that perform the action, the proximate secondary cause is the cause closest to the effect. But if we consider the powers required by the action, the power of the superior cause, present in the particular agent, is more immediately the cause of the effect than the power of the inferior cause, because it gives existence, without which, obviously, the effect would be nothing (i.e., there would be no effect of the secondary cause at all)—more on this below. Cf. De Ver. 3.7.c.: “Sed quia nos ponimus Deum immediatam causam uniuscuiusque rei secundum quod in omnibus causis secundis operatur (...)”; ScG III.70.5: “Oportet ergo quod actio inferioris agentis non solum sit ab eo per virtutem propriam, sed per virtutem omnium superiorum agentium; agit enim in virtute omnium. Et sicut agens infimum invenitur immediatum activum, ita virtus primi agentis invenitur immediata ad producendum effectum; nam virtus infimi agentis non habet quod producat hunc effectum ex se, sed ex virtute proximi superioris; et virtus illius hoc habet ex virtute superioris; et sic virtus supremi agentis invenitur ex se productiva effectus, quasi causa immediata, sicut patet in principiis demonstrationum, quorum primum est immediatum”; De pot. 3.7.c.: “Et cum coniunxerimus his, quod Deus sit sua virtus, et quod sit intra rem quamlibet non sicut pars essentiae, sed sicut tenens rem in esse, sequetur quod ipse in quolibet operante immediate operetur, non exclusa operatione voluntatis et naturae”. |
40 | Liber de Causis, an anonymous, Arabic compilation of Proclus’ Elements of Theology. |
41 | |
42 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.4.c.: “(…) ordo effectuum est secundum ordinem causarum. Primus autem effectus est ipsum esse, quod omnibus aliis effectibus praesupponitur et ipsum non praesupponit aliquem alium effectum; et ideo oportet quod dare esse in quantum huiusmodi sit effectus primae causae solius secundum propriam virtutem (…)”. See also ScG III.66.6. For other demonstrations, see (Solère 2022, pp. 306–9). |
43 | Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Quanto enim aliqua causa est altior, tanto est communior et efficacior, et quanto est efficacior, tanto profundius ingreditur in effectum et de remotiori potentia ipsum reducit in actum”. |
44 | Liber de Causis (1990), cap. I, §§ 12–13 and 18, p. 40. More exactly, “vehementius causa”, “more strongly the cause”, says the text (cf. Proclus 1963, prop. 56, p. 54, l. 5 and 21): aitioterôn, meizonôs aition), because it “attaches itself more strongly to the thing than the operation of the next cause”, or “adheres” in it with a stronger adhesion. Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.67.5: “Causa autem actionis magis est illud cuius virtute agitur quam etiam illud quod agit: sicut principale agens magis quam instrumentum. Deus igitur principalius est causa cuiuslibet actionis quam etiam secundae causae agentes”. |
45 | |
46 | Thomas, in his commentary (Super librum De causis expositio, lectio 1), points out that Aristotle argues the same thing in Gen. An. II.3, 736a 24: the individual is animal before being human. |
47 | Liber de Causis (1990), cap. XVII, § 144, p. 66. |
48 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.67.1: “Omne enim operans est aliquo modo causa essendi, vel secundum esse substantiale, vel accidentale. Nihil autem est causa essendi nisi inquantum agit in virtute Dei, ut ostensum est. Omne igitur operans operatur per virtutem Dei”; De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Nec causa secunda potest in effectum causae primae per virtutem propriam, quamvis sit instrumentum causae primae respectu illius effectus. Instrumentum enim est causa quodammodo effectus principalis causae, non per formam vel virtutem propriam, sed in quantum participat aliquid de virtute principalis causae per motum eius”. |
49 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Non ergo sic est intelligendum quod Deus in omni re naturali operetur, quasi res naturalis nihil operetur; sed quia in ipsa natura vel voluntate operante Deus operatur”. |
50 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.4.c.: “quaecumque alia causa dat esse, hoc habet in quantum est in ea virtus et operatio primae causae, et non per propriam virtutem; sicut et instrumentum efficit actionem instrumentalem non per virtutem propriae naturae, sed per virtutem moventis; sicut calor naturalis per virtutem animae generat carnem vivam, per virtutem autem propriae naturae solummodo calefacit et dissolvit”; De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Sic ergo Deus est causa omnis actionis, prout quodlibet agens est instrumentum divinae virtutis operantis”. |
51 | |
52 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.66.6: “esse est proprius effectus primi agentis, et omnia alia agunt ipsum inquantum agunt in virtute primi agentis”; De Pot. 3.1.c: “inde etiam est quod nulla res dat esse, nisi in quantum est in ea participatio divinae virtutis. Propter quod etiam dicitur in Lib. de causis, quod anima nobilis habet operationem divinam in quantum dat esse”. |
53 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 5.1.ad5: “Si autem ponamus formas substantiales educi de potentia materiae, secundum sententiam Aristotelis, agentia naturalia non solum erunt causae dispositionum materiae, sed etiam formarum substantialium; quantum ad hoc dumtaxat quod de potentia educuntur in actum, ut dictum est, et per consequens sunt essendi principia quantum ad inchoationem ad esse, et non quantum ad ipsum esse absolute”. |
54 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “(…) nihil agit ad speciem in istis inferioribus nisi per virtutem corporis caelestis, nec aliquid agit ad esse nisi per virtutem Dei. (…) unde etiam, ut dicitur in Lib. de causis, intelligentia non dat esse, nisi prout est in ea virtus divina”. See also ScG III.66.3: “Cum igitur esse sit communis effectus omnium agentium (nam omne agens facit esse actu), oportet quod hunc effectum producunt inquantum ordinantur sub primo agente, et agunt in virtute ipsius” (all emphases mine). |
55 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Sed ulterius invenimus, secundum ordinem causarum, esse ordinem effectuum, quod necesse est propter similitudinem effectus et causae”. See above the argument from De Pot. 3.4.c. |
56 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “In qualibet autem re naturali invenimus quod est ens et quod est res naturalis, et quod est talis vel talis naturae. Quorum primum est commune omnibus entibus; secundum omnibus rebus naturalibus; tertium in una specie; et quartum, si addamus accidentia, est proprium huic individuo”. |
57 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh I.45.5.c.: “Non enim hic homo potest esse causa naturae humanae absolute, quia sic esset causa sui ipsius, sed est causa quod natura humana sit in hoc homine generato. Et sic praesupponit in sua actione determinatam materiam per quam est hic homo”. |
58 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG II.89.16: “Sic enim homo sibi simile in specie generat, inquantum virtus seminis eius dispositive operatur ad ultimam formam, ex qua homo speciem sortitur”; De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Hoc ergo individuum agendo non potest constituere aliud in simili specie nisi prout est instrumentum illius causae, quae respicit totam speciem et ulterius totum esse naturae inferioris. Et propter hoc nihil agit ad speciem in istis inferioribus nisi per virtutem corporis caelestis (…)”; STh I.115.3.ad2: “Unde secundum philosophum, in II de Gen., necesse est ponere aliquod principium activum mobile, quod per sui praesentiam et absentiam causet varietatem circa generationem et corruptionem inferiorum corporum. Et huiusmodi sunt corpora caelestia. Et ideo quidquid in istis inferioribus generat, movet ad speciem sicut instrumentum caelestis corporis; secundum quod dicitur in II Physic., quod homo generat hominem, et sol”; Quaestiones disputatae de malo 16.9.c.: “Cum enim suprema in entibus habeant virtutes maxime universales, passiva infima non sunt proportionata ad recipiendum effectum universalem immediate, sed per medias virtutes magis particulares et contractas; sicut apparet etiam in ipso ordine corporalium rerum. Nam corpora caelestia sunt principia generationis hominum, et aliorum animalium perfectorum, mediante virtute particulari, quae est in seminibus (…)”. |
59 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “(…) nihil agit ad speciem in istis inferioribus nisi per virtutem corporis caelestis, nec aliquid agit ad esse nisi per virtutem Dei. Ipsum enim esse est communissimus effectus primus et intimior omnibus aliis effectibus; et ideo soli Deo competit secundum virtutem propriam talis effectus (…)”. |
60 | |
61 | Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.1.c.: “Causalitates enim entis absolute reducuntur in primam causam universalem; causalitas vero aliorum quae ad esse superadduntur; vel quibus esse specificatur, pertinet ad causas secundas, quae agunt per informationem, quasi supposito effectu causae universalis: et inde etiam est quod nulla res dat esse, nisi in quantum est in ea participatio divinae virtutis. Propter quod etiam dicitur in Lib. de causis, quod anima nobilis habet operationem divinam in quantum dat esse”; De Pot. 3.7.c.: “Ipsum enim esse est communissimus effectus primus et intimior omnibus aliis effectibus; et ideo soli Deo competit secundum virtutem propriam talis effectus: unde etiam, ut dicitur in Lib.de causis, intelligentia non dat esse, nisi prout est in ea virtus divina. Sic ergo Deus est causa omnis actionis, prout quodlibet agens est instrumentum divinae virtutis operantis”. See also De Pot. 7.2.c. |
62 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.1.c: “(…) in nulla re naturali includuntur actus et perfectiones omnium eorum quae sunt in actu; sed quaelibet illarum habet actum determinatum ad unum genus et ad unam speciem; et inde est quod nulla earum est activa entis secundum quod est ens, sed eius entis secundum quod est hoc ens, determinatum in hac vel illa specie: nam agens agit sibi simile. Et ideo agens naturale non producit simpliciter ens, sed ens praeexistens et determinatum ad hoc vel ad aliud (…) Et inde est quod in Lib. de causis, dicitur, quod esse eius est per creationem, vivere vero, et caetera huiusmodi, per informationem. Causalitates enim entis absolute reducuntur in primam causam universalem; causalitas vero aliorum quae ad esse superadduntur; vel quibus esse specificatur, pertinet ad causas secundas, quae agunt per informationem, quasi supposito effectu causae universalis (…)”. |
63 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.66.6: “Primum autem in omnibus effectibus est esse: nam omnia alia sunt quaedam determinationes ipsius. Igitur esse est proprius effectus primi agentis, et omnia alia agunt ipsum inquantum agunt in virtute primi agentis. Secunda autem agentia, quae sunt quasi particulantes et determinantes actionem primi agentis, agunt sicut proprios effectus alias perfectiones, quae determinant esse”. See also ScG II.21: “Alia vero agentia non sunt causa essendi simpliciter, sed causa essendi hoc, ut hominem vel album”. |
64 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.4.c.: “Nam actio alicuius, etiamsi sit eius ut instrumenti, oportet ut ab eius potentia egrediatur”. |
65 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.70.7: “Patet etiam quod non sic idem effectus causae naturali et divinae virtuti attribuitur quasi partim a Deo, et partim a naturali agente fiat, sed totus ab utroque secundum alium modum: sicut idem effectus totus attribuitur instrumento, et principali agenti etiam totus”. |
66 | Durandus de Sancto Porciano (1571, [Redactio C] II.1.5, § 5, p. 130 va). For this question, I will use version C of Durand’s Commentary. As I said above, Durand altogether omitted this sensitive question in version B (besides moving part of it to distinction 37), and the text of version C is here identical to that of version A (it is an example of how Durand reverted to his first positions when he got free rein). Whereas it was the fourth question of distinction 1 in version A, it is the fifth in version C, because of the insertion of an additional question in the latter. |
67 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. II.1.1.4.c.: “Aliorum vero quae per motum et generationem producuntur, creatura causa esse potest, vel ita quod habeat causalitatem supra totam speciem, sicut sol est causa in generatione hominis vel leonis; vel ita quod habeat causalitatem ad unum individuum speciei tantum, sicut homo generat hominem, et ignis ignem. Horum tamen causa etiam Deus est, magis intime in eis operans quam aliae causae moventes: quia ipse est dans esse rebus. Causae autem aliae sunt quasi determinantes illud esse. Nullius enim rei totum esse ab aliqua creatura principium sumit, cum materia a Deo solum sit; esse autem est magis intimum cuilibet rei quam ea per quae esse determinatur; unde et remanet, illis remotis, ut in libro de causis dicitur. Unde operatio creatoris magis pertingit ad intima rei quam operatio causarum secundarum: et ideo hoc quod creatum est causa alii creaturae, non excludit quin Deus immediate in rebus omnibus operetur, inquantum virtus sua est sicut medium conjungens virtutem cujuslibet causae secundae cum suo effectu (…)”. |
68 | Freddoso (1994, pp. 143–47), did not realize that it is Aquinas, and specifically this passage, that Durand discusses, whereas Stufler 1935 had long since highlighted it. As a consequence, if the position stated here is a blunder with respect to true concurrentism, as Freddoso underlines (the proposed solution suggests a “division of labor” between principal and secondary cause, by which “each agent contributes independently as an immediate cause to its own distinctive effect”, i.e., matter and form, whereas true concurrentism maintains that the two actions combine in the production of one and the same effect, the composite form-matter), it is Aquinas’ blunder—which he does not repeat later. |
69 | Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De pot. 5.1.c.: “(...) formae generatorum dependent a generantibus naturaliter, quod educuntur de potentia materiae, non autem quantum ad esse absolutum”. It is possible that we find here an echo of Avicenna’s thesis according to which the builder of a house is not the efficient cause of the existence of the house, but only of its construction, as he assembles materials that already have existence. |
70 | |
71 | Durandus de Sancto Porciano (1571), lib. II, dist. 1, q. 5, § 6, p. 130 va. |
72 | See Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. II.9.1.4.c.; De Principiis Naturae, cap. 1; De Ente et Essentia, cap. III; ScG II.68; STh I.76.4.c. |
73 | One should however keep in mind that the context of the passage at hand is the creation ab initio and ex nihilo. That may be why Aquinas is drawn to the idea that creatures cannot produce existence because they need to act on some preexisting matter. |
74 | See Aegidius Romanus (1581 [Ordinatio], lib. II, pars I, q. 2, a. 6, p. 31a, B–C): “Intimius enim operatur Deus actionem ignis, quam ipse ignis; et magis conservat Deus ignem in esse et facit magis ad esse ignis, quam ipsa essentia ignis. Hoc enim modo dicitur esse Deus intimior rei quam ipsa res sibi, qui per se et potissime conservat rem in esse. Nam esse extrinsice magis faciunt ad fieri rei, intrinsece autem magis ad esse (…). Et quod dictum est de Deo respectu esse rei, verum est de Deo respectu actionis rei; nam ipsam actionem rei magis Deus causat et in esse conservat quam res ipsa agens actionem illam. Nam ad momentum nec res nec sua actio posset subsistere nisi Deus esset in ea”. |
75 | Cf. Aristotle, Phys. II.1, 193b 3–8. |
76 | |
77 | See Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Super Evangelium S. loannis Lectura, cap. I, 1ect. 5, § 133: “Sed tamen aliter est de Verbo agente et causante omnia, et al.iter de aliis agentibus. Nam alia agentia operantur ut extrinsecus existentia: cum enim non agant nisi movendo et al.terando aliquo modo ea quae sunt extrinseca rei, ut extrinseca operantur. Deus vero operatur in omnibus ut interius agens, quia agit creando. Creare autem est dare esse rei creatae. Cum ergo esse sit intimum cuilibet rei, Deus, qui operando dat esse, operatur in rebus ut intimus agens”; De Ver. 8.16.ad12: “(…) ipse Deus est propria et immediata causa uniuscuiusque rei, et quodammodo magis intima unicuique quam ipsum sit intimum sibi, ut Augustinus dicit”; STh I.105.5.c.: “Et quia forma rei est intra rem, et tanto magis quanto consideratur ut prior et universalior; et ipse Deus est proprie causa ipsius esse universalis in rebus omnibus, quod inter omnia est magis intimum rebus; sequitur quod Deus in omnibus intime operetur. Et propter hoc in sacra Scriptura operationes naturae Deo attribuuntur quasi operanti in natura (…)”. Cf. Aegidius Romanus (1581), II.1.2.6, p. 31a: “Intimius enim operatur Deus actionem ignis, quam ipse ignis; et magis conservat Deus ignem in esse et facit magis ad esse ignis, quam ipsa essentia ignis. Hoc enim modo dicitur esse Deus intimior rei quam ipsa res sibi, qui per se et potissime conservat rem in esse. Nam esse extrinsice magis faciunt ad fieri rei, intrinsece autem magis ad esse (…). Et quod dictum est de Deo respectu esse rei, verum est de Deo respectu actionis rei; nam ipsam actionem rei magis Deus causat et in esse conservat quam res ipsa agens actionem illam. Nam ad momentum nec res nec sua actio posset subsistere nisi Deus esset in ea”. |
78 | Aristotle, De An. II.4, 415b13. Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. I.8.5.3.ad3: “(…) uno modo vivere est ipsum esse viventis, sicut dicit philosophus: vivere viventibus est esse; et hoc modo anima immediate facit vivere quamlibet partem corporis, inquantum est ejus forma (…)”; Sent. IV.49.1.2.3.c.: “(…) vita dicitur dupliciter. Uno modo ipsum esse viventis; quia, ut in 2 de anima dicitur, vivere viventibus est esse”; Sententia Libri De Anima I.14.11: “Unde et vivere dupliciter accipitur. Uno modo accipitur vivere, quod est esse viventis, sicut dicit philosophus, quod vivere est esse viventibus. Alio modo vivere est operatio”. |
79 | Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), Sent. Lib. De An., II.7.11: “(…) anima viventibus est causa essendi; per animam enim vivunt, et ipsum vivere est esse eorum (…)”. |
80 | |
81 | |
82 | Durand discusses Giles’ Reportatio (written perhaps before 1271), which is the only version he could have known when he first wrote his own Commentary, before 1308 (version A, but recall that this quaestio is omitted in version B, and that its content is identical in version C). Giles worked on the ordinatio of his Commentary on book II of the Sentences only after 1309. The relevant passage there (II.2.6, p. 29b–33a) is longer than in the Reportatio because Giles preliminarily discusses more alternative views, but the gist of his answer (pp. 31b, B—32a, C) is the same as in the Reportatio. See also Aegidius Romanus (1503) (ca. 1286–87), q. 4 and 5. |
83 | Giles specifies in the Ordinatio that of course, if he wanted to, God could make anything “completely”, in every respect, i.e., including the particular kind of being it is, without the intervention of any secondary agent: “(…) posset sine igne calefacere; quod faciendo, calefactionem ipsam faceret immediate totam, ut est ens et ut est tale ens; propter quod faceret eam immediate totam, et immediate totaliter” (Aegidius Romanus 1581, 1.2.6, p. 32a, B). |
84 | See Aegidius Romanus (1581, 1.2.6, p. 31b, B–C): “Sic ergo imaginabimur de actione Dei et secundorum agentium in his quae producit Deus secundum naturae cursum mediantibus eis, sicut imaginatur Dionysius, 4 De Divinis Nominibus, quod sicut sol non ratiocinans aut praeeligens, omnia illuminat valentia participare lumen secundum propriam rationem, sic bonum, quod est super solem, omnibus existentibus proportionabiliter immittit totius bonitatis radios. Prima ergo causa, non ratiocinans aut praeeligens, uniformiter se habet ad omnia. Existit enim in omnibus rebus secundum dispositionem unam, ut dicitur in 24. propositione de causis. Quantum ergo ad hunc modum agendi, omnia agit uno modo, sed non omnia recipiunt actionem Dei eodem modo”. Aegidius Romanus (1503, q. 4, p. 9 rb): “Deus uniformiter operetur omnia, sed si est diversitas in rebus, hoc est propter secunda agentia mediantibus quibus operatur Deus. Ipsam enim infrigidationem operatur Deus et etiam ipsam calefactionem, et secundum hunc modum agendi quem videmus Deus uniformiter operatur hanc et illam. Sed quod differat hec ab illa, ut quod differat calefactio ab infrigidatione, hoc est propter secunda agentia, ut quia calefactionem operatur mediante igne, infrigidationem vero mediante aqua”. |
85 | Durandus de Sancto Porciano (1571, II.1.5, § 7, p. 130 vb). Cf. Aegidius Romanus (2003, II.8, p. 208, l. 19–35), and Aegidius Romanus (1581, 1.2.6, p. 32a, A): “Omnes ergo effectus, de quibus loquimur, sunt immediate a Deo, ut sunt entia et ut habent esse, et sunt immediate a secundis agentibus ut sunt tale ens et ut habent tale esse”. The same goes not only for the effects but also the actions of the creatures (ibid., A–B: “calefactio ergo, quae est actio ignis, tota est immediate a Deo ut est ens (…) et tota est immediate ab igne ut est tale ens et ut differt ab alia actione, quia, ut dictum est, ipsa secunda agentia, recipiendo diversimode influentiam Dei, faciunt diversitatem in huiusmodi actionibus”). |
86 | Aegidius Romanus (1503, q. 5, p. 10 rb): “Concedimus enim eandem rem esse causatam a Deo et a natura, sed non eodem modo. Ut si Deus mediante igne causat ignem, ignis causatus ut est ignis est ab igne, ut est ens est a Deo. Ignis ergo causat ignem et ens, et Deus causat ens et ignem; sed ignis causat ens quia causat ignem, Deus autem e converso causat ignem quia causat ens”. |
87 | |
88 | |
89 | Phys. II.3, 195b 25–27. |
90 | Durandus de Sancto Porciano (1571, II.1.5, § 8, p. 130 vb). The editor of Durand’s version A refers to James of Metz (Durandus de Sancto Porciano 2012, II.1.4, 52, n. 106). |
91 | Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), STh I.45.5.c.: “Oportet enim universaliores effectus in universaliores et priores causas reducere. Inter omnes autem effectus, universalissimum est ipsum esse. Unde oportet quod sit proprius effectus primae et universalissimae causae, quae est Deus”. |
92 | Durandus de Sancto Porciano (1571, II.1.5, § 10, p. 130 vb). The examples of concurrence between really distinct causes that Freddoso (1994, pp. 148–49), opposes to Durand are irrelevant, since they all involve particular causes, whereas what Durand is questioning is that there is a real distinction between universal cause and particular cause. For him, the former is merely the latter taken at a certain degree of generality. |
93 | |
94 | |
95 | Contrary to Tuttle (2022, p. 89), I do not find it particularly difficult to interpret Durand’s present argument, provided that it is read in continuity with the earlier refutations of Thomas and Giles. |
96 | |
97 | Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), De Pot. 3.7.c.: “[S]i consideremus supposita agentia, quodlibet agens particulare est immediatum ad suum effectum. Si autem consideremus virtutem qua fit actio, sic virtus superioris causae erit immediatior effectui quam virtus inferioris; nam virtus inferior non coniungitur effectui nisi per virtutem superioris (…)”. |
98 | Thus, the similar case that Freddoso (1994, p. 149), tries to oppose to Durand, has in fact been described and taken into account by the latter. |
99 | Cf. Thomas de Aquino (2000–2019), ScG III.70.5: “Quibusdam autem difficile videtur ad intelligendum quod effectus naturales et Deo attribuantur et naturali agenti. Nam una actio a duobus agentibus non videtur progredi posse. (…) Haec autem difficultatem non afferunt si praemissa considerentur. In quolibet enim agente est duo considerare, scilicet rem ipsam quae agit, et virtutem qua agit: sicut ignis calefacit per calorem. Virtus autem inferioris agentis dependet a virtute superioris agentis, inquantum superius agens dat virtutem ipsam inferiori agenti per quam agit; vel conservat eam; aut etiam applicat eam ad agendum, sicut artifex applicat instrumentum ad proprium effectum; cui tamen non dat formam per quam agit instrumentum, nec conservat, sed dat ei solum motum”. |
100 | |
101 | |
102 | Again, if he wanted to, God could directly cause what the secondary cause produces, but in that case, it would be without the help of the secondary cause. |
103 | John Duns Scotus seems to have maintained this view at the end of his career. See Frost (2009) and Wolter (1994). Henry of Ghent endorses it more explicitly (Henricus de Gandavo 1983, q. 5, pp. 120–21, and Henricus de Gandavo 1987, q. 26, pp. 155–56). |
104 | See Newlands (2014, pp. 290–92). Cf. above, p. 3. |
105 | |
106 | As Newlands concludes. See these objections above, p. 3, and Newland’s conclusion about Leibniz’s later doctrine (Newlands 2014, pp. 303–5; see also Newlands 2019). |
References
- Aegidius Romanus (Giles of Rome). 1503. Questiones Disputate de Esse et Essentia, de Mensura Angelorum, et de Cognitione Angelorum. Venice: Andrea Torresanus de Asula. [Google Scholar]
- Aegidius Romanus (Giles of Rome). 1581. In Secundum Librum Sententiarum Quaestiones [Ordinatio]. Venice: Francisco Ziletto. [Google Scholar]
- Aegidius Romanus (Giles of Rome). 2003. Reportatio lecturae super libros I–IV Sententiarum: Reportatio Monacensis; Excerpta Godefridi de Fontibus. In Aegidii Romani Opera Omnia. Edited by Concetta Luna. Florence: SISMEL—Edizioni del Galluzo, vol. III, p. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Albertus Magnus. 1893. Commentarii in secundum librum Sententiarum. In Opera Omnia. Edited by Auguste Borgnet. Paris: Louis Vivès, vol. XXVII. [Google Scholar]
- Bayle, Pierre. 1731. Institutio Brevis et Accurata Totius Philosophiæ/Systême Abrégé de Philosophie. In Œuvres Diverses. Rotterdam and La Haye: P. Husson et al., vol. IV, pp. 199–520. [Google Scholar]
- Bernier, François. 1685. Traité du Libre et du Volontaire. Amsterdam: Henri Desbordes. [Google Scholar]
- Boulnois, Olivier, Pierre Magnard, Bruno Pinchard, and Jean-Luc Solère, eds. 1990. Liber de Causis. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Durandus de Sancto Porciano. 1571. Petri Lombardi Sententias Theologicas Commentariorum Libri IIII [Redactio C]. Edited by Nicolaus a Martimbos. 2 vols. Venice: Guerrea. [Google Scholar]
- Durandus de Sancto Porciano. 2012. Scriptum Super IV Libros Sententiarum, Distinctiones 1–5 Libri Secundi [Redactiones A et B]. Edited by Fiorella Retucci. Leuven, Paris and Walpole: Peeters. [Google Scholar]
- Durandus de Sancto Porciano. 2013. Scriptum Super IV Libros Sententiarum, Distinctiones 22–38 Libri Secundi [Redactiones A et B]. Edited by Fiorella Retucci and Massimo Perrone. Leuven, Paris and Walpole: Peeters. [Google Scholar]
- Flasch, Kurt. 2013. Das Philosophische Denken im Mittelalter. Von Augustin zu Machiavelli. Stuttgart: Reclam Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Freddoso, Alfred J. 1991. God’s General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Why Conservation Is Not Enough. Philosophical Perspectives 5: 553–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Freddoso, Alfred J. 1994. God’s General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Pitfalls and Prospects. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 68: 131–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frost, Gloria. 2009. John Duns Scotus on God’s Knowledge of Sins. Journal of the History of Philosophy 48: 15–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frost, Gloria. 2014. Peter Olivi’s Rejection of God’s Concurrence with Created Causes. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22: 655–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Henricus de Gandavo. 1983. Quodlibet IX. In Henrici de Gandavo Opera Omnia. Edited by Raymond Macken. Leuven: Leuven University Press, vol. 13. [Google Scholar]
- Henricus de Gandavo. 1987. Quodlibet XII, Quaestiones 1–30. In Henrici de Gandavo Opera Omnia. Edited by Jos Decorte. Leuven: Leuven University Press, vol. 16. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2008. Essais de Théodicée. In Die Philosophichen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Edited by C. I. Gebhardt. Hildesheim, Zürich and New York: Georg Olms Verlag, vol. 6. [Google Scholar]
- Malebranche, Nicolas. 1976. De la Recherche de la Vérité. Éclaircissements. In Œuvres Complètes. Edited by Geneviève Rodis-Lewis. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, t. III. [Google Scholar]
- Newlands, Samuel. 2014. Leibniz on Privations, Limitations, and the Metaphysics of Evil. Journal of the History of Philosophy 52: 281–308. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Newlands, Samuel. 2019. Evils, Privations, and the Early Moderns. In Evil: A History. Edited by Andrew Chignell. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 273–305. [Google Scholar]
- Petrus Iohannis Olivi. 1926. Quaestiones in Secundum Librum Sententiarum, Vol. III: Quaestiones 72–118. In Bibliotheca Franciscana Scholastica Medii Aevi. Edited by Bernhard Jansen. Quaracchi: Collegium S. Bonaventura, t. VI. [Google Scholar]
- Piro, Francesco. 2009. Lo Scolastico che faceva un partito a sé (faisait bande à part). Leibniz su Durando di San Porziano e la disputa sui futuri contingenti. Medioevo 34: 507–43. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. 1963. The Elements of Theology, 2nd ed. Translated and Edited by Eric R. Dodds. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sleigh, Robert. 1996. Leibniz’s First Theodicy. Philosophical Perspectives 10: 481–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Solère, Jean-Luc. 2022. Thomas d’Aquin, l’étiologie proclusienne, et la théorie du concours de Dieu à la causalité naturelle. In Reading Proclus and the Book of Causes. Edited by Dragos Calma. Leiden: Brill, vol. 3, pp. 303–37. [Google Scholar]
- Speer, Andreas, Fiorella Retucci, Thomas Jeschke, and Guy Guldentops, eds. 2014. Durand of Saint-Pourçain and His Sentences Commentary. Historical, Philosophical and Theological Issues. Leuven: Peeters. [Google Scholar]
- Stufler, Johann Baptist. 1935. Bemerkungen Zur Konkurslehre Des Durandus von St. Pourçain. In Aus Der Geisteswelt des Mittelalters: Studien Und Texte Martin Grabmann Zur Vollendung Des 60. Lebensjahres. Munster: Aschendorff Verlag, pp. 1081–90. [Google Scholar]
- Suárez, Francisco. 1866. Disputationes Metaphysicae. In Opera omnia. Edited by Charles Berton. Paris: Louis Vivès, vol. XXV. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas de Aquino. 2000–2019. Opera Omnia. Edited by Enrique Alarcón. Available online: http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/iopera.html (accessed on 26 January 2024).
- Toth, Zita V. 2020. Peter of Palude and the Fiery Furnace. History of Philosophy Quarterly 37: 121–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tuttle, Jacob. 2022. Durand and Suárez on Divine Causation. In Philosophical Essays on Divine Causation. Edited by Gregory Ganssle. New York: Routledge, pp. 82–101. [Google Scholar]
- Wippel, John. 2000. Thomas Aquinas on Creatures as Causes of Esse. International Philosophical Quarterly 40: 197–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolter, Allan B. 1994. Alnwick on Scotus and Divine Concurrence. In Greek and Medieval Studies in Honor of Leo Sweeney, S.J. New York: P. Lang, pp. 255–83. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Solère, J.-L. Durand of Saint-Pourçain’s Refutation of Concurrentism. Religions 2024, 15, 558. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050558
Solère J-L. Durand of Saint-Pourçain’s Refutation of Concurrentism. Religions. 2024; 15(5):558. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050558
Chicago/Turabian StyleSolère, Jean-Luc. 2024. "Durand of Saint-Pourçain’s Refutation of Concurrentism" Religions 15, no. 5: 558. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050558