How to Make Correct Predictions in False Belief Tasks without Attributing False Beliefs: An Analysis of Alternative Inferences and How to Avoid Them
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Standard False Belief Task
3. Nonverbal False Belief Task
4. Problems with the False Belief Task
5. The Plurality of Predictive Inferences Available in ToM Tasks
5.1. Belief Attribution + Covering Laws (A-Type)
- (A)
- “People generally see that a state of affairs is the case when it is in their visual fields.”
- (B)
- “If a person sees an object x in the place y, then she forms the belief that x is in the place y, that will last even if the person loses the visual access to x.”
- (C)
- “People usually look for objects in places where they believe objects are.”
5.2. Non-Representational Mental State Attribution + Covering Laws (B-Type)
- (A)
- “People generally see facts when they are in their visual fields.”
- (B)
- “Generally, if a person last saw an object in a certain place, and it continues in this place, then she is aware of the location of the object.”
- (C)
- “Generally, if a person is going to look for an object and is aware of its location, then she will look for it where it is.”
- (A)
- “People usually see facts when they are in their visual fields.”
- (B)
- “Generally, if a person last saw an object in a certain place, and it is in another place, then she ignores the location of the object.”
- (C)
- “Generally, if a person is going to look for an object and ignores its location, then she will not look for it where it is.”
- (A)
- “People usually see facts when they are in their visual fields.”
- (B)
- “Generally, if an object is in a certain place, and a person sees it in this place, then she knows the location of the object.”
- (C)
- “Generally, if a person is going to look for an object and knows its location, then she will look for it where it is.”
- (A)
- “People usually see facts when they are in their visual fields.”
- (B)
- “Generally, if an object is in a certain place, and a person does not see it in this place, then she does not know (=ignores) the location of the object.”
- (C)
- “Generally, if a person is going to look for an object and does not know (=ignores) its location, then she will not look for it in the place where it is.”
- (A)
- “People usually see facts when they are in their visual fields.”
- (B)
- “Generally, if a person last saw an object in a certain place, and she is going to look for this object, then she will look for it in the place where she last saw it.”
5.3. Particular Situation + Covering Laws (C-Type)
To compete and cooperate effectively with others in their group, highly social animals, such as chimpanzees, must be able not only to react to what others are doing but also to anticipate what they will do. One way of accomplishing this is by observing what others do in particular situations and deriving a set of ‘behavioral rules’ (or, in some cases, having those built in). This will enable behavioral prediction when the same or a highly similar situation arises again.(p. 187)
- (A)
- “Generally, if a person’s eyes were last moved towards an object when it was in a certain place, and she is going to look for this object, then she will look for it in this place.”
6. How Can Alternative Inferences Be Eliminated?
- (1)
- (x) x passes the FBT → (x uses A1 ⊻ x uses B1 ⊻ x uses B2 ⊻ x uses B3 ⊻ x uses C1 ⊻ x uses C3) ∧ ¬(x uses C2)
- (2)
- (x) x passes the TBT → (x uses A1 ⊻ x uses B1 ⊻ x uses B3 ⊻ x uses C2 ⊻ x uses C3) ∧ ¬(x uses B2) ∧ ¬(x uses C1)
- (3)
- (x) (x passes the FBT ∧ x passes the TBT) → (x uses A1 ⊻ x uses B1 ⊻ x uses B3 ⊻ x uses C3)
- (4)
- (x) x passes TASK 3 → (x uses A1 ⊻ x uses B2 ⊻ x uses B1 ⊻ x uses C2 ⊻ x uses C3) ∧ ¬(x uses B1) ∧ ¬(x uses C3)
- (5)
- (x) x passes TASK 4 → (x uses A1 ⊻ x uses B1 ⊻ x uses B2 ⊻ x uses C2 ⊻ x uses C3) ∧ ¬(x uses B3) ∧ ¬(x uses C1)
- (6)
- (x) (x passes the FBT ∧ x passes the TBT ∧ x passes TASK 3 ∧ x passes TASK 4) → (x uses A1)
7. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Premack, D.; Woodruff, G. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behav. Brain Sci. 1978, 1, 515–526. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Griffin, R.; Baron-Cohen, S. The intentional stance: Developmental and neurocognitive perspectives. In Dennett Beyond Philosophy; Brook, A., Ross, D., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Saxe, R.; Kanwisher, N. People thinking about thinking people: The role of the temporo-parietal junction in “theory of mind”. Neuroimage 2003, 19, 1835–1842. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lewis, D. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Aust. J. Philos. 1972, 50, 249–258. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Armstrong, D.M. The causal theory of the mind. In The Nature of Mind and Other Essays; Chalmers, D.J., Ed.; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Churchland, P.M. Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. J. Philos. 1981, 78, 67–90. [Google Scholar]
- Churchland, P.M. Folk psychology and the explanation of human behavior. Philos. Perspect. 1989, 3, 225–241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fodor, J.A. A theory of the child’s theory of mind. Cognition 1992, 44, 283–296. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Leslie, A.M. Pretending and believing: Issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition 1994, 50, 211–238. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scholl, B.J.; Leslie, A.M. Modularity, development and ‘theory of mind’. Mind Lang. 1999, 14, 131–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wellman, H.M. The Child’s Theory of Mind; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Gopnik, A.; Wellman, H.M. Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory. Mind Lang. 1992, 7, 145–171. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gopnik, A.; Wellman, H.M. The theory theory. In Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1994; pp. 257–292. [Google Scholar]
- Chomsky, N. Rules and representations. Behav. Brain Sci. 1980, 3, 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Apperly, I.A.; Butterfill, S.A. Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychol. Rev. 2009, 1146, 953–970. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Heyes, C. False belief in infancy: A fresh look. Dev. Sci. 2014, 17, 647–659. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Perner, J.; Ruffman, T. Infants’ insight into the mind: How deep? Science 2005, 308, 214–216. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Rubio-Fernández, P.; Jara-Ettinger, J.; Gibson, E. Can processing demands explain toddlers’ performance in false-belief tasks? Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2017, 114, E3750. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Butterfill, S.A.; Apperly, I.A. How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind Lang. 2013, 28, 606–637. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wimmer, H.; Perner, J. Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition 1983, 13, 103–128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bloom, P.; German, T.P. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind. Cognition 2000, 77, B25–B31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Saxe, R. The right temporo-parietal junction: A specific brain region for thinking about thoughts. In Handbook of Theory of Mind; Erlbaum: Hillsdale, NJ, USA, 2010; pp. 1–35. [Google Scholar]
- Southgate, V.; Senju, A.; Csibra, G. Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by 2-year-olds. Psychol. Sci. 2007, 18, 587–592. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Onishi, K.H.; Baillargeon, R. Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science 2005, 308, 255–258. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Baron-Cohen, S.; Leslie, A.M.; Frith, U. Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”? Cognition 1985, 21, 37–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wellman, H.M.; Cross, D.; Watson, J. Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Dev. 2001, 72, 655–684. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Clements, W.A.; Perner, J. Implicit understanding of belief. Cogn. Dev. 1994, 9, 377–395. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ruffman, T.; Garnham, W.; Import, A.; Connolly, D. Does eye gaze indicate implicit knowledge of false belief? Charting transitions in knowledge. J. Exp. Child Psychol. 2001, 80, 201–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Southgate, V.; Vernetti, A. Belief-based action prediction in preverbal infants. Cognition 2014, 130, 1–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kilner, J.M.; Vargas, C.; Duval, S.; Blakemore, S.J.; Sirigu, A. Motor activation prior to observation of a predicted movement. Nat. Neurosci. 2004, 7, 1299–1301. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Southgate, V.; Begus, K. Motor activation during the prediction of nonexecutable actions in infants. Psychol. Sci. 2013, 24, 828–835. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Quine, W.V.O. From a Logical Point of View: 9 Logico-Philosophical Essays; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1961; Volume 9. [Google Scholar]
- Fabricius, W.V.; Khalil, S.L. False beliefs or false positives? Limits on children’s understanding of mental representation. J. Cogn. Dev. 2003, 4, 239–262. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fabricius, W.V.; Boyer, T.W.; Weimer, A.A.; Carroll, K. True or false: Do 5-year-olds understand belief? Dev. Psychol. 2010, 46, 1402–1416. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hedger, J.A.; Fabricius, W.V. True belief belies false belief: Recent findings of competence in infants and limitations in 5-year-olds, and implications for theory of mind development. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2011, 2, 429–447. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Povinelli, D.J.; Vonk, J. Chimpanzee minds: Suspiciously human? Trends Cogn. Sci. 2003, 7, 157–160. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Povinelli, D.J.; Vonk, J. We don’t need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee’s mind. Mind Lang. 2004, 19, 1–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Call, J.; Tomasello, M. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2008, 12, 187–192. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Apperly, I.A.; Robinson, E.J. Children’s mental representation of referential relations. Cognition 1998, 67, 289–309. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Apperly, I.A.; Robinson, E.J. When can children handle referential opacity? Evidence for systematic variation in 5-and 6-year-old children’s reasoning about beliefs and belief reports. J. Exp. Child Psychol. 2003, 85, 297–311. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dennett, D.C. Beliefs about beliefs [P&W, SR&B]. Behav. Brain Sci. 1978, 1, 568–570. [Google Scholar]
- Fodor, J.A. The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
© 2018 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Perera, R.A.; Albornoz Stein, S.I. How to Make Correct Predictions in False Belief Tasks without Attributing False Beliefs: An Analysis of Alternative Inferences and How to Avoid Them. Philosophies 2018, 3, 10. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies3020010
Perera RA, Albornoz Stein SI. How to Make Correct Predictions in False Belief Tasks without Attributing False Beliefs: An Analysis of Alternative Inferences and How to Avoid Them. Philosophies. 2018; 3(2):10. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies3020010
Chicago/Turabian StylePerera, Ricardo Augusto, and Sofia Inês Albornoz Stein. 2018. "How to Make Correct Predictions in False Belief Tasks without Attributing False Beliefs: An Analysis of Alternative Inferences and How to Avoid Them" Philosophies 3, no. 2: 10. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies3020010
APA StylePerera, R. A., & Albornoz Stein, S. I. (2018). How to Make Correct Predictions in False Belief Tasks without Attributing False Beliefs: An Analysis of Alternative Inferences and How to Avoid Them. Philosophies, 3(2), 10. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies3020010