Aesthetic Gadgets: Rethinking Universalism in Evolutionary Aesthetics
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Modules, Gadgets, Judgments
“All these mechanisms on the instinct-expertise continuum are what in biology (or in engineering) might typically be called modules: they are autonomous mechanisms with a history, a function, and procedures appropriate to this function. They should be viewed as components of larger systems to which they each make a distinct contribution. Conversely, the capacities of a modular system cannot be well explained without identifying its modular components and the way they work together”.[15] (p. 73)
3. Level of the Explanation
4. Aesthetic Metacognition
5. Aesthetic Gadget in Transmission
“Experience is the result, the sign, and the reward of that interaction of organism and environment which, when it is carried to the full, is a transformation of interaction into participation and communication”.[16] (p. 22)
“A cognitive mechanism certainly is not a pellet of information that can be copied inside your head, sent through the air, and planted wholesale in my head. […] Instead, we can recognize that certain kinds of social interaction, sometimes with many agents over a protracted period of time, gradually shape a child’s cognitive mechanisms so that they resemble those of the people around them”.[13] (p. 44)
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Hirn thinks that an artist has an “art-impulse” and a member of the audience has an “art-sense” that both have developed from other traits during the course of evolution [1] (p. 16). Hirn’s theory and terminology are in many parts outdated, but I do not think he explicitly claims that the art impulse and art sense would be innate. Dutton, in turn, uses the terminology of innateness in his book The Art Instinct: Beauty, Pleasure & Human Evolution and summarizes his point by saying that “[a]rt may seem largely cultural, but the art instinct that conditions it is not” [2] (p. 206). Hirn uses the Einfühlung theories of his era. By leaving the role of emotions and feelings untouched here, I do not wish to indicate they were irrelevant for metacognition, aesthetic judgement, its sub-modules, or its transmission. Since dealing with this important and large issue would mean, for instance, delving in length and detail into the vast Cognitivism vs. Emotionalism debates going on in analytic aesthetics at the moment, I leave it for another paper. |
2 | In the case of aesthetic judgment, this would translate into trying to find some loose features of aesthetic objects, not just aesthetic artifacts. |
3 | However, defining a cognitive mechanism and a behavioral trait as well as differentiating between psychological and behavioral traits is ambiguous [9] (p. 151), [10] (pp. 192–193, 200–202, 254–256, 262–263). Furthermore, choosing a focus between behavior and psychology contributes to what questions can be answered. I do not see it relevant to differentiate between sociobiology, behavioral ecology, evolutionary psychology, cultural evolution, and gene-culture co-evolution here, because the dividing lines—if there are any—tell more about the history of evolutionary humanities than contribute to understanding the evolutionary aspects of aesthetic judgment today. The approaches are not fixed or mutually exclusive, and scholars can conduct research under several of these labels at the same time [11] (p. 195). For an analysis on how these approaches intertwine and how their research questions differ, see [11] (pp. 210–213). |
4 | The central features of Fodor modules are domain specificity, mandatory operation, limited central accessibility, fast processing, informational encapsulation, “shallow” outputs, fixed neural architecture, characteristic and specific breakdown patterns, and characteristic ontogenetic pace and sequencing. Carruthers modules’ central features are dissociability, weak neural localizability, and central inaccessibility [14]. |
5 | However, it does not allow direct or empirical access to reality but serves as a heuristic device. |
6 | For example, via phenomenology, we can obtain complementary information about aesthetic experience. |
7 | I am not saying that empirical aesthetics would give the field of aesthetics no relevant information whatsoever. My point concerns only how we understand the object of the explanation, what we are receiving information about. |
8 | “…the ethologist Niko Tinbergen (1963) stressed that, when we ask why an animal exhibits a particular behavioural pattern, we could potentially be asking one of four different questions. First, we can ask questions about the function of the behavior pattern implying the role that the trait plays in enhancing reproductive success. Second, we can ask about the evolutionary history of the behavior pattern, including an account of its original ancestral state and the selective pressures in the evolutionary history of the lineage that led to the species possessing this derived behaviour. Third, we can ask what proximate causes leads the individual to express the behaviour pattern, for instance, by looking at the sensory input, neural mechanisms, and effector systems that produce the behaviour. Finally, we can ask what factors during development have played a role in directing the appearance of the behaviour at the relevant stage in its lifetime” [11] (p. 205). Answering all of the Tinbergen’s dimensions separately is a requirement for the evolutionary understanding of a behavioral trait [11] (p. 7). When it comes to aesthetic judgment, researchers are unanimous about none of them. It is also worth noting that it is controversial how many explanatory levels there are. In this article, I am only considering the proximate and evolutionary levels without paying much attention to the rest. |
9 | Note that Jérôme Dokic suggests aesthetic experience is not necessarily meta-representational [18] (p. 75). |
10 | Aesthetic judgment requires inference. The process may be fast, but it includes interpreting evidence—aesthetic properties—for conclusions. As we have to process several aesthetic features and often also data from several senses, we have to employ our working memory. If burdened enough, we experience “aesthetic fatigue” [24]. Further support for treating aesthetic judgment as metacognitive is that we communicate our aesthetic judgments with each other, and they become shared even to the point where they are agreed or disagreed upon. Additionally, so-called external (for the judgment) “second-order” factors, such as previous experience and homeostasis, hunger for example, influence our aesthetic judgments—they are not external to it, strictly speaking [20]. Discrimination means the ability to draw apart different signals so that one can build confidence on the correctness, subjective justification, of a judgment. As already touched upon above, we have an intuition about good aesthetic judgments not as an abstract category but on a case-by-case basis, even when we do not consciously go through or are not able to go through the exact process of forming an aesthetic judgment. This is a precondition for interpersonal discussion on aesthetic judgments, as well as agreement and disagreement with other people. Heyes et al. state: “Explicit metacognition uses conscious representations in working memory to monitor or evaluate–and often to control–cognitive states and processes. Explicit metacognition (here metacognition, when not qualified) is sensitive to cognitive load, and is typically slow, deliberate, and verbally reportable” [23] (p. 350). It can operate either in the level of first-order (lower-level aesthetic properties), but more commonly, second-order (aesthetic properties) computations (or confidence). I speak only about metacognition and leave it open here whether aesthetic judgment is explicit metacognition. |
11 | Terms ‘representation’ and ‘model’ have several usages. Here, representations are embodied, although not necessarily internal to the brain. They are also far from complete and stagnant. Models, too, refer to a state of the organism: The generative model should therefore be interpreted as instantiated by the agent as a whole. In other words, it is not something that one can abstract away from the phenotypic traits of an organism, because it is those traits, including states of its local niche, that instantiate such a model” [26] (p. 57). The loop of top-down and bottom-up processes refers to the predictive processing framework gaining popularity in philosophy of mind at the moment. The central idea of predictive processing is unconscious prediction error minimization. We receive bottom-up messages from the world (including ourselves) concerning effects, but rather than just passively registering, we process them inferentially. This means that our prior beliefs, accumulated during a longer period of time, shape what causes we end up taking to be most likely for a given effect. We position ourselves in the world so that our expectations or hypotheses and sensory feedback match the best way possible. Understood in this way, perception is action, and action is perception in the sense that perceptual inference works to optimize the mental models about the world to fit the data from the senses, and active inference, in turn, tests the hypotheses and changes the sensory input to fit them [27] (p. 183), [28] (pp. 75, 81, 96). |
12 | Heyes’ hypothesis concerns specifically human metacognition. It is not my aim here to study if aesthetic module is human-specific, or if other species have it as well. For example, Desideri thinks the cognitive mechanism is species-typical for humans [12] (p. 32). This would be in line with the idea that the factors characteristic of his aesthetic mechanism are Heyesian gadgets. For my purposes in this article, however, it suffices to say that at least humans have aesthetic metacognition. |
13 | In a general sense, a scenario where functioning genetic traits would not be realized in culture/nurture is only an abstract thought experiment. An exception could be for example reflexive blinking, but those cases are not relevant for this article. |
14 | Bender talks about “sensibility” whereas Heyes et al. talk about “sensitivity”. For Bender, aesthetic sensitivity refers to differences in the intensity of perceptual experience, sensitivity of the sense organs [30] (p. 76). My argument concerns aesthetic judgments as metarepresentations rather than immediate perceptiveness of the senses, in which case Benderian aesthetic sensibility is analogical to metacognitive sensitivity. |
15 | For the metarepresentational process of forming aesthetic judgments, see [22] (p. 87). |
16 | For an opposite stance, see [36] (p. 48). |
17 | |
18 | My argumentation here still leaves open to what extent the module would be innate. I do not by any means rule out that there could be statistically universal aesthetic preferences, such as certain odors. For an empirical study, see [37]. If there are some innate aesthetic preferences, the module utilizes them. |
19 | For the sake of the argument, if one still insisted on treating seeking in the case of the aesthetic as a mechanism, it would point to social learning. It is linked to perceiving symmetry or invariance (and thus, asymmetry and variance) [39]. Nanay argues that people learn socially to direct their attention [8] (p. 92). He refers to attention that can be: “i. Distributed with regards to objects and focused with regards to properties ii. Distributed with regards to objects and distributed with regards to properties iii. Focused with regards to objects and focused with regards to properties iv. Focused with regards to objects and distributed with regards to properties” [40] (p. 24). Attention applies here only in the context of the aesthetic, but talking about a functioning aesthetic module, it suffices for the purposes of this article. If Nanay is correct, how we guide our attention, properties that can catch our attention and hold meaning for us in the first place—things we are curious about and that form the soil of our aesthetic judgments—depend on social learning that molds our “mental imagery”, or horizon of expectation that affects interpretation of signals [8] (p. 90). This means that the way we seek, what generates this behavior, would not be an instinct. |
20 | Again, I will make a detour into the wilder speculations of whether preferring, in the case of aesthetic judgment, is mostly learned. At large, we have the capacity to prefer since day one in our lives—for example, over if we eat or refuse milk, or sleep or demand attention—similar to how we have consciousness since day one. Similarly to consciousness at large, the ability to prefer aesthetically forms fully in the course of social life. For the social development of consciousness, see [41] (pp. 229, 249). This is a rather common notion in philosophical aesthetics and can be derived from what was said about directing attention in the previous note. Besides the abundance of philosophical theorizing, there is also empirical evidence that taste varies according to whether a person is interacting in artworlds or not [42] (p. 32). |
21 | Play, broadly construed, has been considered crucial for the cognitive development of humans [43]. Even if play was treated as a module, it does not entail that we know the evolutionary function and ontogeny of play in humans or in other animals, and it also remains unknown if it is a mostly genetically inherited instinct or not. Neither possibility is ruled out. [44] (pp. 551, 555–556), [45] (p. 1), [46] (pp. 9, 12). |
22 | Consoli also holds that “[—]aesthetic experience is supported by a multiple set of preexisting mental properties, evolved for other reasons, and then exapted to a new and original adaptive function” [36] (p. 39). Although I use Consoli’s stance that mindreading has a role in aesthetic experience, I do not take a stance on the level of adaptations here. |
23 | The view is not challenged by empirical evidence of the appreciation of AI-created art, because the appreciator (not the AI) is in this case the maker or artist as the appreciator is looking at the object as art, as part of the historical continuum of other artworks, no matter how much the algorithm used previous artworks as reference. |
24 | Tague says: “In terms of biology, there clearly are striking benefits to making art over the costs, and the behavior is not only passed on by instruction and learning but the impulse is innate and heritable” [38] (p. 1). Although I agree that at least some of the sub-modules of the aesthetic module are heritable, and that some may also be innate, in this article I argue why it is a bit misleading to talk about the impulse for artistic behavior. |
25 | For more on mindreading and imitating other people’s mental states (“embodied simulation”) as different from each other but both present when looking at movies, see [47]. |
26 | For habits, see [48]. |
27 |
References
- Hirn, Y. The Origins of Art: A Psychological & Sociological Inquiry; MacMillan and Co.: London, UK, 1900. [Google Scholar]
- Dutton, D. The Art Instinct: Beauty, Pleasure, & Human Evolution; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, S. The Artful Species: Aesthetics, Art, and Evolution; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Richards, R. The Biology of Art; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Luty, J. Is Art an Adaptation? The Timeless Controversy over the Existence of Aesthetic Universals (by the Lens of Evolutionary Informed Aesthetics). Rocz. Kult. 2021, 12, 75–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rampley, M. The Seductions of Darwin: Art, Evolution, Neuroscience; The Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park, PA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, I. Critique of Judgment; Meredith, J.C., Translator; Walker, N., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Nanay, B. Aesthetics: A Very Short Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Longino, H.E. Studying Human Behavior: How Scientists Investigate Aggression and Sexuality; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, LI, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Kokkonen, T. Evolving in Groups: Individualism and Holism in Evolutionary Explanation of Human Social Behaviour. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland, 10 September 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Laland, K.N.; Brown, G.R. Sense and Nonsense: Evolutionary Perspectives on Human Behaviour, 2nd ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Desideri, F. Epigenesis and Coherence of the Aesthetic Mechanism. Aisthesis. Prat. Ling. E Saperi Dell’estetico 2015, 8, 25–40. [Google Scholar]
- Heyes, C. Cognitive Gadgets: The Cultural Evolution of Thinking; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Robbins, P. Modularity of Mind. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Winter Edition; 2017; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/modularity-mind/ (accessed on 14 May 2022).
- Mercier, H.; Sperber, D. The Enigma of Reason: A New Theory of Human Understanding; Penguin Books: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. Art as Experience; Perigee: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Stecker, R. Aesthetic Experience and Aesthetic Value. Philos. Compass 2006, 1, 1–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dokic, J. Aesthetic Experience as a Metacognitive Feeling? A Dual-Aspect View. Proc. Aristot. Soc. 2016, 116, 69–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Seghers, E. Proximate and Ultimate Factors in Evolutionary Thinking on Art. Hum. Ethol. Bull. 2016, 31, 47–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Skov, M.; Nadal, M. The Nature of Perception and Emotion in Aesthetic Appreciation: A Response to Makin’s Challenge to Empirical Aesthetics. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat Arts 2021, 15, 470–483. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Chuan-Peng, H.; Yi Huang, Y.; Eikchoff, S.B.; Peng, K.; Sui, J. Seeking the “Beauty Center” in the Brain: A Meta-Analysis of fMRI Studies of Beautiful Human Faces and Visual Art. Cogn. Affect. Behav Neurosci. 2020, 20, 1200–1215. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kiianlinna, O. Contradiction That Never Was. Epigenesis versus Modularity in Evolutionary Aesthetics. Aisthesis. Prat. Ling. E Saperi Dell’estetico 2021, 14, 79–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heyes, C.; Bang, D.; Shea, N.; Frith, C.D.; Fleming, S. Knowing Ourselves Together: The Cultural Origins of Metacognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2020, 24, 349–362. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mikuni, J.; Specker, E.; Pelowski, M.; Leder, H.; Kawabata, H. Is There a General “Art Fatigue” effect? A Cross-Paradigm, Cross-Cultural Study of Repeated Art Viewing in the Laboratory. Psychol. Aesthet. Create. Arts 2021, 16, 343–360. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wilson, D. Metarepresentation in Linguistic Communication. In Metarepresentations: A Multidisciplinary Perspective; Sperber, D., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Kirchhoff, M.D.; Kiverstein, J. Extended Consciousness and Predictive Processing: A Third-Wave View, 1st ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2019; Taylor & Francis eBooks Complete. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 2013, 36, 181–253. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hohwy, J. The Predictive Mind, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; EBSCOhost. [Google Scholar]
- Keller, E.F. The Mirage of a Space Between Nature and Nurture; Duke University Press: Durham, NC, USA, 2010; EBSCOhost. [Google Scholar]
- Bender, J.W. Sensitivity, Sensibility, and Aesthetic Realism. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2001, 59, 73–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scott, R.B.; Dienes, Z.; Barrett, A.B.; Bor, D.; Seth, A.K. Blind Insight: Metacognitive Discrimination Despite Chance Task Performance. Psychol. Sci. 2014, 25, 2199–2208. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Specker, E.; Forster, M.; Brinkmann, H.; Boddy, J.; Immelmann, B.; Goller, J.; Pelowski, M.; Rosenberg, R.; Leder, H. Warm, lively, rough? Assessing agreement on aesthetic effects of artworks. PLoS ONE 2020, 15, e0232083. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Malotki, E.; Dissanayake, E. Early Rock Art of the American West: The Geometric Enigma; University of Washington Press: Seattle, WA, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, S. Adornment: What Self-Decoration Tells Us about Who We Are; Bloomsbury Publishing Plc: London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Seghers, E. Cross-Species Comparison in the Evolutionary Study of Art: A Cognitive Approach to the Ape Art Debate. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 2014, 18, 263–272. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Consoli, G. The Emergence of the Modern Mind: An Evolutionary Perspective on Aesthetic Experience. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2014, 72, 37–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arshamian, A.; Gerkin, R.C.; Kruspe, N.; Wnuk, E.; Floyd, S.; O’Meara, C.; Rodriguez, G.; Lundström, J.N.; Mainland, J.D.; Majid, A. The perception of odor pleasantness is shared across cultures. Curr. Biol. 2022, 32, 2061–2066. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tague, G. Art and Adaptability: Consciousness and Cognitive Culture; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2017; ProQuest Ebook Central. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K.J.; Lin, M.; Frith, C.D.; Pezzulo, G.; Hobson, J.A.; Ondobaka, S. Active Inference, Curiosity and Insight. Neural. Comput. 2017, 29, 2633–2683. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nanay, B. Aesthetics as Philosophy of Perception; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Donald, M. A Mind So Rare: The Evolution of Human Consciousness, 1st ed.; W.W. Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Verpooten, J.; Dewitte, S. The Conundrum of Modern Art: Prestige-Driven Coevolutionary Aesthetics Trumps Evolutionary Aesthetics among Art Experts. Hum. Nat. 2017, 28, 16–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ginsburg, K.R.; The Committee on Communications; The Committee on Psychosocial Aspects of Child and Family Health. The Importance of Play in Promoting Healthy Child Development and Maintaining Strong Parent-Child Bonds. Pediatrics 2007, 119, 182–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sharpe, L.L. Play does not enhance social cohesion in a cooperative mammal. Anim. Behav. 2005, 70, 551–558. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lillard, A.S.; Lerner, M.D.; Hopkins, E.J.; Dore, R.A.; Smith, E.D.; Palmquist, C.M. The Impact of Pretend Play on Children’s Development: A Review of the Evidence. Psychol. Bull. 2013, 139, 661–686. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Allison, M.L.; Reed, R.; Michels, E.; Boogert, N.J. The drivers and functions of rock juggling in otters. R. Soc. Open Sci. 2020, 7, 200141. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Raz, G.; Hendler, T. Forking Cinematic Paths to the Self: Neurocinematically Informed Model of Empathy in Motion Pictures. Projections 2014, 8, 89–114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Portera, M. Aesthetics as a Habit: Between Constraints and Freedom, Nudges and Creativity. Philosophies 2022, 7, 24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prum, R. Coevolutionary aesthetics in human and biotic artworlds. Biol. Philos. 2013, 28, 811–832. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dissanayake, E. Komar and Melamid Discover Pleistocene Taste. Philos. Lit. 1998, 22, 486–496. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pinker, S. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature; Penguin Books: London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kiianlinna, O. Aesthetic Gadgets: Rethinking Universalism in Evolutionary Aesthetics. Philosophies 2022, 7, 71. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040071
Kiianlinna O. Aesthetic Gadgets: Rethinking Universalism in Evolutionary Aesthetics. Philosophies. 2022; 7(4):71. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040071
Chicago/Turabian StyleKiianlinna, Onerva. 2022. "Aesthetic Gadgets: Rethinking Universalism in Evolutionary Aesthetics" Philosophies 7, no. 4: 71. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040071
APA StyleKiianlinna, O. (2022). Aesthetic Gadgets: Rethinking Universalism in Evolutionary Aesthetics. Philosophies, 7(4), 71. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040071