Theory of Knowledge Based on the Idea of the Discursive Space
Abstract
:1. Introduction
- The most important event is a change in the attitude towards creating models of the world, i.e., representing the world with the help of constructions considered to be correct. At the end of the nineteenth century, the Hilbert and Peano axiomatic systems appeared. These are free-form constructions, the correctness of which is based solely on internal consistency. Compliance with experience is not only unnecessary, but principally discarded at the stage of theory development. The principle of correspondence, one of the fundamental and most widely used ideas of truth, ceases to apply, e.g., refs. [19,20,21,22].According to the idea adopted here, the aforementioned process occurred as fundamental changes in mathematics and physics in the nineteenth century, e.g., [23,24] (1906/1907), and it further developed as some fundamental means of treating knowledge “as a generalized capacity to act and as a model for reality” [25] (p. 22) and a separate issue [25,26,27,28]. The pragmatic approach takes on a special character within the philosophy of science, where it appears as a discussion on the justification of scientific judgments. Although the philosophy of science is as old as philosophy itself, e.g., [29,30], in the twentieth century, it became the “distinct yet central part of philosophy” [31] (p. xxi), formulating fundamental questions about the justification of scientific reasoning, e.g., ref. [32]. It led later to the “historical turn” in the understanding of science as a product of current historical and social circumstances in the ideas of the aforementioned Kuhn, Lakatos, and Feyerabend [33] (p. 21).
- Popper draws consequences from these experiences, formulating a weak, negative version of the correctness of knowledge based on the idea of falsification as the only reasonable certainty available to science. Such a consideration of all existing, unfalsified, and binding theories de facto in a situation of uncertainty can be understood as a withdrawal from the pursuit of achieving truth by them [34].
- The third event is based on the so-called Gettier problem, which shows an error in Plato’s definition of knowledge [35]. For a broad discussion of Plato’s views on knowledge, one can refer to Cornfold [36]. The problem is also discussed, among others, by Sober, Pritchard, Russell, Moser, Shope, and Borges et al. [9,23,37,38,39,40]. This error, which Gettier justifies with two examples, proves that Plato (through the mouth of Theaetetus) defines knowledge incorrectly. In particular, he presents two situations in which the fulfillment of the condition of having a justified and true belief does not mean having knowledge. This is an important case as it introduces distrust into the so-far transparent area, which is the meeting of man and his epistemic structures with the world. Gettier shows that it is not an easy meeting, as Russell summarizes in the following statement: “Every case of knowledge is a case of true belief, but not vice versa” [23]. Russell seems to prejudge knowledge to be necessarily true. The problem, however, is that dóksa (belief, opinion, expectation) turns out to be an immanent component of knowledge available to the human. This kind of conviction crept into science in the twentieth century, leading to point 4.
- In the twentieth century, many ideas emerged, the common feature of which was the link between knowledge and the social context. Adolf and Stehr associate their sources with researchers such as Max Weber, Max Scheler, Karol Marks, Karl Mannheim, Georg Simmel, and Emil Durkheim [25], whose insights were complemented and continued by researchers such as Steve Woolgar, Bruno Latour [41], Karin Knorr-Cetina [42], or David Bloor, one of the creators of the so-called strong programme in the field of the sociology of scientific knowledge [43]. These ideas also include the so-called social constructivism in various forms, e.g., Peter Berger and Thomas Luckman [44], Michel Foucault [45,46], and Jean-François Lyotard [47]. A more strictly epistemological approach is represented by, e.g., Thomas Kuhn [48], Paul Feyerabend [49], and Imre Lakatos [50]. One should also mention the precursor of many of the aforementioned reflections, Ludwik Fleck [51]. The aforementioned reflections are based on the variously interpreted assumption that knowledge is deeply determined by the social context, which excludes its objectivity, mandatory character, etc. In this situation, its unequivocally true character is also undermined.
- The pragmatic approach also appears as an articulation of the role of social conditions, determining both knowledge and the procedures for its acquisition, scientific or otherwise. Such a social context becomes not only important but even decisive, as indicated above. The pragmatic approach to knowledge materializes through the following three main articulations: first, as a political or/and economical project, the foundation of economics, the society organization base, etc. [52,53,54,55]; second, as a subject of management where knowledge can be treated as an organizational asset [56,57], and, third, where knowledge is understood as the utilitarian goal of the practical activity of an individual [58]. This approach made it possible to formulate great political projects in the second half of the twentieth century, and it also became the basis for reforming entirely practical management strategies [59].
- One of the most important variants of the pragmatic concern of knowledge developed in the field of technology. Knowledge is treated as a separate asset that appears in such contexts as the Internet (World Wide Web) or artificial intelligence. Both provide either more abstract and theoretical approaches [28,60,61,62] or are strictly related to practical solutions, e.g., [63,64]. The latter approach has a long history in the development of knowledge representation, e.g., [65,66,67,68], described widely, e.g., [69,70]. The latest development of knowledge representation in digital technology, namely artificial intelligence, is based on a nonsymbolic, distributed manner [70]. The different possibilities of knowledge understanding in the context of artificial intelligence come with the idea of the holder of knowledge, which is an artificial cognitive system. Such a situation causes a complete transformation of the means of understanding the phenomenon of knowledge concerning Plato’s definition, including its necessary truthfulness (alethés). This problem is taken up, e.g., by Burgin, who proposes an introduction of the concept of the artificial observer, who is the only reference for knowledge [28]. The Internet (World Wide Web), as a source of knowledge, could be considered a prototype for the other massive data sources, currently recognized as a new and very promising knowledge repository accessible through several techniques known as mining, including data mining or, in particular, text mining [71,72,73].
2. Theory of Discursive Space
3. Discussion of the Theory
4. Methodological Considerations
5. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Chisholm, R. Theory of Knowledge, Subsequent, ed.; Pearson College Div: Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA, 1989; ISBN 978-0-13-914177-5. [Google Scholar]
- Woleński, J. The History of Epistemology. In Handbook of Epistemology; Niiniluoto, I., Sintonen, M., Woleński, J., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2004; pp. 3–54. ISBN 978-1-4020-1986-9. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, R. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, 2nd ed.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2003; ISBN 978-0-415-87923-1. [Google Scholar]
- Niiniluoto, I.; Sintonen, M.; Woleński, J. (Eds.) Handbook of Epistemology; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2004; ISBN 978-94-015-6969-9. [Google Scholar]
- Woleński, J. Epistemologia: Poznanie, Prawda, Wiedza, Realizm; Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN: Warszawa, Poland, 2007; ISBN 978-83-01-14465-4. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Q. Epistemology: New Essays; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2008; ISBN 978-0-19-171847-2. [Google Scholar]
- Dancy, J.; Sosa, E.; Steup, M. (Eds.) A Companion to Epistemology; Wiley-Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA, 2010; ISBN 978-1-4051-3900-7. [Google Scholar]
- Goldman, A.I.; McGrath, M. Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2014; ISBN 978-0-19-998112-0. [Google Scholar]
- Pritchard, D. Epistemology, 2nd ed.; Palgrave Philosophy Today; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 2016; ISBN 978-1-137-52690-8. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. Philosophy & Civilization; Minton, Balch & Company: New York, NY, USA, 1931. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, C.S. What Pragmatism Is. Monist 1905, 15, 161–181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plato. Theaetetus; Penguin Classics: Harmondsworth, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1987; ISBN 978-0-14-044450-6. [Google Scholar]
- Appiah, K.A. Thinking It Through: An Introduction to Contemporary Philosophy; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2003; ISBN 978-0-19-513458-2. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, D. The Folly of Trying to Define Truth. In The Nature of Truth Classic and Contemporary Perspectives; Lynch, M.P., Ed.; A Bradford Book; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2001; pp. 623–640. [Google Scholar]
- Hestir, B.E. Plato on the Metaphysical Foundation of Meaning and Truth; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2016; ISBN 978-1-107-13232-0. [Google Scholar]
- Preus, A. Historical Dictionary of Ancient Greek Philosophy; Historical Dictionaries of Religions, Philosophies, and Movements, No. 78; The Scarecrow Press, Inc.: Lanham, MD, USA, 2007; ISBN 978-0-8108-5487-1. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Platons Werke; Georg Reimer: Berlin, Germany, 1856. [Google Scholar]
- Platon. Oeuvres Complètes; Flammarion: Paris, France, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Kline, M. Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1972; ISBN 978-0-19-501496-9. [Google Scholar]
- Murawski, R. Essays in the Philosophy and History of Logic and Mathematics; Editions Rodopi, B.V.: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2010; ISBN 978-90-420-3090-9. [Google Scholar]
- Peckhaus, V. The Pragmatism of Hilbert’s Programme. Synthese 2003, 137, 141–156. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hodgkin, L.H. A History of Mathematics: From Mesopotamia to Modernity; OUP Oxford: Oxford, UK, 2005; ISBN 978-0-19-852937-8. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. Human Knowledge–Its Scope and Limits; George Allen and Unwin Ltd.: London, UK, 1948. [Google Scholar]
- Husserl, E. Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2008; ISBN 978-1-4020-6726-6. [Google Scholar]
- Adolf, M.; Stehr, N. Knowledge; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2014; ISBN 978-1-138-01450-3. [Google Scholar]
- Tolksdorf, S. Conceptions of Knowledge; Bilingual, Ed.; de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany; Boston, MA, USA, 2011; ISBN 978-3-11-025358-0. [Google Scholar]
- Ibekwe-SanJuan, F.; Dousa, T.M. (Eds.) Theories of Information, Communication and Knowledge: A Multidisciplinary Approach; Studies in History and Philosophy of Science; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2014; Volume 34, ISBN 978-94-007-6972-4. [Google Scholar]
- Burgin, M. Theory of Knowledge: Structures and Processes; World Scientific Series in Information Studies; World Scientifc Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd.: Singapore, 2015; Volume 5, ISBN 978-981-4522-67-0. [Google Scholar]
- Losee, J. A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, 4th ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Machamer, P.; Silberstein, M. (Eds.) The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science; Blackwell Publishers Ltd.: Malden, MA, USA; Oxford, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Psillos, S.; Curd, M. (Eds.) The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science; Routledge: London, UK, 2008; ISBN 978-0-415-35403-5. [Google Scholar]
- Popper, K. Logik der Forschung: Zur Erkenntnistheorie der Modernen Naturwissenschaft; Springer: Vienna, Austria, 1935. [Google Scholar]
- Bird, A. The Historical Turn in The Philosophy of Science. In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science; Psillos, S., Curd, M., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2008; pp. 67–77. ISBN 978-0-415-35403-5. [Google Scholar]
- Popper, K. The Logic of Scientific Discovery: On the Epistemology of Modern Science, 2nd ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2002; ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7. [Google Scholar]
- Gettier, E.L. Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis 1963, 23, 121–123. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cornford, P.F.M. Plato’s Theory of Knowledge, The Theaetetus and the Sophist of Plato Translated with a Running Commentary; Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.: New York, NY, USA, 1935. [Google Scholar]
- Sober, E. Core Questions in Philosophy. A Text with Readings; Pearson Education, Inc.: New Jersey, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Moser, P.K. Gettier Problem. In A Companion to Epistemology; Dancy, J., Sosa, E., Steup, M., Eds.; Wiley-Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA, 2010; pp. 395–397. ISBN 978-1-4051-3900-7. [Google Scholar]
- Shope, R.K. The Analyzis of Knowing. In Handbook of Epistemology; Niiniluoto, I., Sintonen, M., Woleński, J., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2004; pp. 283–329. ISBN 978-94-015-6969-9. [Google Scholar]
- Borges, R.; Almeida, C.; de Klein, P.D. (Eds.) Explaining Knowledge: New Essays on the Gettier Problem, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-0-19-872456-8. [Google Scholar]
- Latour, B.; Woolgar, S. Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1979; ISBN 978-0-691-02832-3. [Google Scholar]
- Knorr-Cetina, K. The Manufacture of Knowledge: An Essay on the Constructivist and Contextual Nature of Science; Elsevier Science Limited: Pergamon Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1981; ISBN 978-0-08-025777-8. [Google Scholar]
- Bloor, D. Knowledge and Social Imagery; Routledge & Kegan Paul: London, UK, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Berger, P.L.; Luckmann, T. The Social Construction of Reality; Doubleday: New York, NY, USA, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. Les Mots et les Choses. Une Archéologie des Sciences Humaines; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1966; ISBN 978-2-07-022484-5. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. L’archéologie du Savoir; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1969; ISBN 978-2-07-026999-0. [Google Scholar]
- Lyotard, J.-F. La Condition Postmoderne. Rapport sur le Savoir; Éd. de Minuit: Paris, France, 1979; ISBN 978-2-7073-0276-2. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, T.S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P.K. Against Method. Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge; New Left Books: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. Proofs and Refutations. The Logic of Mathematical Discovery; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1976; ISBN 0-521-29038-4. [Google Scholar]
- Fleck, L. Entstehung und Entwicklung Einer Wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv; Benno Schwabe: Basel, Switzerland, 1935. [Google Scholar]
- Drucker, P. The Technological Revolution: Notes on the Relationship of Technology, Science, and Culture. Technol. Cult. 1961, 2, 342–351. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Machlup, F. The Production and Distribution of Knowledge in the United States; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, H.A. Designing Organizations for an Information-Rich World. In Computers, Communications and the Public Interest; Greenberger, P.M., Ed.; The Johns Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, MD, USA, 1971; pp. 37–72. ISBN 978-0-8018-1135-7. [Google Scholar]
- Bell, D. The Coming of Post-Industrial Society: A Venture in Social Forecasting; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Nonaka, I.; Takeuchi, H. The Knowledge-Creating Company How Japanese Companies Create the Dynamics of Innovation; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1991; ISBN 978-0-19-509269-1. [Google Scholar]
- Wiig, K.M. Knowledge Management; Schema Press: Arlington, TX, USA, 1993; ISBN 978-0-9638925-0-8. [Google Scholar]
- Hjørland, B. Knowledge Organization. Knowl. Organ. 2016, 43, 475–484. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crane, L. Knowledge and Discourse Matters: Relocating Knowledge Management’s Sphere of Interest onto Language; John Wiley & Sons, Inc.: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2016; ISBN 978-1-119-07931-6. [Google Scholar]
- Weller, K. Knowledge Representation in the Social Semantic Web; De Gruyter Saur: Berlin, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 2010; ISBN 978-3-598-25180-1. [Google Scholar]
- Zhuge, H. The Knowledge Grid: Toward Cyber-Physical Society, 2nd ed.; World Scientific: Singapore, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Moldoveanu, M.C.; Baum, J.A.C. Epinets: The Epistemic Structure and Dynamics of Social Networks; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 2014; ISBN 978-0-8047-7791-9. [Google Scholar]
- Brachman, R.; Levesque, H. Knowledge Representation and Reasoning, 1st ed.; Morgan Kaufmann: Burlington, MA, USA, 2004; ISBN 978-1-55860-932-7. [Google Scholar]
- Van Harmelen, F.; Lifschitz, V.; Porter, B. (Eds.) Handbook of Knowledge Representation; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2008; ISBN 978-0-444-52211-5. [Google Scholar]
- Collins, A.M.; Quillian, M.R. Retrieval Time from Semantic Memory. J. Verbal Learn. Verbal Behav. 1969, 8, 240–247. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Minsky, M. A Framework for Representing Knowledge; Massachusetts Institute of Technology: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1974. [Google Scholar]
- Schank, R.C.; Abelson, R.P. Scripts, Plans, and Knowledge. In Proceedings of the 4th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence; Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc.: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1975; Volume 1, pp. 151–157. [Google Scholar]
- Sowa, J.F. Knowledge Representation: Logical, Philosophical, and Computational Foundations; P.W.S.: Boston, MA, USA, 2000; ISBN 978-0-534-94965-5. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, S.J.; Norvig, P. Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach; Pearson Education, Inc.: New Jersey, NJ, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Flasiński, M. Introduction to Artificial Intelligence; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2016; ISBN 978-3-319-40020-4. [Google Scholar]
- Kitchin, R. Big Data, New Epistemologies and Paradigm Shifts. Big Data Soc. 2014, 1, 2053951714528481. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Bramer, M. Principles of Data Mining, Undergraduate Topics in Computer Science, 3rd ed.; Springer: London, UK, 2016; ISBN 978-1-4471-7306-9. [Google Scholar]
- Jo, T. Text Mining; Studies in Big Data; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2019; Volume 45, ISBN 978-3-319-91814-3. [Google Scholar]
- Maciag, R. The Analysis of the Internet Development Based on the Complex Model of the Discursive Space. Information 2018, 9, 7. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Maciag, R. Discursive Space and Its Consequences for Understanding Knowledge and Information. Philosophies 2018, 3, 34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Derrida, J. De La Grammatologie; Les Éditions de Minuit: Paris, France, 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Gadamer, H.G. Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzüge einer Philosophischen Hermeneutik; J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck): Tübingen, Germany, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Luhmann, N. Die Form der Schrift. In Schrift; Pfeiffer, K.L., Gumbrecht, H.U., Eds.; Wilhelm Fink Verlag: Munchen, Germany, 1993; pp. 349–355. [Google Scholar]
- Ong, W. Orality and Literacy. The Technologizing of the Word; Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Mikolov, T.; Sutskever, I.; Chen, K.; Corrado, G.; Dean, J. Distributed Representations of Words and Phrases and Their Compositionality. arXiv 2013, arXiv:1310.4546. [Google Scholar]
- Radford, A.; Wu, J.; Child, R.; Luan, D.; Amodei, D.; Sutskever, I. Language Models Are Unsupervised Multitask Learners. OpenAI Blog 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Vaswani, A.; Shazeer, N.; Parmar, N.; Uszkoreit, J.; Jones, L.; Gomez, A.N.; Kaiser, L.; Polosukhin, I. Attention Is All You Need. arXiv 2017, arXiv:1706.03762. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. L’ordre du Discours: Leçon Inaugurale au Collège de France Prononcée le 2 Décembre 1970; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Angermuller, J.; Maingueneau, D.; Wodak, R. The Discourse Studies Reader: Main Currents in Theory and Analysis; John Benjamins Publishing Company: Amsterdam, The Netherlands; Philadelphia, PA, USA, 2014; ISBN 978-90-272-1210-8. [Google Scholar]
- van Dijk, T.A. Discourse and Knowledge. In The Routledge Handbook of Discourse Analysis; Routledge: London, UK, 2013; pp. 587–603. ISBN 978-0-415-70978-1. [Google Scholar]
- Hyland, K.; Paltridge, B. (Eds.) Bloomsbury Companion to Discourse Analysis; Bloomsbury: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2011; ISBN 978-1-4411-6786-6. [Google Scholar]
- Jørgensen, M.; Phillips, L. Discourse Analysis as Theory and Method; Sage Publications: London, UK; Thousand Oaks, CA, USA, 2002; ISBN 978-0-7619-7111-5. [Google Scholar]
- Nolte, D.D. The Tangled Tale of Phase Space. Phys. Today 2010, 63, 33–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nolte, D.D. Introduction to Modern Dynamics: Chaos, Networks, Space and Time, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2015; ISBN 978-0-19-965704-9. [Google Scholar]
- Maciag, R. The Analysis of the Internet Development Based on the Complex Model of the Discursive Space. In Proceedings of the IS4SI 2017 Summit Digitalisation for a Sustainable Society, Gothenbg, Sweden, 12–16 June 2017; Volume 1, p. 55. [Google Scholar]
- Inselberg, A.; Shneiderman, B. Parallel Coordinates Visual Multidimensional Geometry and Its Applications; with 230 Color Illustrations; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2009; ISBN 978-0-387-21507-5. [Google Scholar]
- Maciag, R. Digital Transformation as the Subject of Discursive Analysis. In Proceedings of the 2018 IEEE 16th International Conference on Industrial Informatics (INDIN), Porto, Portugal, 18–20 July 2018; pp. 1065–1070. [Google Scholar]
- Armstrong, D.M. A World of States of Affairs; Cambridge Studies in Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1997; ISBN 978-0-521-58948-2. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus; Russell, B., Ed.; Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.: London, UK, 1922. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. Analytic Realism. In Russell on Metaphysics. Selections from the Writings of Bertrand Russell; Mumford, S., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2003; pp. 91–96. ISBN 978-0-415-27745-7. [Google Scholar]
- Klement, K. Russell’s Logical Atomism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Riemann, B. On the Hypotheses Which Lie at the Bases of Geometry; Jost, J., Ed.; Classic Texts in the Sciences; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2016; ISBN 978-3-319-26040-2. [Google Scholar]
- Horsman, D.; Kendon, V.; Stepney, S.; Young, J.P.W. Abstraction and Representation in Living Organisms: When Does a Biological System Compute? In Representation and Reality in Humans, Other Living Organisms and Intelligent Machines; Dodig-Crnkovic, G., Giovagnoli, R., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2017; pp. 91–116. ISBN 978-3-319-43784-2. [Google Scholar]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G.; von Haugwitz, R. Reality Construction in Cognitive Agents Through Processes of Info-Computation. In Representation and Reality in Humans, Other Living Organisms and Intelligent Machines; Dodig-Crnkovic, G., Giovagnoli, R., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2017; pp. 211–232. ISBN 978-3-319-43784-2. [Google Scholar]
- Rob, K.; Gavin, M. What Makes Big Data, Big Data? Exploring the Ontological Characteristics of 26 Datasets. Big Data Soc. 2016, 3, 2053951716631130. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bateson, G. Steps to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution, and Epistemology; J. Aronson: Northvale, NJ, USA; London, UK, 1987; ISBN 978-0-87668-950-9. [Google Scholar]
- Van Dijk, T.A. (Ed.) Discourse as Structure and Process; Discourse Studies: A Multidisciplinary Introduction; SAGE: London, UK, 1997; Volume I, ISBN 978-0-8039-7844-7. [Google Scholar]
- Fairclough, N. Analysing Discourse: Textual Analysis for Social Research; Routledge: London, UK, 2003; ISBN 978-0-415-25892-0. [Google Scholar]
- Boole, G. An Investigation of the Laws of Thought: On Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities; Walton and Maberly: London, UK, 1854. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, R. (Ed.) The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2nd ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999; ISBN 978-0-521-63136-5. [Google Scholar]
- Dascălu, M. Computational Discourse Analysis. In Analyzing Discourse and Text Complexity for Learning and Collaborating: A Cognitive Approach Based on Natural Language Processing; Dascălu, M., Ed.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2014; pp. 53–77. ISBN 978-3-319-03419-5. [Google Scholar]
- Jurafsky, D.; Martin, J.H. Speech and Language Processing: An Introduction to Natural Language Processing, Computational Linguistics, and Speech Recognition, 2nd ed.; Prentice Hall: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2009; ISBN 978-0-13-187321-6. [Google Scholar]
- Paltridge, B. Discourse Analysis: An Introduction; Continuum: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2006; ISBN 978-0-8264-8557-1. [Google Scholar]
- Wodak, R. Critical Discourse Analysis. In Bloomsbury Companion to Discourse Analysis; Hyland, K., Paltridge, B., Eds.; Bloomsbury: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2011; pp. 38–53. ISBN 978-1-4411-6786-6. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, M. The Order of Discourse. In Untying the text: A post-structuralist reader; Young, R., Ed.; Routledge & Kegan Paul: Boston, MA, USA, 1981; pp. 51–78. [Google Scholar]
- Gärdenfors, P. Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2000; ISBN 0-262-07199-1. [Google Scholar]
- Gärdenfors, P. Conceptual Spaces as a Framework for Knowledge Representation. Mind Matter 2004, 2, 9–27. [Google Scholar]
- Zenker, F.; Gärdenfors, P. (Eds.) Applications of Conceptual Spaces; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; ISBN 978-3-319-15020-8. [Google Scholar]
- Byrne, D.S.; Callaghan, G. Complexity Theory and the Social Sciences: The State of the Art; Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group: New York, NY, USA, 2014; ISBN 978-0-415-69367-7. [Google Scholar]
- Abraham, R.; Marsden, J.E.; Ratiu, T.; Cushman, R. Foundations of Mechanics, 2nd ed.; Addison-Wesley Publishing Company: Reading, MA, USA, 1980; ISBN 978-0-8053-0102-1. [Google Scholar]
- Birkhoff, G.D. Dynamical Systems, Revise ed.; American Mathematical Society Colloquium Publications; American Mathematical Society: Providence, RI, USA, 1966; Volume 9. [Google Scholar]
- Torretti, R. Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1978; ISBN 978-90-277-1837-2. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, D.W. Mathematical Form in the World. Philos. Math. 2002, 10, 102–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lee, J.M. Introduction to Topological Manifolds; Graduate Texts in Mathematics; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2011; Volume 202, ISBN 978-1-4419-7939-1. [Google Scholar]
- Kirby, R.C.; Siebenmann, L.C. Foundational Essays on Topological Manifolds, Smoothings, and Triangulations. (AM-88); Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1977; Volume 88, ISBN 978-1-4008-8150-5. [Google Scholar]
- Tu, L.W. An Introduction to Manifolds; Universitext; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2011; ISBN 978-1-4419-7399-3. [Google Scholar]
- Devlin, J.; Chang, M.-W.; Lee, K.; Toutanova, K. BERT: Pre-Training of Deep Bidirectional Transformers for Language Understanding. arXiv 2018, arXiv:1810.04805. [Google Scholar]
- Rescher, N. Epistemic Logic: A Survey of the Logic of Knowledge, 1st ed.; University of Pittsburgh Press: Pittsburgh, PA, USA, 2005; ISBN 978-0-8229-6130-7. [Google Scholar]
- Ditmarsch, H.; van Halpern, J.Y.; Hoek, W.; van der Kooi, B. (Eds.) Handbook of Epistemic Logic; College Publications: London, UK, 2015; ISBN 978-1-84890-158-2. [Google Scholar]
- Rendsvig, R.; Symons, J. Epistemic Logic. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Hintikka, J. Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- van Ditmarsch, H.; van der Hoek, W.; Kooi, B. Dynamic Epistemic Logic; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2008; ISBN 978-1-4020-5838-7. [Google Scholar]
- Gillies, D. Frege, Dedekind, and Peano on the Foundations of Arithmetic; Van Gorcum & Co: Assen, The Netherlands, 1982; ISBN 978-1-136-72107-6. [Google Scholar]
- Hilbert, D. Grundlagen der Geometrie; Verlag von B.G. Teubner: Leipzig, Germany, 1899. [Google Scholar]
- Peano, G. Arithmetices Principia: Nova Methodo; Fratres Bocca: Romae, Florentiae, Italy, 1889. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Maciag, R. Theory of Knowledge Based on the Idea of the Discursive Space. Philosophies 2022, 7, 72. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040072
Maciag R. Theory of Knowledge Based on the Idea of the Discursive Space. Philosophies. 2022; 7(4):72. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040072
Chicago/Turabian StyleMaciag, Rafal. 2022. "Theory of Knowledge Based on the Idea of the Discursive Space" Philosophies 7, no. 4: 72. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040072
APA StyleMaciag, R. (2022). Theory of Knowledge Based on the Idea of the Discursive Space. Philosophies, 7(4), 72. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7040072