Introduction
Composition is the “science of combination” and can be simply defined as the arrangement of elements to create a painting (
Poore, 2008) and thus create a focal point of compositional order (
Topper, 2001). However, the concept of composition is much more complex (
Duro, 2003;
Puttfarken, 2000) than simple arrangement and includes aspects such as the spatial relationship of elements relating to aesthetic quality (
Waichulis, 2016) and addresses principles such as balance (
Tatarkiewicz, 1980), movement, colour and contrast amongst others. The notion of composition has also changed over time (see Puutfarken, 2000) and encompasses perspective and geometrical shapes and placement of bodies and even includes knowledge and sensitivity of the physical position of the original artwork (
Topper, 2001). The premise of the current study is based on the fact that every element in a picture has the potential to attract attention (
Poore, 1976) and the overarching observation of
Yarbus (
1967) that “composition is the means whereby the artist to some extent may compel the viewer to perceive what is portrayed in the picture”. The placement and arrangement of the elements in the picture “can be recognised only by shifting the gaze from place to place in a specific order and time” (
Francuz et al., 2018). It may thus be inferred that the intention of the artist is to lead the eye of the viewer along a chosen path – the placed elements essentially becoming the salient features that attract the gaze of the viewer and even cause the viewer to focus on these elements in a certain order by using for example the compositional design element of movement, thus creating what will be referred to in this paper as the compositional line. The goal of the artist is thus to ensure that the viewer will see the elements in the order planned by the artist (
Graham, 1970). All these assertions and the premise of the study rests on the analyses of Diederot who proposed that there is an explicit link between eye movements and composition, suggesting that the composition is an “instruction to the eye, a path which the gaze follows in a certain order” (as cited in
Rosenberg and Klein, 2015). Such composition could be considered analogous to bottom-up processing (in other words, visual selection that is automatically conducted based on features that are present in the scene (
Theeuwes, 2010)) in the sense that salient features are focused on, the difference here being that the order of fixation and salient elements are preplanned by the artist (as opposed to voluntary selection performed under control of the viewer, which is referred to as top-down selection (
Theeuwes, 2010)). For example, a flowing river may create the illusion of movement, causing the eye to follow the flow of the river towards the next salient feature of the painting.
Apart from the use of elements to guide the eye, other elements can be placed strategically to cause the viewer to fixate on those elements; the guiding elements then lead the eye in order to achieve the order of fixations as desired by the artist.
Therefore, composition could be an influencing factor for visual selection during the entire observation period or at the very least during the initial sweep of the painting while the viewer becomes acquainted with the elements and the scene as a whole. The premise of this study is to determine whether composition may be the overriding factor in the initial viewing behaviour of the artwork, whereafter it is possible that top-down and bottom-up processes of visual selection are employed. Regardless of whether there is a task at hand or not, if the composition is successful in leading the eye, the initial viewing of the painting should be sufficient to guide the eye along the compositional line.
Background
As far back as 1935,
Buswell (
1935) discovered that gaze patterns between trained and untrained viewers of art did not differ significantly but that individuals tended to fixate on the same spatial locations but not necessarily in the same temporal order. Similar to the seminal work of
Yarbus (
1967), later confirmed by
DeAngelus and Pelz (
2009), he discovered that the task of the viewer changes the gaze pattern significantly. Furthermore
Molnar (
1965,
1981) suggests that gaze patterns are governed by whether the viewer is looking at the picture for pleasure or to seek knowledge.
When merely looking at the painting, whether it be in a museum, book or computer, this is considered to be looking for pleasure and devoid of any task that may influence the viewing pattern – in this instance it may be the composition that is the compelling influential factor.
A number of studies have focused on this and found that the compositional design had an influence on the gaze patterns of the trained viewers – suggesting in the words of the authors that “beauty is less in the eye and more in the mind of the beholder” (Nodine and Locher, 1993). Eye movements of viewers also differ based on preference and balance, that is, gaze patterns of viewers who preferred a balanced composition in paintings differed from those who preferred an altered or unbalanced composition. When a viewer found a painting more attractive than an alternative, where attractiveness is expressed as a sense of balance in the composition, they exhibited shorter fixations and accuracy of painting evaluation correlated with fixation duration and dwell time (
Francuz et al., 2018). However, experts and naïve art viewers can tend to focus on different elements in the painting (Pihko, 2011).
An informal study by
Gurney (
2009) presents some preliminary findings on eye-tracking as it relates to composition. Among these was the conclusion that placing an element in the so-called golden section - an aesthetically pleasing proportioning of the artwork as calculated by the golden ratio (
Esaak, 2013) - does not guarantee that it will draw the attention of the viewer. However, an attention- getting element, such as a face, will attract attention regardless of its position. Specifically, when painting subjects engaged in social interaction, faces attract attention while individual actions generated attention on individual body parts (
Villani, et al., 2015). This is also found when adolescents look at paintings as they display high visual attention on the human body, and give priority to elements in a painting that evoke movement or action (Savazzi, et al., 2014). The finding that bodies or faces attract attention is in accordance with previous studies that found that viewers can spend as much as 40% of viewing time on the eye region when viewing facial photographs (Janik, Wellens, Goldberg and Dell’Osso, 1978) and that faces do indeed attract attention (Cerf, Frady and Kock, 2009). Therefore, this phenomenon is not exclusive to paintings nor, as concluded, is it as a consequence of placement, and is attributed to the fact that a person will always attempt to find a body or a face in an image and that eyes are a prominent feature of a face (
Elkins, 1996;
Bergh and Beelders, 2014). Using the same reasoning, it can be concluded that other attention-getting elements will attract attention regardless of placement and simply because a human seeks such elements in an image or scene. A second observation that was made is that no two people follow the exact same scanpath in a painting and that while the composition does not control the scanpath, it does exert an influence over the scanpath (
Gurney, 2009).
Rosenberg and Klein (
2015) confirmed these findings, suggesting that eyes do not follow the compositional line nor do viewers scan paintings in any controlled way – that is, neither from top to bottom or left to right. There do, however, tend to be areas of interest in paintings that attract the attention of most viewers at some point (
Rosenberg and Klein, 2015). Most recently,
Sancarlo et al. (
2020) found that the gaze does follow the compositional line, basing their findings on cumulative saccades instead of the gaze path, which is a different means of analysis to previous studies. Therefore, the current study can serve to formalise these findings or perhaps to discount the preliminary conclusions drawn.
In a previous study (Mannan, Ruddock and Wooding, 1995), eye movements within a short and prolonged period were examined. Results indicated that over a brief period, specifically 1.5 seconds, there was high similarity between how participants looked at images - but that for a longer period (3 seconds), the similarity decreases. Thus, spatial features, and perhaps the composition, of the image guide the eye during short presentations of the image.
In a recent study similar to the current study, paintings where the compositional line was known were used to determine whether the gaze indeed followed these lines. Results indicated that focal points were successful in attracting and keeping attention, but the intended entry and exit points were not used. Furthermore, the compositional line was not closely followed and the compositional elements did not exert a significant influence over eye movements (
Kirtley, 2018).
Interestingly, children rely on bottom-up processing when free-viewing a painting, but revert to top-down processing when they view the painting again after being given background information. In contrast, adults rely on top-down processing both during free viewing and after being given background information on the painting (
Walker et al., 2017). Under conditions where a task has been given, specifically that participants must rate the painting or give a description thereof, indicated that an initial global (bottom-up) exploration is followed by a more focused (top-down) exploration (
Hristova and Grinberg, 2011). These findings support the premise of this study in that, regardless of the task at hand, a successful compositional line should dominate eye movements during initial viewing.
Other studies on eye-tracking and art that do not explicitly look at composition have also been conducted. For example, gaze patterns differ based on the physical properties of the painting and whether they are viewed in realistic circumstances, such as in a museum, or on-screen (Estrada-Gonzalez, East, Garbutt and Spehar, 2020). Furthermore, the number of fixations and scanpath length increase while fixation duration decreases as the painting’s level of abstraction increases (
Pihko et al., 2011). Both higher-level and lower-level tasks result in viewers first scanning a whole painting, followed by smaller local fixations (
Wallraven et al., 2009). First fixation duration, total viewing time and number of fixations are all more when viewing a restored painting than the same unrestored painting (Locher, Tinio and Krupinski, 2020).
Conceptual-theoretical framework
In this article, the analysis of the eye-tracking experiment fits into the overall framework of Cognitive Linguistics as presented in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014) and is similarly enriched by the notion of Active Vision.
Cognitive Linguistics is a branch of Linguistics and Cognitive Science that aims to account for language in accordance with the latest knowledge about the human mind, while cultural and contextual differences are also taken into consideration (
Barcelona, 2000:2).
Cognitive Linguistics is ‘cognitive’ in the sense that, “insofar as possible, language is characterised in terms of other, more fundamental phenomena” such as memory, perception, attention and imagery (
Langacker, 2016: 467).
The advantages of the notion of Active Vision (
Findlay and Gilchrist, 2003) for this analysis are that it integrates seeing and looking, takes the role of eye movements into account and gives prominence to visual attention as a cognitive occurrence in “understanding perception as a dynamic process” (
Ware, 2008: ix).
The analysis in this article is based on the said model in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014) together with further elaboration concerning it (
Bergh in press a,
in press b;
Bergh and Beelders 2017; Miller-Naudé, Beelders, Naudé and Bergh, 2017) and as proposed by
Gärdenfors (
2015), and
Croft and Cruse (
2004). As was pointed out in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014:16), conventional metaphors are usually automatic, unconscious mappings in ordinary language (“often as a result of visual perception”) and can be extended creatively (
Lakoff and Turner, 1989:67-72). In Cognitive Linguistics, linguistic constructions such as words or sentences are complex cognitive models with two dimensions characterising the parameters of form and meaning (
Lakoff, 1987). Given this association, they are symbolic structures that should furthermore be regarded on a continuum with other, non-linguistic constructions (
Langacker, 1987:60;76). As emphasised in
Bergh (
in press b), all manifestations and aspects of language are central to Cognitive Science research. Conceptual metaphors can also be expressed non-verbally or can motivate behaviour in terms of, say, decision-making (
Lakoff and Johnson, 2003:156-158;
Lakoff and Turner, 1989:49-67;
Rossouw, 2017).
The latter point concerns especially the artists Sartore, Osner and Van der Merwe discussed below in relation to reference points in their creative way of working, which then requires them and their work to be seen in the context of research on branding (Bergh, Jordaan, Lombard, Naudé and Van Zyl, 2017; Bergh, Lombard and Van Zyl, 2013). Both the relationship with reference points and that with branding ties in with their artistic creativity in a space-time context (
Van der Merwe, 2005), which is the main focus of Cognitive Linguistics, here then as posited in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014).
Within the approach in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014), the most basic, overarching metaphors have “image schemas” such as verticality and centre-periphery as their input or source domain (
Langacker, 1993:3).
Besides image-schematic representation, elementary structural relations also include a “profile” and a “trajector- landmark” structure (
Lakoff and Johnson, 1999:31), which in turn, link to attentional tuning and pop-out phenomena (
Ware, 2008) and human construal, which include prominence (
Langacker, 1992:288). “Profiling”, that is, when a substructure is chosen for attentional focus in an expression, represents one kind of prominence (
Taylor, 2002:198). Another kind of prominence is known as the “salience of relational participants” – where the main figure in a scene is the relational trajector and a salient, supporting figure, the landmark, brings about the trajector (
Langacker, 1987,
1992). Related to this is
Langacker’s (
1993:5, 35) “reference-point phenomenon”, a general and basic cognitive ability that may be present in most linguistic phenomena. The way in which reference points, mental spaces and conceptual blending are related and reveals motion in the relevant model is explained in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014). Essentially, a notion must first be activated as a suitable reference point (
Bergh and Beelders, 2014:17), which then facilitates movement along a reference point path. Cognitive salience or characterisation of another entity serves as qualification of a notion as a reference point and the human body is an apt example of a reference point in this regard (
Langacker, 1993: 9, 13).
Composition within
Bergh and Beelders (
2014) relates to multimodality; is included in conceptual blending; and for linguistic units is based on
Langacker’s (
1987,
2008) Cognitive Grammar views.
Langacker (
2008:60) considers composition as “focussing that is inherent in the meanings of individual expressions”, which are mostly “symbolically complex, being assembled out of smaller symbolic components to form composite symbolic structures”. For example,
art and
–ist are symbolic components of the composite expression
artist.
Composite expressions exhibit varying degrees of analysability; that is, they vary in how salient the component structures are in relation to the composite conception, “and how strongly they contribute to its emergence” (
Langacker, 2008: 61). The way in which an expression’s composite meaning relates to those of its components (“at successive levels of organisation”) is called its
compositional path - which is often shown via a tree diagram in linguistics. This means that an expression’s meaning resides in its composite semantic structure together with its compositional path in a foreground/background relationship.
Langacker (
2008:61) explains it as follows: “While the composite conception is primary, it is viewed against the background of the component semantic structures at all lower levels. How strongly a particular component contributes to this secondary dimension of meaning depends on its proximity to the composite structure along the compositional path as well as the expression’s degree of analysability at the various levels.”
Langacker (
2008:61-62) gives three reasons for defining an expression’s meaning as including its compositional path. Firstly, it is “a very real dimension of conceptual organisation”. Secondly, it aids in explaining the general observation that “no two expressions are exactly the same in meaning”. Thirdly, “by acknowledging the semantic contribution of compositional paths, we can also explain why expressions that are
semantically anomalous – having no coherent composite structure – nonetheless seem meaningful”.
Langacker (
2008:66-72) uses the terms
prominence and
salience interchangeably, and – like other aspects of construal, as conceptual phenomena. Even at the conceptual level, though, “the objects of our mental universe have no inherent status as profile, trajector, or landmark. These pertain specifically to the conceptualizations evoked as the meanings of linguistic expressions. How prominent a particular entity is – whether it functions as profile, trajector, landmark, or none of the above - depends on the construal imposed by the linguistic elements employed, in accordance with their conventional semantic values. … each structure in a symbolic assembly makes its own assignment of focus, so an entity focused in one structure need not have comparable salience in another” (
Langacker, 2008:73).
Croft and Cruse (
2004) provide a useful overview of linguistic construal operations as instances of general cognitive processes. The main categories are: Attention/salience; Judgement/comparison (including metaphor); Perspective/situatedness (including vantage point, orientation and deixis; and Constitution/Gestalt (including topological/geometric schematization and scale). Two aspects are of specific importance to this article, namely firstly that
Croft and Cruse (
2004:46) point out that attention is a well-known basic phenomenon in cognitive linguistics. As such, it focusses on the human cognitive ability involved, but “there are also natural properties of phenomena in the perceived world that lend themselves to being attended to by human beings, and these properties are said to enhance those phenomena’s
salience to human beings’ attention” and so brings about a salient-less salient continuum that relates to Langacker’s varying saliency in an overall composite structure, as mentioned earlier. An example in this regard may be a footpath. Secondly,
Croft and Cruse’s (
2004:60) explanation of ‘here’ as opposed to ‘there’ in that “deictic elements display two layers of conceptualization: one relative to the situatedness of the speech act participants, and another construal that displaces the actual situatedness of the interlocutors to another time and place”.
One of the advantages of the framework in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014) for this article regarding composition is that nested in multimodality and semiotics, it considers colour and movement to be semiotic modes. Because time and space are focus areas of Cognitive Linguistics (
Langacker, 1987), height, verticality, direction of movement and associated grammatical elements such as prepositions are key aspects analysed within this framework, but – as was pointed out earlier above, such linguistic symbolic structures should furthermore be regarded on a continuum with other, non-linguistic constructions (
Langacker, 1987: 60; 76). At such an interface, Ware (2008 in
Bergh and Beelders, 2014) considers conceptual metaphors to provide a common semantic layer between verbal and visual language. Conceptual path metaphors would seem to be relevant for the analysis in this article – given the various types of paths at issue - yet most paths in this article do not represent conventional metaphors. Nevertheless, elements involved in motion along paths – such as the route - are generally relevant to the analysis based on proposals that involve pre- linguistic image schemas that structure general patters of human experience.
In considering motion along paths, and from a Cognitive Linguistics geometry perspective,
Gärdenfors (
2015:27) highlights
endpoint focus as a special case of profiling. Such a disposition could affect saliency - in that the destination is a goal.
Gärdenfors (
2015:27-28) explains that endpoint focus can be applied to spatial phenomena (such as when a speaker’s inner gaze results in a fictive motion over a bridge) as well as processes (as in
The movie is over, where the movie “is construed as an extended event that creates a path in time”).
For the purposes of this article, the focus is on salience – specifically then also in terms of how it relates to what may be potentially problematic in the analysis concerning points in an intended composition.
In Cognitive Linguistics, much in language are considered to be “a matter of degree”; such indistinct boundaries (
Langacker, 1987:14) can be dealt with optimally on continua. This also applies to saliency, which is considered to be relative.
Discussion
In general, it could be said that the loci similarity was higher than the sequencing similarity, which indicated that participants looked at the same AOIs, which is to be expected, but in a different order. This confirms the oringinal findings of
Buswell (
1935) who found spatial fixation order was similar but differed in temporal order. Thus, the path constructed by the artist is not followed in the order intended by the artist. This confirms the finding of previous studies that showed that scanpaths vary according to the viewer (
Quiroga and Pedreira, 2011;
Zangemeister and Privitera, 2013). These studies did, however, not account for composition. The informal study on composition indicated that placement of an element in the golden section does not guarantee that a viewer will look at the element. Since the current study did not take the golden section into account, it is difficult to determine whether this finding was confirmed or not. It can, however, be confirmed that similar to
Gurney (
2009), the intention of the artist as constructed by the composition (the golden section being an element of composition), plays a part in the scanpath of the viewer, but is not necessarily the overriding factor.
Since the sequencing similarity is low, but the loci similarity high, it would be beneficial to determine if any part of the expected sequence was present in the actual scanpaths. This would allow for determination on whether the guiding elements are successful, either in reverse order or dependent on where the person started looking at the painting. Future analysis could address this question that arises from the findings.
The same level of correlation was seen with comparison with the randomly generated scanpaths. In terms of loci similarity, all differed significantly from the random model for both the full scanpaths and the dwell-based scanpaths. This indicates a significant difference in terms of the AOIs that were viewed by the participants and those predicted by the model based on their saliency. The main reason for this could be attributed to the fact that more AOIs were identified and visited than were predicted by the saliency model, thus leading to a significant difference between the metrics. Furthermore, dwell-based scanpaths often had a higher similarity index than the full scanpath, thus indicating that there was a high incidence of successive fixations within a single AOI. This does not negatively impact on the success of the composition as the AOI holds the attention of the viewer as desired by the artist. In some instances, the surface area of the AOI could play a role as multiple fixations may be required to fixate on standout elements within a single AOI, such as with the branch of the tree. For each of the paintings, there was a significant difference between the actual-expected and random-expected indices, indicating that there was a significant difference between these paths.
This could be indicative of the saliency model simply evaluating the prominence of elements, whereas the expected scanpath is constructed using prominent elements in the order that the intended guiding elements dictate. Similarly, this could explain the significant differences between the actual-expected and actual-random indices. Once again, the importance of integrating the salient - less salient continuum into our analysis.
Focal points succeeded in drawing the initial attention of the viewer and were, moreover, successful in drawing the gaze a number of times. Similarity indices verified that the composition was successful in terms of positional similarity, but that the ordering of fixations differed greatly. This finding can be validated in terms of our proposals regarding reference points, but moreover and also at a different level concerning the way reference points fits into the overall model of complex metaphors (
Bergh and Beelders, 2014) that can also guide behaviour and decisions reached by artists about their creative process.
Focus and ordering can thus vary for viewers as well as artists.
For viewers, the first reference point on a path can be the endpoint or destination, or a picnic spot en route. Alternatively, because the journey may look dangerous, the viewer may decide not to take a particular path.
In turn, for the photographer
Sartore (
2016), for example, the photograph is the first reference point in that a picture of a scene is taken at the starting point (
Sartore, 2016). In contrast, South African landscape artist Strijdom Van der Merwe (in
Van Lill, 2019) considers the photograph of a scene to be the final, documenting reference point.
South African art photographer Martin
Osner (
2017) does not distinguish between art and photography, yet points out that you are not required to be an artist to be able to take an effective picture with a camera:
“The camera does not record what the eye sees – in contrast to what we expect. Focus, depth contrast, colour and lens compression change how we see the world.
“A photograph is a recording of the moment. Photography is a mechanical, technical instrument in the hands of a creative artist. But, the system is not perfect, and it is in this that lie the creative art process. If the camera is purely used in the way that it is been designed [as a perfect system], things can get quite boring. This is what makes photography so interesting. The camera is another tool on the work bench, used variously in the creative process. Knowing what to do and applying it [is the art]. The camera is just a modern inclusion in the history of art. Photography is not perfect; yet it is in this context of inconsistency that art can be realized.”
As was pointed out earlier in the analysis of Painting 1, viewers did search for the artist’s name, therefore branding does play a role in viewing a work of art. In proposing the Art Creation Continuum below in this regard, our thinking is founded in the reasoning above together with the following points made by Strijdom van der Merwe (in
Van Lill, 2019):
- □
Moments – Art is not required to last – what happens in a few present moments can be documented with a photograph. The experience is more important than the work of art.
- □
Art creation – The landscape is not imitated; material from the landscape is simply selected, used and arranged in the work of art. Personal, intimate experience with the landscape is captured in art creation. Often far away from other people, in nature. An artist is born to bring that which is deeply innate to the fore.
- □
Trust – with nature must be built. Landscape art creation is unpredictable in terms of time (of day), space, creation, productivity and complications such as wind and ebb and flow. It is necessary to clear the mind to capture what is seen and to create a work of art that fits the moment experienced in relation to nature as focus; harmony, not ego. Everything needed is in nature – colour, texture, designs.
- □
Documentation – of the work of art as a photograph to bring it to viewers, audiences and potential buyers.
Based on these points and after the analogy of our 2013 continuum in the context of visual art (cf. Bergh, Lombard & Van Zyl, 2013:31):
![Jemr 13 00019 i001]()
and in keeping with the model in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014), and following the verbal preamble (Bergh and Beelders 2019), we propose the following Art Creation Continuum:
Figure 5.
Art Creation Continuum.
Figure 5.
Art Creation Continuum.
This continuum sees personal art creation together with art in the competitive business sector on a spectrum instead of as a binary division. Established composition may play a role in especially designing and conveying clear messages and lines when vital, whereas other forms of art may capture personal, private or sacred meaning. In building trust with nature currently, careful consideration and renewed respect in the face of climate change is essential in this treasured process.
Essentially, the continuum reveals indistinct boundaries among the categories personal-personal art creation, personal branding, public relations and commercial marketing. Predictability, consistency and chaos-order fill the in-between spaces, as the process need not always complete the full course.
Personal-personal art creation is most private and sacred in selecting compositional components and elements. This means that visibility increases from this category leftwards on the spectrum.
Three general observations about paths (
Joubert, 2020) illuminate the positions of artists as well as viewers on the Art Creation Continuum; namely, that no road simply dwindles somewhere; all roads also originate somewhere; and at a given point, a person joins an existing road. As in
Bergh and Beelders (
2017), the continuum enables the visualisation of movement between the points on the spectrum. The established artists and photographers have revealed their preferred creative journey and are differentiated together with their genres in terms of the direction of their travelling, although they are bound by interfaces such as art, landscapes, photographic documentation and simplicity in their approaches.
Osner (
2020a), for instance, reasons that “simplicity is most often key … and will always stand the test of time, and can be achieved” in various genres. “… when given a very busy composition to look at, instead of taking our time and working through each focus point of information, most of us would choose to ignore the whole photograph and just move on. I think this again is because we are continually bombarded by so much visual information on a second to second basis that we very often choose not to look at everything, again just so that we can cope”. The viewing paths of observers that join the continuum path at some point may be unknown (until revealed by eye-tracking, for example) or also confidential in being personal, personal art (re)creation, but do vary in direction – as shown by our results.
The viewers’ connection with the artist is especially through personal branding. From our stance, the viewers’ search for the artist’s signature is more than the link between text and pictures or an indication of the salience of written language, but a manifestation of a language user’s knowledge of conventions in a usage-based context endorsed by Cognitive Linguistics, as exemplified in
Bergh (
in press a). In the current environment, potential art and art photography buyers are recommended to invest in a reputable artist’s work, because quality, consistency and experience count, and to do research on the artist’s reputation, “as there is no place to hide in today’s digital society with social media and online reviews” (
Osner, 2020b).
That much in language is a matter of degree on a continuum, “is perhaps unfortunate from the analytical standpoint – discrete entities are easier to manipulate, require simpler descriptive tools, lend themselves to stronger claims, and yield aesthetically more pleasing analyses” (
Langacker, 1987:14). The continuum does, however, capture the actual complexity of the data and analysis – and conclusions such as that of
Sartore (
2016) that, “Composition (looking and thinking and deciding what you want to say with your picture and how to provide order to chaos) is the hardest part of photography”.
In the context of art creation, the continuum as confirmation of the claim that, “Because something can be salient in many different ways, describing it as such is not an adequate characterisation but only a starting point for analysis” (
Langacker, 2008:66). This confirmation corroborates and enforces the proposals in
Bergh and Beelders (
2014) in terms of which salience serves as a starting point of a reference point path in a viewing path, but in this article especially as a starting point of a reference point path where an image schema (such as motion along a path) combines with a conceptual archetype (such as the use of an instrument, part-whole relationships and the natural properties of phenomena) to form complex metaphors such as ART CREATION IS A JOURNEY.
This complex metaphor captures the conclusion that for this study and in terms of our Art Creation Continuum, a mega metaphor after the analogy of
Bergh (
2016) and to some extent
Rossouw (
2017) captures the overall paths to composition in the paintings concerned. As was pointed out earlier, several of the paths in our exposition are not profiled in a figurative sense, but rather technical, cognitive scientific or natural paths.
Langacker’s view mentioned above that something can be salient in many ways and that salience should therefore be merely the starting point of the analysis also corroborates our findings presented in this article on the role of composition in viewing landscape art. The Cognitive Linguistic view of relative salience is relevant in analysing especially the viewing patterns of Painting 3, but at a different level, seeing salience merely as the starting point in the analysis of the compositional line or path may reveal a further interface between visual and verbal language use - in terms of how the composite conception is viewed against the background of semantic structure at all lower levels. For example,
Osner (
2020a) explains that Landscapes can “evoke emotion and stimulate memories of places once visited” … and that “most great compositions are achieved though simplicity. It has as much to do with what we choose to leave out … than what we decide to include. By removing elements in a composition, we create mystery and interest. Success is achieved by introducing the story and letting the viewer complete it using their imagination”. Such aspects related to “fundamental phenomena” (
Langacker, 2016: 467) may then enhance the conceptual metaphor semantic layer that
Ware (
2008) identifies between visual and verbal language. From a different angle, a Cognitive Linguistics analysis may then endorse the way in which variable top- down processing of guiding elements follow the initial general identification of salient elements in the compositional line in an eye-tracking study of landscape paintings.
Conclusion
The aim of the study was to determine whether composition does in fact lead the eye of a viewer along the intended path. Viewing artwork is similar to scene selection and could therefore be subject to the same visual behaviour in terms of top-down and bottom-up processes. However, the supposition was that, due to the intended composition of the artwork, it is plausible to assume that the initial sweep of the artwork could be governed by the guidance of this composition. Thereafter, the usual gaze behaviour may take precedence. For the purposes of this paper, it was first investigated whether the composition does in fact guide the eye in any way when no specific task is given to the viewer.
The results indicate that the composition is effective in leading the eye to a large degree, generally averaging higher than 50% similarity in terms of location. This result was seen for both comparison between actual- and expected-scanpaths and between participants, more often in the dwell-based scanpaths. However, the eye did not necessarily follow in the order or direction specified. Therefore, the standout elements are successful, but the guiding elements less so. Further analysis could reveal whether the order of fixation is reversed or is present in some way to determine more definitely whether the guiding elements are successful. The eye may start at an AOI not originally intended as the first AOI, but thereafter the gaze may settle into the intended path from that point. Therefore, the intended sequence may be present somewhere within the scanpath or be reversed in some way. Analysis of this kind will also give more clarity on whether it is indeed the composition, guiding elements included, which govern gaze behaviour or whether the observed phenomenon of focusing on the standout elements is simply natural bottom-up selection. If the guiding elements are successful, then the intended sequence would appear in some form in the actual scanpath. Conversely, if it is purely natural bottom-up selection, then there may be large differences in the order in which the AOIs are visited. Comparison with a random scanpath indicated the same tendencies, namely low sequential similarity but high loci similarity indicating that the predicted AOIs were similar to the visited AOIs but, as in the case of the expected path, the order of visits to the AOI differed.
It could therefore be concluded that the composition is mostly successful in leading the eye of the viewer around the elements of the painting, albeit in varying order or direction. This strengthens prior findings (
Gurney, 2009) that composition does influence the scanpath, but does not dictate the scanpath of the viewer. The results are similar to those of
Kirtley (
2018), confirming that focal points attract and keep attention but that the entry and exit points are largely not used as intended. Furthermore, it confirms that the compositional line guided the eye but did not dictate either order or direction. If successful, the composition could result in the eyes repeating the scanpath as constructed by the artist.
The next stage of the study would be to determine whether the guiding elements are successful, followed by an analysis on whether tasks influence this initial gaze behaviour in any way or whether top-down processes only appear once the viewer has become familiar with the composition and layout of the artwork. Factors such as prior knowledge and preference were not evaluated and could perhaps be included in further studies in order to determine whether there is interaction between these factors and the composition of the painting. Furthermore, it could be beneficial to analyse multiple viewings of the same painting in order to determine whether the observed patterns repeat with subsequent viewings.
The overall conclusion of this article is that when the eye- tracking results and statistical analyses are complemented by insights from the Cognitive Linguistics framework, apparent inconsistencies regarding salience can be accounted for in terms of endpoint-point focus in motion along a path; a salient-non-salient continuum; and immediate as opposed to distant deixis. An overarching Cognitive Science analysis incorporating Cognitive Psychology, Cognitive Linguistics and Mathematical calculations would thus be optimal. So far, our combination of these fields lead to our Art Creation Continuum, which incorporates the value of known composition lines – but also unpredictability in space and time; mood; the current increasing valued senses of touch, smell, taste and sound in aesthetic appreciation and experience (
Lauwrens, 2019); embodied human emotion and memories (
Lauwrens, 2019: 338); and viewing variation – all essential for making and seeing art.