Egalitarian-Equivalence and Strategy-Proofness in the Object Allocation Problem with Non-Quasi-Linear Preferences
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Motivation
1.2. Main Result
1.3. Related Literature
1.4. Organization
2. Model
- Money monotonicity. For each and each pair with , we have .
- Desirability of objects. For each and each , we have .
- Possibility of compensation. For each and each , there is a pair such that and .
- Continuity. For each , its upper contour set, , and its lower contour set, , are both closed.
- Egalitarian-equivalence. For each , there is a reference bundle for R such that for each .
- Envy-freeness. For each and each pair , .
- Strategy-proofness. For each , each , and each , .
- Individual rationality. For each and each , .
- No subsidy for losers. For each and each , if , then .
- Efficiency. For each , there is no such that (i) for each , (ii) for some , and (iii) .
- Constrained efficiency. For each , there is no such that (i) for each , (ii) for each , (iii) for some , and (iv) .
- No wastage. For each and each , there is such that .
- Minimal no wastage. For each , there are and such that .
- (ii)
- If a rule f on satisfies efficiency, then it satisfies no wastage.
- (iii)
- If a rule f on satisfies no wastage, then it satisfies minimal no wastage.
- (iv)
- A rule f on satisfies efficiency if and only if it satisfies constrained efficiency and no wastage.
- (v)
- Suppose . A rule f on satisfies minimal no wastage if and only if it satisfies no wastage.
3. The Independent Second-Prices Rule with Variable Constraints
- Step 1:
- A second-price rule for each object is conducted.
- Step 2:
- Each winner of some object(s) in the first step chooses a best bundle among the bundles that he won in the first step.
- Step 3:
- The outcome allocation of the rule is as follows. Each winner in the first step receives the bundle chosen by him in the second step. Each loser in the first step receives no object and pays nothing.
4. Main Result
4.1. Rich Domain
4.2. Constraints
- (i)
- If , then for each and each pair j, , .
- (ii)
- If , then there is such that for each pair i, , .
- (i)
- Let be such that for each and each , . In other words, each agent never has a chance to win an object under the profile of variable constraints . Then, f associated with coincides with the no-trade rule.
- (ii)
- Let . Let be such that for each , for each pair j, , and for each and each , . In other words, agent i can receive an object only if all the other agents’ valuations of the object at coincide with each other, and no other agent has an opportunity to win objects.
- (iii)
- Let . Let be such that for each and each , if for each pair , and otherwise. In words, each agent has an opportunity to win the object a only if all the other agents’ valuations of a at coincide with each other, but it has no access to all the other real objects.
- (iv)
- Let be such that for each and each , if for each pair and each , , and otherwise. In words, each agent has access to all the objects when all the other agents’ valuations of each object coincide with each other, but it has no access to a real object otherwise.
4.3. Main Result
5. Discussion
5.1. Efficiency
- (i)
- A rule on satisfies egalitarian-equivalence, efficiency, strategy-proofness, individual rationality, and no subsidy for losers if and only if it is a generalized Vickrey rule.
- (ii)
- A rule on satisfies egalitarian-equivalence, no wastage, strategy-proofness, individual rationality, and no subsidy for losers if and only if it is a generalized Vikcrey rule.
- (i)
- No rule on satisfies egalitarian-equivalence, efficiency, strategy-proofness, individual rationality, and no subsidy for losers.
- (ii)
- No rule on satisfies egalitarian-equivalence, no wastage, strategy-proofness, individual rationality, and no subsidy for losers.
5.2. Envy-Freeness
6. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A. Preliminaries
Appendix B. Proof of Theorem 1
Appendix B.1. Proof of the “If” Part
- Case 1. .
- Case 2. .
- Case 3. .
Appendix B.2. Proof of the “Only If” Part
- Step 1. We show that for each i and each , , i.e., .
- Step 2. We show that for each , each , and each , if , then for each pair .
- Step 2-1. By egalitarian-equivalence, there is a reference bundle for R such that for each . We show . Let . By , . This impliesThus, . By Step 1, Lemma A9 gives
- Step 2-2. We show that for each , . By contradiction, suppose there is such that . By , . By Step 2-1, . Thus, by , . By , . Thus, by , . This implies . Thus, by , , which contradicts individual rationality.
- Step 2-3. We show that for each and each , . Let and . Suppose by contradiction that . By Lemma A2, . By Step 1, Lemma A8 implies . By Step 2-1, . Thus, . Thus, by ,By egalitarian-equivalence, there is a reference bundle for such that and for each . By Step 1, Lemma A9 gives . Thus, by (A6) and Step 2-2,
- Step 2-4. We show that for each and each , we have . Let and . By Step 2-3, we have .By egalitarian-equivalence, there is a reference bundle for such that and for each , . By Step 1, Lemma A9 implies . By Step 1, Lemma A8 gives . Thus,
- Step 2-5. Let . Let be a price vector such that and for each . By Step 1 and , Lemma A7 implies .By Step 2-3,By and Lemma A10, . Thus, is well-defined, and . Note that .9
- Step 3. We show that for each , each , and each , . Let , , and . If , then by Lemma A2, . Thus, assume .
- Step 4. We show that f is an independent second-prices rule with variable constraints. Let and . Let be a price vector such that for each , . By Step 3, for each , . By Lemma A6, . Furthermore, . Thus, by Lemma A1 and Step 1, f is an independent second-prices rule with variable constraints associated with .
- Step 5. Now, we complete the proof of Theorem 1. By Step 4, f is an independent second-prices rule with variable constraints associated with . Thus, we finally show that it respects the valuation coincidence.
Appendix C. Proof of Propositions
Appendix C.1. Proof of Proposition 5
Appendix C.2. Proof of Proposition 6
- Case 1. .
- Case 2. .
Appendix C.3. Proof of Proposition 7
1 | |
2 | For the comprehensive survey on fair allocation theory, see [8] |
3 | A rule on is a generalized Vickrey rule if it holds that for each , , and for each , . |
4 | By and , in this case it must hold that . |
5 | Note that all Propositions 1–3 follow from Theorem 1. The purpose of the three propositions in Section 4.2 was to clarify the motivation of the respecting the valuation coincidence condition. |
6 | For the formal definition of the minimum price Warlasian see, for example, Morimoto and Serizawa [6] |
7 | In the companion paper [20], motivated by the observation that real-life bidders usually have neither the full access to the outcomes of auctions nor full confidence that the published data are correct, we propose a new property of fairness that we call obvious envy-freeness. It extends envy-freeness to the agents who has only partial access to or partial confidence in the other agents’ outcome bundles. In Shinozaki [20], we establish that the independent second-prices rule with variable reserve prices is the only rule satisfying obvious envy-freeness, strategy-proofness, individual rationality, and no subsidy for losers. |
8 | We are grateful to an anonymous referee for suggesting such interesting directions of future research. |
9 | Indeed, suppose by contradiction that . Then, there is such that . By Step 1, Lemma A8 implies . However, this contradicts since and . |
References
- Pazner, E.A.; Shmeidler, D. Egalitarian equivalent allocations: A new concept of economic equity. Q. J. Econ. 1978, 92, 671–687. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kazumura, T.; Mishra, D.; Serizawa, S. Strategy-proof multi-object mechanism design: Ex-post revenue maximization with non-quasilinear preferences. J. Econ. Theory 2020, 188, 105036. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Holmström, B. Groves’ sheme on restricted domains. Econometrica 1979, 47, 1137–1144. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Saitoh, H.; Serizawa, S. Vickrey allocation rule with income effect. Econ. Theory 2008, 35, 391–401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sakai, T. Second price auctions on general preference domains: Two characteriations. Econ. Theory 2008, 37, 347–356. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Morimoto, S.; Serizawa, S. Strategy-proofness and efficiency with non-quasi-linear preferences: A characterization of minimum price Warlasian rule. Theor. Econ. 2015, 10, 445–487. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Demange, G.; Gale, D. The strategy structure of two-sided matching markets. Econometrica 1985, 53, 873–888. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thomson, W. Fair allocation rules. In Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare; Arrow, K., Sen, A., Suzumura, K., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2011; pp. 393–506. [Google Scholar]
- Ohseto, S. Characterizations of strategy-proof and fair mechanisms for allocating indivisible goods. Econ. Theory 2006, 29, 111–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Svensson, L.G. Coalitional strategy-proofness and fairness. Econ. Theory 2009, 40, 227–245. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Andersson, T.; Ehlers, L.; Svensson, L.G. Budget balance, fairness, and minimal manipulability. Theor. Econ. 2014, 9, 753–777. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yengin, D. No-envy and egalitarian-equivalence under multi-object-demand for heterogeneous objects. Soc. Choice Welf. 2017, 48, 81–180. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yengin, D. Egalitarian-equivalent Groves mechanisms in the allocation of heterogeneous objects. Soc. Choice Welf. 2012, 38, 137–160. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ohseto, S. Implementing egalitarian-equivalent allocation of indivisible goods on restricted domains. Econ. Theory 2004, 23, 659–670. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chun, Y.; Mitra, M.; Mutuswami, S. Egalitarian equivalence and strategyproofness in the queueing problem. Econ. Theory 2014, 56, 425–442. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hayashi, T. Egalitarian Equivalence and Implementability Imply Equal Division. Working Paper. 2022. Available online: https://drive.google.com/file/d/12bze9XaLtFM_MSd3uG-stRzgKElcMjS6/view (accessed on 12 November 2022).
- Ashlagi, I.; Serizawa, S. Characterizing Vickrey allocation rule by anonymity. Soc. Choice Welf. 2012, 38, 531–542. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Foley, D. Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Econ. Essays 1967, 7, 45–98. [Google Scholar]
- Thomson, W. On the non existence of envy-free and egalitarian-equivalent allocations in economies with indivisiblities. Econ. Lett. 1990, 34, 227–229. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shinozaki, H. Obviously fair object allocation with money. Graduate School of Economics, Osaka University, 1-7 Machikaneyama, Toyonaka, Osaka, Japan. 2022; manuscript in preparation. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Shinozaki, H. Egalitarian-Equivalence and Strategy-Proofness in the Object Allocation Problem with Non-Quasi-Linear Preferences. Games 2022, 13, 75. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13060075
Shinozaki H. Egalitarian-Equivalence and Strategy-Proofness in the Object Allocation Problem with Non-Quasi-Linear Preferences. Games. 2022; 13(6):75. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13060075
Chicago/Turabian StyleShinozaki, Hiroki. 2022. "Egalitarian-Equivalence and Strategy-Proofness in the Object Allocation Problem with Non-Quasi-Linear Preferences" Games 13, no. 6: 75. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13060075
APA StyleShinozaki, H. (2022). Egalitarian-Equivalence and Strategy-Proofness in the Object Allocation Problem with Non-Quasi-Linear Preferences. Games, 13(6), 75. https://doi.org/10.3390/g13060075