2. Comparison of Different Physical and Mathematical Theories
When two physical or mathematical theories are compared one can pose a problem whether one of them is more general than the other.
One of the known examples is the comparison of nonrelativistic theory (NT) with relativistic one (RT). Usually RT is treated as more general than NT for several reasons. The basic principles of RT are treated as more general than those for NT but a necessary condition for theory A to be treated as more general than theory B is that A should describe experiment better than B, and indeed RT describes experiment better than NT. A problem arises whether there are mathematical arguments in favor of the statement that RT is more general than NT. One of the arguments is that RT contains a finite parameter c and NT can be treated as a special degenerated case of RT in the formal limit . Therefore, by choosing a large value of c, RT can reproduce any result of NT with a high accuracy. On the contrary, when the limit is already taken one cannot return back from NT to RT and NT cannot reproduce all results of RT. It can reproduce only results obtained when .
Other known examples are that classical theory is a special degenerated case of quantum one in the formal limit and RT is a special degenerated case of de Sitter (dS) and anti-de Sitter (AdS) invariant theories in the formal limit where R is the parameter of contraction from the dS or AdS algebras to the Poincare algebra (see below). A problem arises whether it is possible to give a general definition when theory A is more general than theory B. In view of the above examples, we propose the following
Definition 1. Let theory A contain a finite parameter and theory B be obtained from theory A in the formal limit when the parameter goes to zero or infinity. Suppose that with any desired accuracy theory A can reproduce any result of theory B by choosing a value of the parameter. On the contrary, when the limit is already taken then one cannot return back to theory A, and theory B cannot reproduce all results of theory A. Then theory A is more general than theory B and theory B is a special degenerated case of theory A.
A problem arises how to justify this Definition not only from physical but also from mathematical considerations.
In relativistic quantum theory the usual approach to symmetry on quantum level follows. Since the Poincare group is the group of motions of Minkowski space, quantum states should be described by representations of this group. This implies that the representation generators acting in the Hilbert space of the system under consideration commute according to the commutation relations of the Poincare group Lie algebra:
where
,
are the operators of the four-momentum and
are the operators of Lorentz angular momenta. This approach is in the spirit of Klein’s Erlangen Program in mathematics.
However, background space has a direct physical meaning only on classical level, and this is clear even from the fact that in quantum theory neither time nor coordinates can be measured with the absolute accuracy (see a more detailed discussion below). In QED, QCD and electroweak theory the Lagrangian density depends on the four-vector x which is associated with a point in Minkowski space but this is only the integration parameter which is used in the intermediate stage. The goal of the theory is to construct the S-matrix and when the theory is already constructed one can forget about Minkowski space because no physical quantity depends on x. This is in the spirit of the Heisenberg S-matrix program according to which in relativistic quantum theory it is possible to describe only transitions of states from the infinite past when to the distant future when .
Note that the fact that the
S-matrix is the operator in momentum space does not exclude the possibility that in some situations it is possible to have a space-time description with some accuracy but not with absolute accuracy. First of all, the problem of time is one of the most important unsolved problems of quantum theory (see e.g., Reference [
1] and references therein), and time cannot be measured with an accuracy better than
s. Also, in typical situations, the position operator in momentum representation exists not only in the nonrelativistic case but in the relativistic case as well. In the latter case it is known, for example, as the Newton-Wigner position operator [
2] or its modification (see e.g., Reference [
3]). As pointed out even in textbooks on quantum theory, the coordinate description of elementary particles can work only in some approximations. In particular, even in most favorable scenarios, for a massive particle with the mass
m its coordinate cannot be measured with an accuracy better than the particle Compton wave length
[
4].
For illustration of the background problem, consider first classical electrodynamics. We know that the electromagnetic field consists of photons but on classical level the theory does not describe the state of each photon. The classical electromagnetic fields and describe the effective contribution of all photons at the point of Minkowski space, and in classical (non-quantum) theory it is assumed that the parameters can be measured with any desired accuracy.
On quantum level a problem arises how to define the photon coordinate wave function. For example, a section in the known textbook [
5] is titled “Impossibility of introducing the photon wave function in coordinate representation”. On the other hand, a detailed discussion of the photon position operator in papers by Margaret Hawton [
6,
7,
8] and references therein indicates that it is possible to define the photon coordinate wave function
but the description with such a wave function can have a good accuracy only in semiclassical approximation (see also Reference [
3]), and coordinates cannot be directly measured with an accuracy better than the size of the hydrogen atom.
In particle physics distances are never measured directly, and the phrase that the physics of some process is defined by characteristic distances
l means only that if
q is a characteristic momentum transfer in this process then
. This conclusion is based on the assumption that coordinate and momentum representations in quantum theory are related to each other by the Fourier transform. However, as shown in Reference [
3], this assumption is based neither on strong theoretical arguments nor on experimental data.
Local quantum field theories (QFT) work with local quantized field operators . Such operators act in the Fock space of the system under consideration. Here the quantity x is not related to any particle, this is only a formal parameter. One of the principles of quantum theory is that any physical quantity should be described by an operator. However, since x is not related to any particle, there is no operator related to x. Therefore x cannot be directly measured and does not have a direct physical meaning. Strictly speaking, even the word "local" here might be misleading since x is not related to any particle.
Foundational problems of QFT have been discussed by many authors. One of the main problems in substantiating QFT is that QFT contains products of interacting local quantized fields at the same points. As explained in textbooks (e.g., in the book [
9]), such fields can be treated only as distributions, and the product of distributions at the same point is not a correct mathematical operation. As a consequence, in QFT there are divergences and other inconsistencies. It is rather strange that many physicists believe that such products are needed to preserve locality. However, such products have nothing to do with locality because
x is not a physical quantity.
As stated in the introductory section of the textbook [
4], local quantum fields and Lagrangians are rudimentary notions which will disappear in the ultimate quantum theory. My observation is that now physicists usually do not believe that such words could be written in such a known textbook. The reason is that in view of successes of QCD and electroweak theory for explaining experimental data those ideas have become almost forgotten. However, although the successes are rather impressive, they do not contribute to resolving inconsistencies in QFT. Also, in the textbook [
9] devoted to mathematical aspects of QFT, products of interacting quantum local fields are never used.
In QED one can formally define the operators and which are local quantized field operators acting in the Fock space for the quantum electromagnetic field. However, since x is not related to any photon, those operators do not define observable physical quantities. Those operators are used in theory such that integrals of their combinations over space-like hypersurfaces of Minkowski space define the energy-momentum and angular momentum operators of the electromagnetic field. So the situation is similar to that mentioned above when x in the Lagrangian density is only the integration parameter.
For illustration of the foundational problems of QFT, consider a photon emitted in the famous 21 cm transition line between the hyperfine energy levels of the hydrogen atom. The phrase that the lifetime of this transition is of the order of years is understood such that the width of the level is of the order of that is, the uncertainty of the photon energy is . In this situation a description of the system (atom + electric field) by the wave function (e.g., in the Fock space) depending on a continuous parameter t has no physical meaning (since roughly speaking the quantum of time in this process is of the order of years).
The above examples show that space-time description with continuous space-time parameters cannot be universal in all situations. In particular, the notion of background space cannot be universal on quantum level. For all those reasons, as argued in Reference [
10], the approach to symmetry should be the opposite to that proceeding from the Erlangen Program. Each system is described by a set of linearly independent operators. By definition, the rules how they commute with each other define the symmetry algebra. In particular,
by definition, Poincare symmetry on quantum level means that the operators commute according to Equation (
1). This definition does not involve Minkowski space at all.
Such a definition of symmetry on quantum level has been proposed in Reference [
11] and in subsequent publications of those authors. I am very grateful to Leonid Avksent’evich Kondratyuk for explaining me this definition during our collaboration. I believe that this replacement of standard paradigm is fundamental for understanding quantum theory, and I did not succeed in finding a similar idea in the literature.
Our goal is to compare four theories: classical (i.e., non-quantum) theory, nonrelativistic quantum theory, relativistic quantum theory and de Sitter (dS) or anti-de Sitter (AdS) quantum theory. All those theories are described by representations of the symmetry algebra containing ten linearly independent operators : four energy-momentum operators, three angular momentum operators and three Galilei or Lorentz boost operators. For definiteness we assume that the operators where refer to energy-momentum operators, the operators where refer to angular momentum operators and the operators where refer to Galilei or Lorentz boost operators. Let where summation over repeated indices is assumed. In the theory of Lie algebras the quantities are called the structure constants.
Let be a set of pairs such that for all values of and be a set of pairs such that at least for some values of . Since it suffices to consider only such pairs where . If then the operators and commute while if then they do not commute. Let be the sets for theory A and be the sets for theory B. As noted above, we will consider only theories where . Then one can prove the following
Statement: Let theory A contain a finite parameter and theory B be obtained from theory A in the formal limit when the parameter goes to zero or infinity. If the setsandare different and(what equivalent to) then theory A is more general than theory B and theory B is a special degenerated case of theory A.
Proof. Let be the set of pairs such that and . Then, in theory B, for any . One can choose the parameter such that in theory A all the quantities are arbitrarily small. Therefore, by choosing a value of the parameter, theory A can reproduce any result of theory B with any desired accuracy. When the limit is already taken then, in theory B, for all . For a set of mutually commuting selfadjourned operators there exists a basis such that its basis elements are eigenvectors of all the operators from the set. This means that the operators and become fully independent and therefore there is no way to return to the situation when they do not commute. Therefore for theories A and B the conditions of Definition are satisfied. ☐
It is sometimes stated that the expressions in Equation (
1) are written in the system of units
. Strictly speaking, this statement is not correct because for the construction of relativistic quantum theory based on those equations neither
c nor
ℏ is needed. The notion of the system of units is purely classical, and a problem arises whether quantum theory should involve this notion. For example, in the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory, measurement is treated as an interaction with a classical object. Therefore, in this interpretation, quantum theory is not fully independent on classical one. On the other hand, the Copenhagen interpretation probably cannot be universal. For example, according to the present knowledge, at the very early stages of the Universe classical objects did not exist.
In the representation (
1) the operators
are dimensionless. However, this theory still depends on systems of units because the operators
have the dimension
. In particular, standard angular momentum operators
are dimensionless and satisfy the commutation relations
For comparison with classical theory, all physical quantities in both theories should be expressed in the same units. For this reason one can impose a requirement that the operators
should have the dimension
. Then they should be replaced by
, respectively. In that case the new commutation relations will have the same form as in Equations (
1) and (
2) but the right-hand-sides will contain the additional factor
ℏ.
As shown in quantum theory, in the representation (
2) the results for angular momenta are given by half-integer numbers
. One can say that in units where the angular momentum is a half-integer
l, its value in
is
. Which of those two values has more physical significance? In units where the angular momentum components are half-integers, the commutation relations (
2) do not depend on any parameters. Then the meaning of
l is clear: it shows how large the angular momentum is in comparison with the minimum nonzero value 1/2. At the same time, the measurement of the angular momentum in units
reflects only a historic fact that at macroscopic conditions on the Earth between the 18th and 21st centuries people measured the angular momentum in such units.
We conclude that for quantum theory itself the quantity
ℏ is not needed. However, it is needed for the transition from quantum theory to classical one: we introduce
ℏ, then the operators
have the dimension
, and since the right-hand-sides of Equations (
1) and (
2) in this case contain an additional factor
ℏ, all the commutation relations disappear in the formal limit
. Therefore in classical theory the set
is empty and all the
pairs belong to
. Since in quantum theory there exist
pairs such that the operators
and
do not commute then in quantum theory the set
is not empty and, as follows from
Statement, classical theory is a special degenerated case of quantum one in the formal limit
. Since in classical theory all operators commute with each other then in this theory operators are not needed and one can work only with physical quantities. A question why
ℏ is as is does not arise since the answer is: because people’s choice is to measure angular momenta in
.
Consider now the relation between RT and NT. If we introduce the Lorentz boost operators
then Equations (
1) can be written as
where
,
is the fully asymmetric tensor such that
,
is the Kronecker symbol and a summation over repeated indices is assumed. If we now define the energy and Galilei boost operators as
and
, respectively then the new expressions in Equations (
3) will have the same form while instead of Equation (
4) we will have
Note that for relativistic theory itself the quantity
c is not needed. In this theory the primary quantities describing particles are their momenta
and energies
E while the velocity
of a particle is
defined as
. This definition does not involve meters and seconds, and the velocities
are dimensionless quantities such that
if tachyons are not taken into account. One needs
c only for having a possibility to compare RT and NT: when we introduce
c then the velocity of a particle becomes
, and its dimension becomes m/s. In this case, instead of the operators
and
we work with the operators
E and
, respectively. If
M is the Casimir operator for the Poincare algebra defined such that
then in the formal limit
the first expression in Equation (
5) becomes
while the commutators in the second expression become zero. Therefore in NT the
pairs with
belong to
while in RT they belong to
. Therefore, as follows from
Statement, NT is a special degenerated case of RT in the formal limit
. The question of why
m/s and not, say
m/s does not arise since the answer is: because people’s choice is to measure velocities in m/s.
From the mathematical point of view, c is the parameter of contraction from the Poincare algebra to the Galilei one. This parameter must be finite: the formal case corresponds to the situation when the Poincare algebra does not exist because it becomes the Galilei algebra.
In his famous paper “Missed Opportunities” [
12] Dyson notes that RT is more general than NT, and dS and AdS theories are more general than RT not only from physical but also from pure mathematical considerations. Poincare group is more symmetric than Galilei one and the transition from the former to the latter at
is called contraction. Analogously dS and AdS groups are more symmetric than Poincare one and the transition from the former to the latter at
(described below) also is called contraction. At the same time, since dS and AdS groups are semisimple they have a maximum possible symmetry and cannot be obtained from more symmetric groups by contraction. However, since we treat symmetry not from the point of view of a group of motions for the corresponding background space but from the point of view of commutation relations in the symmetry algebra, we will discuss the relations between the dS and AdS algebra on one hand and the Poincare algebra on the other.
By analogy with the definition of Poincare symmetry on quantum level, the definition of dS symmetry on quantum level should not involve the fact that the dS group is the group of motions of dS space. Instead,
the definition is that the operators
(
,
) describing the system under consideration satisfy the commutation relations
of the dS Lie algebra so(1,4), that is,
where
is the diagonal metric tensor such that
. The
definition of AdS symmetry on quantum level is given by the same equations but
.
With such a definition of symmetry on quantum level, dS and AdS symmetries are more natural than Poincare symmetry. In the dS and AdS cases all the ten representation operators of the symmetry algebra are angular momenta while in the Poincare case only six of them are angular momenta and the remaining four operators represent standard energy and momentum. In the representation (
6) all the operators are dimensionless, and the theory does not depend on the system of units. If we
define the operators
as
where
R is a parameter with the dimension
then in the formal limit when
,
but the quantities
are finite, Equations (
6) become Equations (
1). This procedure is called contraction and in the given case it is the same for the dS or AdS symmetries. As follows from Equations (
1) and (
6), if
then the
pairs belong to
in RT and to
in dS and AdS theories. Therefore, as follows from
Statement, RT is indeed a special degenerated case of dS and AdS theories in the formal limit
. By analogy with the abovementioned fact that
c must be finite,
R must be finite too: the formal case
corresponds to the situation when the dS and AdS algebras do not exist because they become the Poincare algebra.
Note that the operators in Equation (
6) do not depend on
R at all. This quantity is needed only for transition from dS quantum theory to Poincare quantum theory. Although
R has the dimension
, it has nothing to do with the radius of the background space which, as noted above, has a direct physical meaning only in classical theory:
R is simply the coefficient of proportionality between the operators
and
. In full analogy with the above discussion of the quantities
ℏ and
c, a question why
R is as is does not arise and the answer is: because people’s choice is to measure distances in meters.
We have proved that all the three discussed comparisons satisfy the conditions formulated in Definition above. Namely, the more general theory contains a finite parameter which is introduced for having a possibility to compare this theory with a less general one. Then the less general theory can be treated as a special degenerated case of the former in the formal limit when the parameter goes to zero or infinity. The more general theory can reproduce all results of the less general one by choosing some value of the parameter. On the contrary, when the limit is already taken one cannot return back from the less general theory to the more general one.
In References [
13,
14] we considered properties of dS quantum theory and argued that dS symmetry is more natural than Poincare one. However, the above discussion proves that dS and AdS symmetries are not only more natural than Poincare symmetry but more general. In particular,
R is fundamental to the same extent as
ℏ and
c and, as noted above,
R must be finite. Indeed,
ℏ is the contraction parameter from quantum Lie algebra to the classical one,
c is the contraction parameter from Poincare invariant quantum theory to Galilei invariant quantum theory, and
R is the contraction parameter from dS and AdS quantum theories to Poincare invariant quantum theory.
4. What Mathematics Is More Pertinent for Describing Nature?
In the preceding sections we discussed symmetries in standard quantum theory which is based on classical mathematics. A belief of the overwhelming majority of scientists is that classical mathematics (involving the notions of infinitely small/large and continuity) is the most general while finite mathematics is something inferior what is used only in special applications. This belief is based on the fact that the history of mankind undoubtedly shows that classical mathematics has demonstrated its power in many areas of science.
The notions of infinitely small, continuity and so forth were proposed by Newton and Leibniz more than 300 years ago and later were substantiated by Cauchy, Weierstrass, and Riemann. At that times people did not know about atoms and elementary particles. On the basis of everyday experience they believed that any macroscopic object can be divided into arbitrarily large number of arbitrarily small parts. However, from the point of view of the present knowledge those notions are problematic. For example, a glass of water contains approximately molecules. We can divide this water by ten, million, and so forth but when we reach the level of atoms and elementary particles the division operation loses its usual meaning and we cannot obtain arbitrarily small parts.
The discovery of atoms and elementary particles indicates that at the very basic level nature is discrete. As a consequence, any description of macroscopic phenomena using continuity and differentiability can be only approximate. For example, in macroscopic physics it is assumed that spatial coordinates and time are continuous measurable variables. However, this is obviously an approximation because coordinates cannot be directly measured with an accuracy better than atomic sizes and time cannot be measured with an accuracy better than s, which is of the order of atomic size over c.
As a consequence, distances less than atomic ones do not have a direct physical meaning and in real life there are no continuous lines and surfaces. As an example, water in the ocean can be described by differential equations of hydrodynamics but this is only an approximation since matter is discrete. Another example is that if we draw a line on a sheet of paper and look at this line by a microscope then we will see that the line is strongly discontinuous because it consists of atoms.
Note that even the name “quantum theory” reflects a belief that nature is quantized, that is, discrete. Nevertheless, when quantum theory was created it was based on classical mathematics developed mainly in the 19th century. One of the greatest successes of the early quantum theory was the discovery that energy levels of the hydrogen atom can be described in the framework of classical mathematics because the Schrödinger differential operator has a discrete spectrum. This and many other successes of quantum theory were treated as indications that all problems of the theory can be solved by using classical mathematics.
As a consequence, even after 90+ years of the existence of quantum theory it is still based on classical mathematics. Although the theory contains divergences and other inconsistencies, physicists persistently try to resolve them in the framework of classical mathematics. This situation is not natural but it is probably a consequence of historical reasons. The founders of quantum theory were highly educated scientists but they used only classical mathematics, and even now discrete and finite mathematics is not a part of standard mathematical education at physics departments. Note that even regardless of applications in physics, classical mathematics has its own foundational problems which cannot be resolved (as follows, in particular, from Gödel’s incompleteness theorems) and therefore the ultimate physical theory cannot be based on that mathematics.
In
Section 2 we have formulated a
Definition that describes when theory
A is more general than theory
B and the latter is a special degenerated case of the former in the formal limit when a finite parameter in the former goes to zero or infinity. In the subsequent sections we prove that the same
Definition applies for the relation between finite quantum theory and finite mathematics on one hand, and standard quantum theory and classical mathematics on the other. Namely, the former theories are based on a ring or field with a finite characteristic
p and the latter theories are special degenerated cases of the former ones in the formal limit
.
In our publications (see e.g., References [
10,
28,
29,
30,
31,
32]) we discussed an approach called Finite Quantum Theory (FQT) where quantum theory is based not on classical but on finite mathematics. Physical states in FQT are elements of a linear space over a finite field or ring, and operators of physical quantities are linear operators in this space. As noted in
Section 2, in standard quantum theory symmetry is defined by a Lie algebra of basic operators acting in the Hilbert space of the system under consideration. Analogously, in FQT symmetry is defined by a Lie algebra of basic operators acting in the space over a finite ring or field of characteristic
p. Following Reference [
33] we prove in
Section 9 that: (a) FQT is more general than standard quantum theory and the latter is a special degenerated case of the former in the formal limit when the characteristic of the field or ring in FQT goes to infinity; (b) finite mathematics itself is more general than classical mathematics and the latter is a special degenerated case of the former in the formal limit when the characteristic of the field or ring in finite mathematics goes to infinity.
9. Why Finite Mathematics Is More General Than Classical One
As noted in
Section 5, finite mathematics is more general than classical mathematics if finite mathematics is more pertinent in applications than classical. Since quantum theory is the most general physical theory (i.e., all other physical theories are special cases of quantum one), the answer to this question depends on whether standard quantum theory based on classical mathematics is the most general or is a special degenerated case of a more general quantum theory.
In classical mathematics, the ring Z is the starting point for introducing the notions of rational, real, complex numbers and so forth. Therefore those notions arise from a degenerated set. Then a question arises whether the fact that is more general than Z implies that finite mathematics is more general than classical one, that is, whether finite mathematics can reproduce all results obtained by applications of classical mathematics. For example, if p is prime then becomes the Galois field , and the results in considerably differ from those in the set Q of rational numbers even when p is very large. In particular, 1/2 in is a very large number .
As proved in
Section 2, standard dS/AdS quantum theories are more general than standard Poincare quantum theory. In the former, quantum states are described by representations of the dS/AdS algebras. To make relations between standard quantum theory and FQT more straightforward, we will modify the commutation relations (
6) by writing them in the form
One might say that these relations are written in units
. However, as noted in
Section 2, quantum theory itself does not involve quantities
ℏ and
c at all, and Equation (
18) indeed does not contain those quantities. The reason for writing the commutation relations in the form (
18) rather than (
6) is that in this case the minimum nonzero value of the angular momentum is 1 instead of 1/2. Therefore the spin of fermions is odd and the spin of bosons is even. This is convenient in FQT where, as noted above, 1/2 is a very large number.
According to principles of quantum theory, from these ten operators one should construct a maximal set S of mutually commuting operators defining independent physical quantities and construct a basis in the representation space such that the basis elements are eigenvectors of the operators from S.
The rotation subalgebra of algebra (
18) is described in every textbook on quantum mechanics. The basis of the subalgebra is
, and with the choice of the commutation relations in the form of Equations (
18) instead of Equation (
2), the commutation relations between those operators operators are
A possible choice of S is where is the Casimir operator of the subalgebra, that is, it commutes with all the operators of the subalgebra. Then any irreducible representation of the subalgebra is described by an integer . The basis elements of the representation space are eigenvectors of the operator K with the eigenvalue and the eigenvectors of the operator with the eigenvalues such that, for a given k, can take values . Therefore all the basis elements are eigenvectors of the operators from S with the eigenvalues belonging to Z.
In Sections 4.1 and 8.2 of Reference [
33] we discussed the dS and AdS cases, respectively and have shown that
Statement 2: For algebra (18) there exist sets S and representations such that basis vectors in the representation spaces are eigenvectors of the operators from S with eigenvalues belonging to Z. Such representations reproduce standard representations of the Poincare algebra in the formal limit. Therefore the remaining problem is whether or not FQT can be a generalization of standard quantum theory where states are described by elements of a separable complex Hilbert spaces
H.
FQT can be defined as a quantum theory where states are elements of a space over a finite ring or field with characteristic
p and operators of physical quantities act in this space. In FQT symmetry can be defined in full analogy with standard quantum theory. In particular, dS and AdS symmetries can be defined such that the commutation relations between basic operators
are the same as in Equation (
18).
Let
x be an element of
H and
be a basis of
H normalized such that the norm of each
is an integer. Then
with any desired accuracy each element of H can be approximated by a finite linear combinationwhere and all the numbers and () are rational. This follows from the known fact that the set of such sums is dense in H.
The next observation is that spaces in standard quantum theory are projective, that is, for any complex number
the elements
x and
describe the same state. This follows from the physical fact that not the probability itself but only ratios of probabilities have a physical meaning. In view of this property, both parts of Equation (
20) can be multiplied by a common denominator of all the numbers
and
. As a result, we have
Statement 3: Each element of H can be approximated by a finite linear combination (20) where all the numbersandbelong to Z.
In the literature it is also considered a version of quantum theory based not on real but on
p-adic numbers (see e.g., the review paper [
45] and references therein). Both, the sets of real and
p-adic numbers are the completions of the set of rational numbers but with respect to different metrics. Therefore the set of rational numbers is dense in both, in the set of real numbers and in the set of
p-adic numbers
. In the
p-adic case, the Hilbert space analog of
H is the space of complex-valued functions
and therefore there is an analog of
Statement 3.
We conclude that Hilbert spaces in standard quantum theory contain a big redundancy of elements. Indeed, although formally the description of states in standard quantum theory involves rational and real numbers, such numbers play only an auxiliary role because with any desired accuracy each state can be described by using only integers. Therefore, as follows from
Definition in
Section 2 and
Statements 1–3,
10. Discussion
In
Section 2 we argue that in quantum theory symmetry is defined by a Lie algebra of basic operators. In the theory of Lie algebras there exist a clear criterion when the Lie algebra
is more general than the Lie algebra
: when
can be obtained from
by contraction. As a consequence, dS and AdS quantum theories are more general than Poincare quantum theory. We note that the same conclusion has been given in the famous Dyson’s paper [
12] where symmetries were treated in terms of Lie groups rather than Lie algebras.
The paper [
12] appeared in 1972 and, in view of Dyson’s results, a question arises of why general theories of elementary particles (QED, electroweak theory and QCD) are still based on Poincare symmetry and not dS or AdS symmetries. Probably a justification is that since the parameter of contraction
R from dS or AdS theories to Poincare one is much greater that sizes of elementary particles, there is no need to use the former symmetries for description of elementary particles.
We believe that this argument is not consistent because usually more general theories shed a new light on standard concepts. For example, as shown in References [
13,
14], in contrast to the situation in Poincare invariant theories, where a particle and its antiparticle are described by different irreducible representations (IRs) of the Poincare algebra (or group), in dS theory a particle and its antiparticle belong to the same IR of the dS algebra. In the formal limit
one IR of the dS algebra splits into two
different IRs of the Poincare algebra for a particle and its antiparticle. Strictly speaking, this implies that in dS theory the very notion of a particle and its antiparticle is only approximate since transitions particle↔antiparticle are not strictly prohibited. As a consequence, in dS theory the electric charge and the baryon and lepton quantum numbers are only approximately conserved. At present they are conserved with a high accuracy. However, one might think that at early stages of the Universe the quantity
R was much less than now and the nonconservation of those quantum numbers was much stronger. This might be a reason of the known phenomenon of baryon asymmetry of the Universe.
Physicists usually understand that physics cannot (and should not) derive that
m/s and
. At the same time they usually believe that physics should derive the value of the cosmological constant
and that the solution of the dark energy problem depends on this value. As noted in
Section 2, the question why the quantities
are as are does not arise since the answer is: because people’s choice is to measure velocities in m/s and angular momenta in
. In the modern system of units, it is postulated that the quantities
are the same at all times. At the same time, as noted in
Section 1 and
Section 2, background space has a clear physical meaning only on classical level while on quantum one transition from dS/AdS symmetries to Poincare symmetry is characterized by the parameter
R which is the coefficient of proportionality between the quantities
and
and has nothing to do with the radius of background space. This parameter
must be finite and, as noted in
Section 2, the question why
R is as is does not arise because people’s choice is to measure distances in meters. Since the modern system of units is based on Poincare invariance, it says nothing on whether
R can change with time. This is the problem of metrology and cosmology but not fundamental physics.
Therefore the quantity
is meaningful only on classical level. As shown in
Section 3, as a consequence of dS symmetry on quantum level, in semiclassical approximation two free bodies have a relative acceleration given by the same expression as in GR if the the radius of dS space equals
R and
. We believe that our result is more important than the result of GR for the following reasons.
In GR there is no restriction on the radius of background space and, for example, the possibility
is not excluded. As noted in
Section 3.1, this possibility is now adopted by majority of physicists and, as a consequence, the results on cosmological acceleration are interpreted as a consequence of the existence of dark energy. However, from the point of view of symmetry on quantum level discussed in the present paper, dS symmetry is more general than Poincare one and there is no freedom in choosing the value of
R. Our result for the cosmological acceleration has been obtained without using dS space, its metric, connection and so forth: it is simply a consequence of dS quantum mechanics of two free bodies and
the calculation does not involve any geometry. The result is more important than the result of GR because any classical result should be a consequence of quantum theory in semiclassical approximation. The result has nothing to do with gravity, existence or nonexistence of dark energy and with the problem whether or not empty space-time should be necessarily flat. Therefore, as noted in
Section 3, the cosmological constant problem and dark energy problem do not arise.
As noted in
Section 3, our conclusion is based on the consideration of the pure mathematical problem: we consider quantum theory where dS symmetry is understood as explained in
Section 2 and then we consider semiclassical approximation in this theory. On the other hand, as noted in
Section 3, there exists a wide literature where standard GR is modified and, as a consequence, the existing data can be explained by using alternatives to standard understanding of dark energy. Therefore the explanation of the of the data is a difficult unsolved problem, and we believe that for solving this problem different approaches should be taken into account.
As argued in
Section 4, at the very general level, quantum theory should not be based on classical mathematics involving the notions of infinitely small/large, continuity, differentiability and so forth. In
Section 5 we give a new look at the problem of potential vs. actual infinity. In classical mathematics the infinite ring of integers
Z is the starting point for introducing the notions of rational, real, complex number and other infinite sets with different cardinalities. However, in
Section 8 we give a
direct proof of
Statement 1 that
Z is a special degenerated case of the ring
in the formal limit
, and the proof does not involve actual infinity. We did not succeed in finding such a proof in the literature and, as noted above, even in standard textbooks on classical mathematics, it is not even posed a problem whether
Z can be treated as a limit of finite sets. As noted in
Section 7, the fact that
Z can be treated as a limit of
in the formal limit
can be proved proceeding from ultraproducts and other sophisticated approaches. However, those approaches involve actual infinity and therefore they cannot be used in the proof that finite mathematics is more general than classical one.
Note also, that the phrase that Z is the ring of characteristic 0 reflects the usual spirit that Z is more general than . In our opinion it is natural to say that Z is the ring of characteristic ∞ because it is a limit of rings of characteristics p when . The characteristic of the ring p is understood such that all operations in the ring are modulo p but operations modulo 0 are meaningless. Usually the characteristic of the ring is defined as the smallest positive number n such that the sum of n units in the ring equals zero if such a number n exists and 0 otherwise. However, this sum can be written as and the equality takes place in any ring.
Legitimacy of the limit of when is problematic because when is replaced by Z which is used as the starting point for constructing classical mathematics, we get classical mathematics which has foundational problems. For example, Gödel’s incompleteness theorems state that no system of axioms can ensure that all facts about natural numbers can be proven and the system of axioms in classical mathematics cannot demonstrate its own consistency. The foundational problems of classical mathematics arise as a consequence of the fact that the number of natural numbers is infinite. On the other hand, since finite mathematics deals only with a finite number of elements, it does not have foundational problems because here every statement can be directly verified, at least in principle.
The efforts of many great mathematicians to resolve foundational problems of classical mathematics have not been successful yet. The philosophy of Cantor, Fraenkel, Gödel, Hilbert, Kronecker, Russell, Zermelo and other great mathematicians was based on macroscopic experience in which the notions of infinitely small, infinitely large, continuity and standard division are natural. However, as noted above, those notions contradict the existence of elementary particles and are not natural in quantum theory. The illusion of continuity arises when one neglects discrete structure of matter.
The above construction has a known historical analogy. For many years people believed that the Earth was flat and infinite, and only after a long period of time they realized that it was finite and curved. It is difficult to notice the curvature dealing only with distances much less than the radius of the curvature. Analogously one might think that the set of numbers describing nature in our Universe has a "curvature" defined by a very large number p but we do not notice it dealing only with numbers much less than p.
As noted in
Section 9, by analogy with standard quantum theory, one can construct a finite quantum theory (FQT) where the space of possible states of the system under consideration is a linear space over a finite ring or field of characteristic
p, and the operators of physical quantities are linear operators in that space. By analogy with standard quantum theory, symmetry in FQT is defined by a Lie algebra of basic operators. In particular, dS or AdS symmetry in FQT means that the structure constants of this Lie algebra is the same as in standard case. Note that in FQT there can be no system of units, no infinitely small/large quantities and no continuity because all physical quantities are elements of a finite ring or field.
In particular, FQT does not contain infinities at all and all operators are automatically well defined. In my discussions with physicists, some of them commented this fact as follows. This is an approach where a cutoff (the characteristic p of the finite ring or field) is introduced from the beginning and for this reason there is nothing strange in the fact that the theory does not have infinities. It has a large number p instead and this number can be practically treated as infinite.
The inconsistency of this argument is clear from the following analogy. It is not correct to say that relativistic theory is simply nonrelativistic one with the cutoff
c for velocities. As a consequence of the fact that
c is finite, relativistic theory considerably differs from nonrelativistic one in several aspects. The difference between finite rings or fields on one hand and usual complex numbers on the other is not only that the former are finite and the latter are infinite. If the set of usual numbers is visualized as a straight line from
to
then the simplest finite ring can be visualized not as a segment of this line but as a circumference (see
Figure 1 in
Section 8). This reflects the fact that in finite mathematics the rules of arithmetic are different and, as a result, FQT has many unusual features which have no analogs in standard theory.
As noted in
Section 5, in abstract mathematics there is no notion that one branch of mathematics is more general than the other. However, as proved in
Section 9, in applications finite mathematics is more pertinent than classical one because FQT is more general than standard quantum theory: the latter is a special degenerated case of the former in the formal limit when the characteristic of the ring or field in the former goes to infinity. Therefore, the problem what branch of mathematics is more general is the problem of physics, not mathematics and, as formulated in
Main Statement, finite mathematics is more general than classical one.
The fact that at the present stage of the Universe
p is a huge number explains why in many cases classical mathematics describes natural phenomena with a very high accuracy. At the same time, as shown in References [
10,
31,
33], the explanation of several phenomena can be given only in the theory where
p is finite.
One of the examples is that in our approach gravity is a manifestation of the fact that
p is finite. In Reference [
33] we have derived the approximate expression for the gravitational constant which depends on
p as
. By comparing this expression with the experimental value we get that
is of the order of
or more, that is,
p is a huge number of the order of
or more. However, since
is “only” of the order of
or more, the existence of
p is observable while in the formal limit
gravity disappears.