1. Introduction
Stochastic order relations between random variables and distributions play a crucial role in statistical analysis by providing insights into the distribution and behavior of data. They are particularly important in estimating percentiles and medians, which are fundamental in descriptive statistics. Additionally, order statistics are widely used in reliability analysis, survival studies and risk assessment, where the minimum and maximum values help model extreme events. Their applications extend to non-parametric methods, ranking procedures and hypothesis testing, making them an essential tool in both theoretical and applied statistics. One of the earliest definitions of stochastic ordering, introduced by Lehmann [
1], states that a random variable
X with cumulative distribution function
F is stochastically greater than a random variable
Y with distribution function
G if
We call this ordering stochastic ordering, and it is denoted by
It is important to note that the inequality (
1) can be rewritten as follows:
Moreover, the inequalities (
1) and (
2) can be reformulated in a more general but actually equivalent manner as follows:
for all upper sets
that is, for all measurable sets
U such that if
, then every
also belongs to
In certain cases, a pair of distributions may verify a stronger condition called
likelihood ratio ordering. Assume that the cumulative distribution functions
F and
G possess the positive probability density functions
f and
g, respectively. We say that
X is smaller than
Y according to likelihood ratio ordering if the function ([
2], Equation (1.C.1)).
or, equivalently, that ([
2], Equation (1.C.2)):
This ordering is denoted by
It is important to note that by integrating (
3) over
and
where
A and
B are measurable sets in
it is seen that (
3) is equivalent to ([
2], Equation (1.C.3)):
where
means that
and
imply that
It is worth mentioning that the inequality (
4) does not directly involve the underlying densities, and thus, it applies equally to continuous distributions or to discrete distributions or even to mixed distributions.
A useful relationship between the likelihood ratio and the stochastic order is described in the following theorem (see [
2], Theorem 1.C.1):
where
X and
Y are two continuous or discrete random variables. It is worth mentioning that in Remark 2, we present a simple proof for the above relation for two continuous random variables supported on
Before we proceed, we need to recall some other basic definitions and some required further notation in what follows.
Definition 1 ([
2], Section 5.A.1)
. Let X and Y be two non-negative random variables such thatThen X is said to be smaller than Y in the Laplace transform order. This ordering is denoted by Moreover, if the functionthen X is said to be smaller than Y in the Laplace transform ratio order and denoted by For some background on Laplace transform ratio order, the reader is referred to ([2], Section 5.B.1). For more details regarding the Laplace transform order, including its properties, we refer the interested reader to ([
2], Chap. 5). In this regards, let us also mention that several notable contributions can be found in [
3,
4,
5,
6,
7,
8,
9].
Definition 2 ([
2], Section 5.C.2)
. Consider now two non-negative random variables X and Y such thatThen X is said to be smaller than Y in the moments order, denoted by . In addition, ifthen X is said to be smaller than Y in the moments ratio order and denoted as The moments order and the moments ratio order are reviewed in ([
2], Section 5.C.2).
Definition 3. Let X and Y be two non-negative random variables such that for some andThen X is said to be smaller than Y in the moment generating function order (or the exponential order), denoted as . For more details, see [2] (Section 5.C.3). See also ([10], Section 4.3, p. 45) and ([11], Section 3, p. 53). In probability theory, the moment generating function essentially reduces to requiring that the moment generating functions of the non-negative random variables
X and
Y are uniformly ordered. Moreover, this ordering reflects the shared risk preferences of all decision makers whose utility functions take the following form
or equivalently, whose pain functions take the following form:
From the series expansion of the exponential function, it is clear that the moment generating function order is weaker than the moment order, i.e., we have ([
2], Theorem 5.C.15):
Definition 4. A function is log-convex on the interval if is convex, i.e., if for all and we haveSimilarly, a function is said to be geometrically (or multiplicatively) convex if g is convex with respect to the geometric mean, i.e., if for all and , we have Remark 1. We note that if f and g are differentiable, then f is log-convex if and only if is increasing on I, while g is geometrically convex if and only if is increasing on A similar definition and characterization of differentiable log-concave and geometrically concave functions also holds.
Motivated by the above definitions, our aim of the paper is to introduce the following new definitions.
Definition 5 (Geometrically convex order–Geometrically concave order)
. Let X and Y be two random variables such that for all geometrically convex functions provided the expectations exist. Then X is said to be smaller than Y in the geometrically convex order and denoted as One can also define a geometrically concave order by requiring (6) to hold for all geometrically concave functions denoted as Moreover, ifwhere is geometrically convex (concave) function, then X is said to be smaller than Y in the geometrically convex (concave) ratio order and denoted as The upcoming sections are organized as follows: In
Section 2, we recollect some lemmas that will be helpful to establish some of the main results of this study. In
Section 3, we present bilateral integral functional inequalities involving the ratio of the probability density functions and the ratio of the corresponding cumulative distribution functions under the assumption that they satisfy the likelihood ratio ordering. Moreover, relationships between the likelihood ratio orders and the Gcx-orders are given. In particular, we propose alternative proofs for some existing results in order statistics. In the final section, we present new characterizations of the Laplace ratio ordering of two random variables. More precisely, we derive a lower bound for the Laplace transform under the likelihood ratio ordering. As a direct consequence, we establish sufficient conditions under which this ordering implies the Laplace transform ordering. Furthermore, we give two-sided exponential bounds for
on bounded support and present a sufficient condition that ensures Laplace ordering between two random variables.
3. First Set of Main Results
In the first result of this section, we report on the bilateral integral functional inequalities related to the ratio of the probability density functions, and the ratio of their cumulative distributions satisfy the likelihood ratio ordering. Moreover, under some conditions, we show that the likelihood ratio implies the geometric convex order and the moment generating function order.
Theorem 1. Let X and Y be positive continuous random variables with probability density functions f and g, respectively. Assume that , then the following assertions are valid:
- (a).
If the functions and are integrable on , then - (b).
Suppose that the functions and are integrable on where If the function is increasing, then the following inequalityholds true. Furthermore, if the function is decreasing on then the inequality (9) is reversed.
Proof. - (a).
The assumption
means that the function
is increasing on
Therefore, we obtain
Therefore, we conclude the asserted inequality (
8).
- (b).
We consider the function
, defined by
Under our assumptions, the functions
and
are synchoronous. From the Chebyshev inequality (
7), it follows that
which is equivalent to
Hence, the inequality (
9) holds true if
f is increasing and reversed if
f is decreasing.
□
Theorem 2. Let X and Y be non-negative random variables with probability density functions and Letbe a differentiable and geometrically convex function. Assume the following conditions hold: - (i).
For all the expectations and exist and are finite.
- (ii).
For each fixed , the functions and are integrable on and there exist integrable functions and , independent of s, such that for all Then, the following implications hold:
Proof. We consider the functions
defined on
by
We observe that the functions
and
are increasing on
under the given conditions. On the other hand, we have
and
According to Lemma 1, we establish that the following inequality
holds true for all
Now, we define the function
by
Therefore, in view of (
10), we obtain
Consequently, the function
is increasing on
Consequently, we deduce that if
, then
Furthermore, we have
The proof of Theorem 2 is completed. □
Remark 3. It is worth mentioning that the inequality (11) is reversed when the function h is geometrically concave and the conditions (i) and (ii) of Theorem 2 are satisfied. Therefore, the following relationshold true. The following result is well known (see, for instance, ([
2], Theorem 5.B.10)); we provide an alternative proof.
Corollary 1. Let X and Y be two non-negative random variables supported on with probability density functions and and assume that both have finite first moments. Then, the following implications hold: Proof. Assume that
then the function
is increasing on
Now, we set
, then the function
is decreasing, i.e., the function
is geometrically concave on
Therefore, by applying Theorem 2, we establish that the function
is decreasing on
This, in turn, implies that
Moreover, we obtain that
This, in turn, implies that the following inequality,
is valid for all
This completes the proof. □
Corollary 2. Let X and Y be two non-negative random variables supported on with probability density functions and such that for some Then Proof. In our case, we set
then the function
is increasing on
. Therefore, thanks to Theorem 2, we conclude that the function
is increasing on
. Hence, we obtain
Hence, X is smaller than Y in the moment generating function order. □
The relationship between the orders and are described in the next Proposition.
Proposition 1. Let X and Y be two non-negative random variables supported on with probability density functions and such that for all Then, Proof. Under the given conditions, the function
is increasing on
Now, we define the function
by
Another use of the Chebyshev integral inequality (
7) is that
, defined by
We observe that the functions
and
are increasing on
under the given conditions. Then, from (
7), it follows that
Owing to the inequalities (
15) and (
16), we conclude that the function
is increasing on
Therefore, for all
, we obtain
In particular, for all
, we conclude that
This ends the proof of Proposition 1. □
5. Conclusions
In this investigation, we have established new properties of the likelihood ratio and Laplace transform orderings by identifying a gap in the application of the Chebyshev integral inequality and the monotone form of L’Hospital’s rule. Specifically, by addressing this gap, we derived new bilateral integral functional inequalities related to the ratio of probability density functions and the ratio of their cumulative distributions that satisfy the likelihood ratio ordering. Additionally, we presented alternative proofs for existing results in order statistics. Moreover, we introduced the geometrically convex order and derived its relationship with the likelihood ratio order. Finally, we provided new characterizations of the Laplace transform ordering.
Several potential directions for further research include extending the results to multivariate distributions and exploring applications in reliability theory and survival analysis. One could also generalize the integral inequalities to broader classes of functions and develop numerical methods to verify stochastic orderings in data. Additionally, the derived inequalities could be used to characterize more probability distributions and to explore connections with other stochastic orders. However, these goals will be addressed and presented in future work.