Information in Explaining Cognition: How to Evaluate It?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Unificatory Explanation in the Cognitive Sciences?
3. A Useful Trichotomy of Information in the Cognitive Sciences
3.1. Natural and Non-Natural Information: The Gricean Path
3.2. Natural, Sensory, and Endogenous Information
4. Desiderata for Cognition-Friendly Theories of Information
4.1. (D1) Quantifiability
4.2. (D2) Substrate Neutrality
4.3. (D3) Sender Neutrality
4.4. (D4) Receiver Dependence
4.5. (D5) Symbolic/Non-Symbolic Information
4.6. (D6) Mistaken Tokening
5. Global Workspace Theory: Which Features of Information Are Posited?
6. Conclusions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Despite the differences between them, cognitive “theories” and “models” are used interchangeably hereafter. |
2 | For a critique of the prospects of an integrative neuroscience, see, e.g., Sullivan [86]. She argues that the multiplicity of distinct experimental protocols used to examine the same supposed phenomenon provide evidence against this integrative endeavour. |
3 | We discuss the factivity of natural information further in Section 4. |
4 | Therefore, maternal hormones provide a mechanism for transferring environmental cues from parents to offspring. |
5 | An odd consequence of this view is that an activation of the reflex without the stimulus counts as a misrepresentation. |
6 | One may also argue that other mechanisms (e.g., a simultaneity constancy mechanism) are required when combining multisensory information (e.g., visual and tactile) about a single environmental event (because different kinds of information take varying amounts of time to be processed in the brain). |
7 | A recent study of V1 and V2 activity in macaque monkeys reports that the “anticipatory signal reflects a nonsensory component of cortical activity that is (…) not related to stimulus coding or choice behavior” [87] (p. 5199). |
8 | “Silence may be very informative. This is a peculiarity of information: its absence may also be informative” [12] (p. 88). If so, then silence supposedly qualifies as disembodied information. However, it does not qualify as information per se, but rather as being informative as part of an inferential process that includes other background information [88]. |
9 | For a similar reason, Scarantino, for example, deems natural information “an objective commodity” that is nonetheless “mind-dependent” [14] (p. 432) relativised to potential receivers. |
10 | Rathkopf similarly argues that if an organism cannot exploit an XY correlation, even in principle, for some biological end, then that correlation cannot be legitimately used to compute the mutual information between events X and Y [58] (p. 324). |
11 | |
12 | It remains unclear, though, (a) why cognitive systems should be in tune with such physical necessities and initial conditions, and (b) how physical necessity is grounded if not by a law of nature. |
13 | The question of whether consciousness is the cause or rather the outcome of access to the global workspace does not affect our main argument here. |
References
- De-Wit, L.; Alexander, D.; Ekroll, V.; Wagemans, J. Is neuroimaging measuring information in the brain? Psychon. Bull. Rev. 2016, 23, 1415–1428. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Koch, C. Biophysics of Computation: Information Processing in Single Neurons; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Ramos, R.T. The concepts of representation and information in explanatory theories of human behavior. Front. Psychol 2014, 5, 1034. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Tononi, G.; Boly, M.; Massimini, M.; Koch, C. Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical substrate. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2016, 17, 450–461. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Dretske, F.I. Knowledge & The Flow of Information; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Fisher, R.A. On the Mathematical Foundations of Theoretical Statistics. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 1922, 222, 309–368. [Google Scholar]
- Hartley, R.V.L. Transmission of Information. Bell Syst. Tech. J. 1928, 7, 535–563. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shannon, C.E. A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Syst. Tech. J. 1948, 27, 379–423. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Lewis, D. Convention: A Philosophical Study; Wiley-Blackwell: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Skyrms, B. Signals: Evolution, learning, & information; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Bar-Hillel, Y.; Carnap, R. Semantic Information. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 1953, 4, 147–157. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Floridi, L. The Philosophy of Information; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Fresco, N.; Ginsburg, S.; Jablonka, E. Functional Information: A Graded Taxonomy of Difference Makers. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2020, 11, 547–567. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scarantino, A. Information as a Probabilistic Difference Maker. Australas. J. Philos. 2015, 93, 419–443. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stegmann, U.E. A primer on information and influence in animal communication. In Animal Communication Theory: Information and Influence; Stegmann, U.E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2013; pp. 1–39. [Google Scholar]
- Rathkopf, C. What Kind of Information is Brain Information? Topoi 2017, 39, 95–102. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Cao, R. A teleosemantic approach to information in the brain. Biol. Philos. 2012, 27, 49–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ramsey, W. Representation Reconsidered; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Miłkowski, M.; Hohol, M. Explanations in cognitive science: Unification versus pluralism. Synthese 2020, 199, 1–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Colombo, M.; Hartmann, S. Bayesian Cognitive Science, Unification, and Explanation. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 2017, 68, 451–484. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- McMullin, E. Explanatory Success and the Truth of Theory. In Scientific Inquiry in Philosophical Perspective; Rescher, N., Ed.; University Press of America: Lanham, MD, USA, 1987; pp. 51–73. [Google Scholar]
- Grice, H.P. Meaning. Philos. Rev. 1957, 66, 377–388. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Groothuis, T.G.G.; Hsu, B.-Y.; Kumar, N.; Tschirren, B. Revisiting mechanisms and functions of prenatal hormone-mediated maternal effects using avian species as a model. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 2019, 374, 20180115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hyun, J.-S.; Luck, S.J. Visual working memory as the substrate for mental rotation. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 2007, 14, 154–158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Birch, J. Propositional content in signalling systems. Philos. Stud. 2014, 171, 493–512. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ramstead, M.J.D.; Veissière, S.P.L.; Kirmayer, L.J. Cultural Affordances: Scaffolding Local Worlds through Shared Intentionality and Regimes of Attention. Front. Psychol. 2016, 7, 1090. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shea, N. Representation in Cognitive Science; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Millikan, R.G. Biosemantics. J. Philos. 1989, 86, 281–297. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lloyd, D.E. Simple Minds; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Schulte, P. Perceptual representations: A teleosemantic answer to the breadth-of-application problem. Biol. Philos. 2015, 30, 119–136. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Burge, T. Origins of Objectivity; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Artiga, M.; Sebastián, M.Á. Informational Theories of Content and Mental Representation. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2020, 11, 613–627. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Corning, P.A. Control information theory: The “missing link” in the science of cybernetics. Syst. Res. Behav. Sci. 2007, 24, 297–311. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miłkowski, M. The Hard Problem of Content: Solved (Long Ago). Stud. Log. Gramm. Rhetor. 2015, 41, 73–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Chang, L.J.; Jolly, E.; Cheong, J.H.; Rapuano, K.M.; Greenstein, N.; Chen, P.-H.A.; Manning, J.R. Endogenous variation in ventromedial prefrontal cortex state dynamics during naturalistic viewing reflects affective experience. Sci. Adv. 2021, 7, eabf7129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- O”Carroll, D.C.; Wiederman, S.D. Contrast sensitivity and the detection of moving patterns and features. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 2014, 369. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Okawa, H.; Miyagishima, K.J.; Arman, A.C.; Hurley, J.B.; Field, G.D.; Sampath, A.P. Optimal processing of photoreceptor signals is required to maximize behavioural sensitivity: Rod signal-to-noise and behavioural threshold. J. Physiol. 2010, 588, 1947–1960. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vetter, P.; Newen, A. Varieties of cognitive penetration in visual perception. Conscious. Cogn. 2014, 27, 62–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Corlett, P.R.; Horga, G.; Fletcher, P.C.; Alderson-Day, B.; Schmack, K.; Powers, A.R. Hallucinations and Strong Priors. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2019, 23, 114–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Miller, G.A. The magical number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on our capacity for processing information. Psychol. Rev. 1956, 63, 81–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Tafreshi, D.; Slaney, K.L.; Neufeld, S.D. Quantification in psychology: Critical analysis of an unreflective practice. J. Theor. Philos. Psychol. 2016, 36, 233–249. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rieke, F.; Warland, D.; de Ruyter van Steveninck, R.; Bialek, W. Spikes: Exploring the Neural Code; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Reznikova, Z. Spatial cognition in the context of foraging styles and information transfer in ants. Anim. Cogn. 2020, 23, 1143–1159. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Polger, T.W.; Shapiro, L.A. The Multiple Realization Book; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Mangan, B. Against functionalism: Consciousness as an information-bearing medium. In Toward a Science of Consciousness II: The Second Tucson Discussions and Debates; Hameroff, S.R., Kaszniak, A.W., Scott, A., Eds.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1998; pp. 135–141. [Google Scholar]
- Miłkowski, M. Explaining the Computational Mind; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Deacon, T.W. Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter; W. W. Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Bennett, C.H. Logical Reversibility of Computation. IBM J. Res. Dev. 1973, 17, 525–532. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Landauer, R. Information is Physical. Phys. Today 1991, 44, 23–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ghazanfar, A.; Schroeder, C. Is neocortex essentially multisensory? Trends Cogn. Sci. 2006, 10, 278–285. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stein, B.E.; Stanford, T.R.; Rowland, B.A. The neural basis of multisensory integration in the midbrain: Its organization and maturation. Hear. Res. 2009, 258, 4–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sugar, J.; Moser, M. Episodic memory: Neuronal codes for what, where, and when. Hippocampus 2019, 29, 1190–1205. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Maynard Smith, J.; Harper, D. Animal signals; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Godfrey-Smith, P. Sender-Receiver Systems within and between Organisms. Philos. Sci. 2014, 81, 866–878. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Jablonka, E. Information: Its Interpretation, Its Inheritance, and Its Sharing. Philos. Sci. 2002, 69, 578–605. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fresco, N. Information, Cognition, and Objectivity. Am. Philos. Q. 2021, 58, 251–268. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mann, S.F. Consequences of a Functional Account of Information. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2018, 11, 1–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rathkopf, C. Neural information and the problem of objectivity. Biol. Philos. 2017, 32, 321–336. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Newell, A. Unified Theories of Cognition; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Deacon, T.W. The symbol concept. In The Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution; Gibson, K.R., Tallerman, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011; pp. 393–405. [Google Scholar]
- Martin, A.E. Language Processing as Cue Integration: Grounding the Psychology of Language in Perception and Neurophysiology. Front. Psychol. 2016, 7, 120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Altmann, G. Psycholinguistics: History in Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2006; pp. 257–265. [Google Scholar]
- Gallistel, C.R. Learning and Representation. In Learning and Memory; Bryne, J.H., Ed.; Elsevier Science: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2017; pp. 141–154. [Google Scholar]
- Michelsen, A.; Andersen, B.B.; Jesper, S.; Kirchner, W.H.; Lindauer, M. How Honeybees Perceive Communication Dances, Studied by Means of a Mechanical Model. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol. 1992, 30, 143–150. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Anderson, S.R. The Place of Human Language in the Animal World. In Formal Models in the Study of Language; J. Blochowiak, J., Grisot, C., Laenzlinger, C., Eds.; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2017; pp. 339–351. [Google Scholar]
- Todorov, E.; Jordan, M.I. Optimal feedback control as a theory of motor coordination. Nat. Neurosci. 2002, 5, 1226–1235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wolpert, D.M. Probabilistic models in human sensorimotor control. Hum. Mov. Sci. 2007, 26, 511–524. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Taylor, J.A.; Ivry, R.B. The role of strategies in motor learning. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 2012, 1251, 1–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Moran, A. Naïve Realism, Hallucination, and Causation: A New Response to the Screening Off Problem. Australas. J. Philos. 2019, 97, 368–382. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crane, T. Is perception a propositional attitude? Philos. Q. 2009, 59, 452–469. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Orlandi, N. The Innocent Eye: Why Vision Is Not a Cognitive Process; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Siegel, S. The Rationality of Perception; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Zahnoun, F. Truth or Accuracy? Theoria 2020, 86, 643–650. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baker, B. Natural information, factivity and nomicity. Biol. Philos. 2021, 36, 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scarantino, A.; Piccinini, G. Information without truth. Metaphilosophy 2010, 41, 313–330. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Melloni, L.; Mudrik, L.; Pitts, M.; Koch, C. Making the hard problem of consciousness easier. Science 2021, 372, 911–912. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Baars, B.J. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Mashour, G.A.; Roelfsema, P.; Changeux, J.-P.; Dehaene, S. Conscious Processing and the Global Neuronal Workspace Hypothesis. Neuron 2020, 105, 776–798. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Dehaene, S.; Changeux, J.-P. Experimental and Theoretical Approaches to Conscious Processing. Neuron 2011, 70, 200–227. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dehaene, S.; Changeux, J.-P.; Naccache, L. The Global Neuronal Workspace Model of Conscious Access: From Neuronal Architectures to Clinical Applications. In Characterizing Consciousness: From Cognition to the Clinic? Dehaene, S., Christen, Y., Eds.; Springer: Berlin, Germany, 2011; pp. 55–84. [Google Scholar]
- Mudrik, L.; Melloni, L.; Pitts, M.; Blumenfeld, H.; de Lange, F.; Jensen, O.; Kreiman, G.; Luo, H.; Chalmers, D.; Devore, S.; et al. Preregistration File-v2-May 2020. Available online: osf.io/f87xq (accessed on 20 February 2022).
- Dehaene, S.; Naccache, L.; Cohen, L.; Bihan, D.L.; Mangin, J.-F.; Poline, J.-B.; Rivière, D. Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and unconscious repetition priming. Nat. Neurosci. 2001, 4, 752–758. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- King, J.-R.; Pescetelli, N.; Dehaene, S. Brain Mechanisms Underlying the Brief Maintenance of Seen and Unseen Sensory Information. Neuron 2016, 92, 1122–1134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Shanahan, M.; Baars, B. Applying global workspace theory to the frame problem. Cognition 2005, 98, 157–176. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hare, S.M. Hallucinations: A Functional Network Model of How Sensory Representations Become Selected for Conscious Awareness in Schizophrenia. Front. Neurosci. 2021, 15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sullivan, J.A. The multiplicity of experimental protocols: A challenge to reductionist and non-reductionist models of the unity of neuroscience. Synthese 2009, 167, 511–539. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goris, R.L.T.; Ziemba, C.M.; Stine, G.M.; Simoncelli, E.P.; Movshon, J.A. Dissociation of Choice Formation and Choice-Correlated Activity in Macaque Visual Cortex. J. Neurosci. 2017, 37, 5195–5203. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fresco, N.; Michael, M. Information and Veridicality: Information Processing and the Bar-Hillel/Carnap Paradox. Philos. Sci. 2016, 83, 131–151. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scarantino, A. Rethinking Functional Reference. Philos. Sci. 2013, 80, 1006–1018. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wheeler, B.C.; Fischer, J. Functionally referential signals: A promising paradigm whose time has passed. Evol. Anthropol. Issues News Rev. 2012, 21, 195–205. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
Desideratum | Natural Information | Sensory Information | Endogenous Information |
---|---|---|---|
1. Quantifiability | ✔ | ✔ | ✔ |
2. Substrate-Neutrality | ✔ | ✔ | ✔ |
3. Sender-Neutrality | ✔ | ✔ | ✔ |
4. Receiver-Dependence | ✔ | ✔ | ✔ |
5. Symbolic/Non-Symbolic | n/a | ✔ | ✔ |
6. Mistaken Tokening | n/a | ✔ | ✔ |
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Fresco, N. Information in Explaining Cognition: How to Evaluate It? Philosophies 2022, 7, 28. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020028
Fresco N. Information in Explaining Cognition: How to Evaluate It? Philosophies. 2022; 7(2):28. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020028
Chicago/Turabian StyleFresco, Nir. 2022. "Information in Explaining Cognition: How to Evaluate It?" Philosophies 7, no. 2: 28. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020028
APA StyleFresco, N. (2022). Information in Explaining Cognition: How to Evaluate It? Philosophies, 7(2), 28. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7020028