Next Article in Journal
Examining the Anthropological–Philosophical Implicit Content in Carl Menger’s Value Theory Through Three Philosophers
Previous Article in Journal
Revisiting Kant’s Conception of Political Freedom and Its Relation to the Practical Concept of Freedom from the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
Previous Article in Special Issue
Hegel’s Souls: Aristotle, Kant, and the Climax of Life
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues

by
Henryk Anzulewicz
1 and
Athanasios Rinotas
2,*
1
Albertus-Magnus-Institut, Adenauerallee 17, 53111 Bonn, Germany
2
IMT Lucca Alti Studi, Piazza S. Francesco, 19, 55100 Lucca, Italy
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Philosophies 2025, 10(5), 108; https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108
Submission received: 7 November 2024 / Revised: 14 September 2025 / Accepted: 16 September 2025 / Published: 27 September 2025
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Ancient and Medieval Theories of Soul)

Abstract

Aristotle’s theory of soul was a hot topic in the Late Middle Ages and it sparked a great series of debates with serious theological and philosophical implications. The medieval commentators of Aristotle played a crucial role in the dissemination of these debates since their explanations and commentaries on Aristotle’s theory of soul served as a springboard for further discussions. One of the most important medieval commentators of Aristotle was Albert the Great (ca 1200–1280) who dealt extensively with the topic of soul and its connection with the doctrine of intellect. Albert discussed the subject of soul not only in the Aristotelian commentaries but also in many genuine works of his which delineated Albert’s theory of soul in great detail. This paper will primarily focus on two works of Albert, De homine and Liber de natura et origine animae; it aims to provide a coherent account of Albert’s early theory of soul and to shed some light on important hermeneutical issues that derive from these two works.

1. Introduction

The problem of soul forms the doctrinal focal point of life sciences in the natural philosophy of Albert the Great. This applies not only to his writings on psychology and psychophysiology in general, such as the commentaries on Aristotle’s works De Anima and the so-called Parva Naturalia, but also specifically to his botanical, zoological, anthropological, and intellectual–theoretical writings. In these, Albert reflects on the principles, the foundations, the prerequisites, and the processes of life in all its biological and intellectual manifestations and stages. The reception of the corpus Aristotelicum provided Albert with the key natural philosophical textual foundation and the methodological tools to develop a Peripatetic theory of soul, mediated by Platonic–Neoplatonic elements and biblical Christian faith. He devoted more attention and space to this issue in his works than any of his contemporaries, including Thomas Aquinas [1,2,3]. The topic of soul is the subject of several writings in the corpus of Albert, the series of which begins with the two-part Summa de creaturis—specifically its anthropological part De homine—which synthesizes knowledge about humanity at the intersection of theology and metaphysics, natural philosophy, and natural science [4].1 Also worth mentioning are Albert’s reflections on the soul of man after death in his work De resurrectione, which serves as a commentary on the eschatological part of Peter Lombard’s Sententiae, written partly immediately before the Summa de creaturis and partly concurrently with it.2 Additionally, there are the Quaestio de origine animae, Quaestio de intellectu animae, Quaestiones de visione Dei in patria, De dotibus sanctorum in patria, De sensibus corporis gloriosi and Quaestio de aureola, all from the author’s collection of questions [5]. The work De homine, however, is largely a commentary on Aristotle’s De Anima and his psychophysiological writings (Parva Naturalia), insofar as these were available to Albert in Latin translations in the first half of the 13th century.3 Furthermore, it contains a two-part treatise on the intellect and its object, with each part titled De differentia intellectuum and De differentia intelligibilis. A few years later, Albert revisited all of Aristotle’s writings commented on De homine, including the treatise De intellectu et intelligibili, in the form of paraphrases, and thoroughly reworked the intellectual–theoretical treatise from the ground up [6]. Following the psychological, psychophysiological, and intellectual–theoretical part of De homine, there are discussions on the topic of soul in Albert’s commentaries on the Sententiae of Peter Lombard (Book I [7] and Book II [8]),4 as well as in his commentary on the Neoplatonically influenced theological work of Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, De divinis nominibus [9],5 and further questions, partly compiled from his early works and transmitted in the Summa theologiae, Book II [10].6 In these writings, Albert reflects on soul from a theological–systematic standpoint. With the beginning of his commentary on Peter Lombard’s Sententiae, he develops the epistemological doctrine of theology and draws a clear boundary between the epistemic orders of theology and philosophy, which is considered a pioneering achievement of historical significance in the theory of science [11,12].7
Albert’s philosophical works on the theory of soul date to the period after theology had been established as a science according to the expanded concept of science in Aristotle and after its separation from philosophy. The first philosophical treatises on soul appear in Albert’s lectures on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Super Ethica, Book I, lecture 15, which he likely held at the Dominican studium generale in Cologne, between 1250 and 1252, after his commentaries on Peter Lombard’s Sententiae and the corpus Dionysiacum [13,14,15].8 The core of his soul theory from a life sciences perspective is found in his psychological, psychophysiological, botanical, and zoological commentaries [16,17,18,19,20,21,22].9 Also noteworthy are Liber de natura et origine animae [23] and the intellectual–theoretical treatises De intellectu et intelligibili and De unitate intellectus, which are not commentaries but independent creations of Albert [24,25].
Without a doubt, Albert’s approach to the topic of soul has attracted the interest of many scholars and there is a good deal of scholarship connected to this subject. In what follows, we limit ourselves to a discussion of some hermeneutical issues of Albert’s theory of soul, while this discussion will be associated and in conversation with the exegetical and structural framework of exitus–perfectio–reductio. Specifically, our contribution focuses on Albert’s genetic conception of the soul in light of the hermeneutical structure of reflection exitus–perfectio–reductio, which is characteristic of his thought and work as a whole and which we will consider on the basis of the Aristotelian–Averroist theory of the inchoatio formarum, as laid out by Albert in the first treatise of De natura et origine animae, the textual foundation of our study. With his theory of the inchoatio formarum, which Albert uses for the genetic interpretation of the human soul, he explicitly distances himself from Avicenna’s competing concept of the dator formarum, already in his Sentences commentary (2.1.12, ed. Borgnet, 34a–b) and in several places in his commentary on De divinis nominibus of Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite (e.g., Super Dionysium De divinis nominibus, ed. P. Simon, 1, 15, 23–64; 2, 72, 36–73, 62). This is the main reason for Avicenna’s absence in the first treatise of De natura et origine animae and in our contribution, in which the human soul is presented genetically in light of Albert’s theory of the inchoatio formarum and the hermeneutical, Neoplatonic structure of reflection exitus–perfectio–reductio reflection (adapted by Pseudo-Dionysius from Proclus and transmitted to Albert). Therefore, we will discuss hermeneutical issues pertaining to soul’s “course of life” from the moment it enters the human body until it leaves it.
Taken together, all the aforesaid writings pertaining to Albert’s theory of soul illustrate not only the breadth of Albert’s engagement with the problem of the soul but also the methodological and hermeneutical challenges involved in interpreting his position. Yet for the purposes of this study, it is neither possible nor necessary to account for the entire corpus. Instead, we concentrate on two key works—De homine and Liber de natura et origine animae—because they mark the transition from Albert’s early synthesis to his mature philosophical account. By reading these texts through the lens of the hermeneutical scheme of exitus–perfectio–reductio, we can trace how Albert conceptualizes the soul’s origin, perfection, and return and thereby clarify some central issues in his interpretation of Aristotelian psychology within a Christian framework.

2. Concept and Origin of the Rational Soul in Albert’s Early Work

With the definition of soul as a substance, Albert begins the soul-theoretical part of his anthropological synthesis in his De homine, which belongs to the early writings of this author.10 In this work, he presents and discusses the most well-known theological and philosophical definitions of soul in the scholastic tradition of the first half of the 13th century.11 The focus is on the “anima humana” and its sensory and vegetative faculties and on the souls of non-human animals and plants. The fundamental question aims at determining the soul in terms of its substance and nature, and it is initially approached by following the theological sources and authorities of Pseudo-Augustine (De spiritu et anima), Pseudo-Remigius (Nemesius of Emesa, De natura hominis), John of Damascus (De fide orthodoxa), and Pseudo-Bernard of Clairvaux (William of St. Thierry, Epistula ad fratres de Monte-Dei). All these authors, except William of St. Thierry, define soul as an incorporeal substance connected to the body, while William of St. Thierry describes it as “an incorporeal thing, receptive to reason, adapted to the body for its animation.”12 The distinction and discussion of soul as an incorporeal substance and res lead Albert to a categorical definition and systematic classification of soul as a concept (ratio) in the domain of logic in terms of difference, as a natural thing (res secundum quod habet esse in natura) in the domain of natural philosophy, and as a substance separate from the body (secundum quod est substantia non comparata ad corpus generabile et corruptibile) in the domain of metaphysics.13
Before Albert proceeds to the discussion of the definitions of soul and its parts or faculties, as handed down through Aristotle’s De anima and the Parva Naturalia, in his early work De homine in the form of questions (Quaestiones), he similarly addresses some definitions of soul which are considered relevant in the scholastic tradition and which he declares to be philosophical.14 Among these, he considers the definitions attributed to Plato and Seneca, as well as the definition by Alfred of Sareshel, along with its philosophical-historical and doctrinal context. If we take a closer and comprehensive look at Albert’s view of soul in his early anthropological writings and compare it with the more developed forms in his philosophical works, we find nearly all the essential elements of his most mature soul-theoretical work, which, as mentioned, he presented in Liber de natura et origine animae. If we trace the development of the teachings back from this work, we notice several significant differences from the early works, which reveal transformations in both form and content.15 These differences are externally evident in the shift from the literary genre of Quaestio, which Albert used as a method for interpreting Aristotle’s De anima and Parva naturalia in teaching and in the written composition of De homine, to the paraphrasing with extended explanations of the source material in the commentaries on these works of Aristotle. Albert often organizes his more extensive discussions, which go beyond the source texts, into separate digression chapters.
Although the soul theory of the early work differs significantly in literary form from Liber de natura et origine animae, which is written as a treatise, and also differs in its sources and theological–systematic approach, the hermeneutical framework of the teaching structure remains essentially the same. In contrast to the commentaries, to which De homine largely belongs as a question-based commentary on Aristotle’s De anima and Parva naturalia, Liber de natura et origine animae follows no source text. It therefore most clearly expresses Albert’s original thinking, inspired by the Peripatetics, and the mature form of his philosophical theory of soul. The detachment of the treatise from its sources allowed Albert to develop Aristotle’s philosophical theory of soul, which he largely assimilated and followed, according to his own discretion. He expanded it by determining the nature and mode of knowledge of the soul separated from the body by death, and elaborated the final segment of his hermeneutical, onto-theologically grounded reflection structure on the understanding of reality as exitus–perfectio–reductio, here applied to the soul [34,35,36,37,38].16
Against the backdrop of Aristotle’s natural philosophy, which focuses on the soul in the body and lacks a clear view of the transcendent origin, immortality, and fate of the soul separated from the body by death, Albert was already faced with the task in his early work De homine of identifying Aristotle’s approaches to these questions and developing them in harmony with the positions of biblical Christian faith. From the corpus Aristotelicum, he derived two philosophically significant indications of the divine origin of the “anima rationalis”, more precisely the intellect, which he regarded as rational evidence for the theological doctrine of the soul’s creation by God.17
Albert found the first indication of the divine origin of the human soul in Aristotle’s work De generatione animalium II 3 (736b28–29), which he had in a Latin translation from Arabic by Michael Scotus, included in the corpus of zoological works of the philosopher under the collective title De animalibus. From the wording of the mentioned passage in the Latin translation, Albert understood that “only the intellect enters (into the embryo) from outside” and that “it alone is divine because its activity in no way involves a bodily function.”18 Based on this statement, and on “the view of all the saints, philosophers, and natural scientists that the vegetative, sensory, and rational faculties in humans are one substance, one soul, and one act,” Albert affirms that the origin of the human soul, due to its divine power, lies in an external giver. This distinguishes it from the vegetative and sensory faculties of plants and sensory beings, which are generated from the material of the plant seed and through the influence of the heavenly forces, or from the material with which the male’s seed substantiates and moves them.19 Albert also derives philosophical arguments for the divine nature of the intellect and its transcendent origin, its separation from matter, and its indestructibility in De homine from Aristotle’s work De anima I 4 (408b18–19), connecting them with the interpretations of Avicenna and Averroes.20
Albert derived the second indication, attributed to Aristotle and linked to the first, regarding the divine origin of the human soul, from the pseudepigraph De causis proprietatum elementorum, which in the Middle Ages was considered part of the corpus Aristotelicum. He notes that, unlike in plants and all non-human animals, the soul in humans does not arise from any seed but is created by God within the body. God is its origin, and it is introduced into the body through creation, as expressed in Aristotle’s statement in the first chapter of the work On the Causes of the Properties of the Elements: “When the male’s seed is poured into the womb of the woman, it is cooked by the warmth of the womb and mixed with her blood until a lump forms; then it is shaped, and at God’s command, the spirit of life arises within it.”21
Albert summarizes the core of his creationist view of the origin of the human soul in De homine as follows: “We say that God creates the soul by infusing it, and He infuses it by creating it; anything else claimed in this regard we consider nonsense.”22 The substrate for the infusion of the soul, according to Albert, is a developed and viable embryo (corpus iam organizatum). The origin of the vegetative and sensory soul forms in the developed embryo before the addition of the rational soul seems, in Albert’s understanding, to oscillate between a successive and a simultaneous ensoulment with the entry of the rational soul.23 His above-quoted statement conveys a sense of ambivalence. Albert rejects as a plausible solution the idea, as attributed to Augustine, that the soul created by God exists prior to the body, which would imply a universal pre-existence of human souls. While Albert appears inclined toward the idea of simultaneous ensoulment of the embryo, he also allows for the possibility of a mediating path between the two extreme positions. According to this view, the “anima rationalis” enters a developed embryo; in this respect, the material principle takes temporal precedence over the soul’s principle. However, Albert attributes to the soul a twofold priority over the body, of a higher order than that of time—namely, the priority of substance and of concept. In other words, the soul has an ontological and logical precedence. This twofold priority of the rational soul over the simple temporal priority of the embryo’s material corresponds to the philosophical coordinates by which Albert formulates and explains his creationist view of the soul’s genesis in De homine—its creation by God out of nothing within the body.24

3. Hermeneutic Aspects Concerning Albert’s Development on His Teaching on the Topic of Soul

A. In Albert’s synthesis De creaturis, systematically embedded in creation theology and essentially based on Aristotle and his Arabic–Islamic commentators concerning the view of the soul in the body and the intellect, the first two segments of his hermeneutical, onto-theologically grounded reflection structure—exitus–perfectio–reductio—are explicated. The focus is thus on the emergence of the soul from the transcendent origin and the first completion corresponding to the soul–body nature of human beings as the prerequisite for its self-responsible perfectio. Albert understands this second perfectio as an intellectual and virtuous, dianoetic and ethical realization of the human being as a human, pursued through experience and study under contingent conditions, i.e., in time, space, and matter.25 The final segment of this structure, the return of the soul to its origin (reductio), is treated by Albert from a theological perspective in the treatise De resurrectione, which, along with the treatises De sacramentis and De incarnatione and the subsequent Summa de creaturis, belongs to his early writings. This part is later addressed in the Sententiae Commentary, Book IV, as well as in the Quaestio de visione Dei in patria, the Quaestio de sensibus corporis gloriosi and the Quaestio de aureola [5]; it is absent from the unfinished Summa theologiae [45,46].26
Two further features that characterize the early work and are of significantly greater hermeneutical relevance than the difference concerning literary genre and the scientific-systematic classification of the topics of the doctrine of soul into logic, natural philosophy, and metaphysics are: on the one hand, the yet-to-be-clarified conception of theology as a science and its relationship to philosophy, and, on the other hand, the possibilities and limitations of philosophical knowledge regarding the nature of the human soul, its state, and its completion after death.
As noted at the beginning, De homine dates from Albert’s period before the scientific-theoretical foundation of theology as a science and its separation from philosophy. In his early work, Albert places natural philosophy and natural sciences at the service of theology and develops a theological–philosophical synthesis that becomes a unified science of soul.27 His epistemic reductionism explains why, in the discussion of definitions of soul in De homine, theologians appear first, followed by philosophers, including Plato and the thinkers Seneca and Alfred of Sareshel, who are more inclined towards Plato than Aristotle, and finally Aristotle and his Arabic–Islamic commentators, Avicenna and Averroes. The distinction and separation of theological and philosophical definitions and theories of soul in De homine is an initial step towards a systematic scientific demarcation between theology and philosophy. For the time being, he does not aim for a scientifically–theoretically grounded separation of the discourses. In his subsequent explanations of soul definitions and theoretical concepts, he assumes a permeability peculiar to both theology and philosophy, whose epistemological permissibility he later grants to theology as a science when developing the science of theology at the beginning of the Sententiae Commentary. He passes over Plato’s conception of soul as a substance per se existing with a reference to the equivalence of the discussions of this determination of soul by theologians.28 The doctrinal focus and main content of the early anthropological work are made up of the Aristotelian psychology and psychophysiology, enriched by Arabic–Islamic and Jewish sources. From a philosophy-systematic perspective, although the Aristotelian parts of De homine constitute the main part of the work, hermeneutically–structurally they cover only the middle portion of Albert’s theory of soul, which begins with a theological–Platonic structural section and ends with reflections on the soul in the body, the original state of man, and his immortality. The questions regarding the soul after its separation from the body by death, as noted above, are already addressed by Albert in the treatise De resurrectione;29 he will revisit them in the Sententiae Commentary, Book IV.
B. In the presentation and development of the philosophical theory of soul in his natural philosophical writings, Albert approaches things differently than in his early work, with two distinct methods being observed. One is typical for the commentaries with few exceptions, which begins with a scientific-theoretical prologue to the respective discipline—here to the foundation of natural philosophical “scientia de anima” and in the middle of the zoological commentary De animalibus in a separate chapter on “scientia de animalibus”—followed by a paraphrase of the source with detailed explanations and content expansions through digression chapters. In this way, Albert presents Aristotle’s views on the soul, its powers, and functions in the body based on his work De anima and the small natural philosophical treatises of psychophysiological content (Parva naturalia). He applies the same method to Aristotle’s zoology, with the difference that the scientific theory of this discipline is presented not at the beginning of the commentary but, due to its source, in the middle of it (De animalibus XI).
The other approach is characteristic of Albert’s own creations [23,24,25], in which he freely develops his natural philosophical, metaphysically grounded theory of the origin and nature of the soul in the body and separated from the body by death without being bound to a source. He conveys Aristotle’s definition of the soul as “forma and actus corporis” with the Platonic conception of the soul as a substance per se existing. He supplements Aristotle’s teaching on the separateness and immortality of the intellect by opening the epistemic perspective of the doctrine to the post-mortem mode of being and activity of the soul and elaborates on it in the sense of the Peripatetic tradition.

4. Transformations in Albert’s Conception of the “Anima Rationalis”

The list of works in which Albert treated the doctrine of soul, mentioned in the introduction, is extensive. The earliest presentation of this is outlined in broad strokes in the previous section through the anthropological synthesis provided by the early work De homine. This early work represents the starting point of the development of the doctrine, which reaches its peak in Liber de natura et origine animae. Looking back from this work at the development of Albert’s doctrine of soul, it can be seen that De homine already contains or outlines the essential components and approaches of his theories on the soul and indicates their further development. We have highlighted that there were some formal and content-related shifts and transformations that give the early and late works on the doctrine of soul their respective individual character. In the following, we will address some of these shifts and transformations from the end of the development and clarify the most mature form of Albert’s views.
In general, it should be noted that Albert’s philosophical theory of soul in Liber de natura et origine animae corresponds in content and fundamental structure with the section on the doctrine of the soul in the Summa de creaturis but no longer deals with the various definitions of the soul and the individual powers of its faculties. However, the a posteriori view makes the hermeneutic structure of exitus–perfectio–reductio, which was already valid in De homine but not yet fully implemented, more apparent.30 This is because De homine is part of Albert’s theological–systematic writings, which are based on the Sententiae of Peter Lombard and conclude with the work De resurrectione. The subject of this work corresponds hermeneutically to the structural part reductio and is accordingly treated by Albert in the early work, while this segment of the hermeneutic structure in Liber de natura et origine animae corresponds to Treatise II. In a structural comparison of the works, it should be noted that Liber de natura et origine animae and De homine, including De resurrectione, implement the same hermeneutic-structural concept under different scientific-systematic orders. The separation of theology and philosophy, which Albert established on the basis of principles and scientific theory at the beginning of the Sententiae commentary, had immediate consequences for the conceptual, substantive, and methodological aspects of analogous structures in the doctrine of soul. The heterogeneity of the principles of theology and philosophy as sciences no longer allowed for a synthesis of theological and philosophical knowledge in the sense of a unified science, which was characteristic of the early work. With this scientific-theoretical rupture, theology and philosophy were designated as autonomous sciences and confined to their respective domains. This limitation was asymmetric in that theological subjects and arguments from philosophy were fundamentally excluded, whereas theology retained the unrestricted right to employ philosophy.31 Albert’s stringent delineation of the boundaries of philosophy in relation to theology concerning knowledge about the immortality of the “anima rationalis” and its state after separation from the body through death is evident in his lectures on the Nicomachean Ethics from the early 1250s. He writes there:
“Philosophically, there can be no sufficient knowledge as to whether the souls of the deceased survive death. Even if they do survive, nothing philosophical can be known about their state and their relation to what happens to us; this is known only through a higher, infused, non-natural light, which is the habitus of faith.”32
Less than ten years after the editing of the Cologne lectures on the Nicomachean Ethics, Albert wrote Liber de natura et origine animae, a philosophical work inspired by Aristotle and the Peripatetics as well as the Platonic–Neoplatonic tradition, which, unlike Super Ethica, is not a commentary work. He dedicates the second treatise of the work to “the nature of soul not connected with the body, insofar as it exists in itself after being separated from the body through death.” His earlier skepticism expressed in the Ethics lectures about the possibility of a philosophical understanding of the immortality of the human soul, its state after death, and its relationship to the here and now has been evidently overcome by his turn to the philosophical tradition of Plato, his engagements with ancient Greek philosophers of various kinds, and the Judeo-Arabic–Islamic and Greek Peripatetics. For the chapter on the postmortem perfection of the soul through the intelligibilia, he begins in Liber de natura et origine animae by announcing that he will only treat those matters about which more probable statements can be made and philosophically proven. He expresses this as follows:
“After all this has been carefully considered, we will discuss what can naturally be said with greater probability. And we will now mention only what can be philosophically proven.”33
Albert’s announcement of a purely philosophical discussion of the perfectio of the “anima rationalis” after the death of the human being, which was new to the Latin tradition, is only partially surprising. He addressed the immortality of the human soul, both theologically and philosophically, in his early work De homine and in the Sententiae commentary. A reflection of his views from the early work can be seen in the Summa theologiae II. In a digression in the commentary on De anima (III.3.13), he argues that the soul does not die with the death of the body; he also rejects the pre-existence of the soul in relation to the body. The question of the individual immortality of the “anima rationalis” is touched upon in the commentary on De morte et vita and in the writings De intellectu et intelligibili, De unitate intellectus, and De XV problematibus. In Liber de natura et origine animae, Treatise II, Chapter 6, he presents eight logically compelling proofs of immortality.34 A philosophical theory of the postmortem perfection of the human soul through the intelligible (intelligibile per se) according to virtue and its work, which is executed by the intellect perfected in the body through the intelligible “cum tempore et continuo”, is laid out by Albert in the commentary on De anima, Book III, Treatises 3, Chapters 6 and 11, and in Liber de natura et origine animae. Parallel to his theological–philosophical synthesis of the illumination theory developed in the Sententiae Commentary (I.5), following Augustine and Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita and in line with the Peripatetic “intellectus agens” doctrine, he now adopts a theory of the soul’s enlightenment by separated intelligence and three kinds of intelligibles, which pave the way for the soul’s ascent to the highest intelligible and enable the perfection in contemplative bliss:
“We say that although the rational soul does not originate from intelligence, it nonetheless receives illuminations from intelligence. Since there are three kinds of intelligibles for the soul, namely the one related to time and space and that which is intelligible by its nature, the first is received together with sensory perception, the second with imagination, and the third through the simple intellect. And there is an order of intelligibles, in that through the intelligible associated with time, the soul reaches what is associated with space, and through what is associated with space, it reaches what is intelligible by itself.”35
Albert understands the perfection of the soul as a progressive process of acquiring knowledge, which is already grasped through the reception of intelligible light by study and scientific understanding during one’s lifetime. The individual is responsible for this perfection in that it pertains to the natural, temporal, spatial, and material realization of his ethical and dianoetical virtues. This realization of virtues during life and the acquisition of intelligible light through the intellect is presented by Albert as the condition for the possibility of postmortem intellectual perfection and human bliss. The path of acquiring intelligible light and perfection corresponds, according to him, to the nature of the human being as a human and is achieved through the study of natural philosophy, mathematics, and metaphysics. He subsumes all other scientific disciplines, including moral philosophy (i.e., ethics and politics), under these three areas of theoretical study, which he summarizes with the term ‘philosophia realis’.36 He emphasizes the individual’s responsibility for their state of perfection and the resulting bliss. Neglecting intellectual perfection during one’s embodied state leaves the “anima separata” incapable of receiving the intelligible light without the mediation of the sensory organs, to which it no longer has access. It remains in eternal darkness:
“The opposite applies, however, to souls that neglect this perfection of the intellect. Just as the intelligible is moved towards the possible intellect by the light of the active intellect, so it is darkened and contracted by the mixture with matter, movement, and size, by the ‘here and now’, and the rational soul receives it only as it is ‘here and now’. It is therefore not free but shadowed and material, and thus the soul receiving it in this manner does not receive any light from it at all. Consequently, the soul has no access to the true intelligible, in which the soul perfectly shines, and thus such an intellect deprived of all light remains dark within itself and is unable to shine after death. As we have said previously, the possible intellect is only capable of receiving light that is truly the light of the intellect when it is strengthened by the lights received from sensory perception or with sensory perception and from imagination or with imagination. A return to sensory perception and imagination is, however, impossible after death; thus, such an intellect is incapable of illumination and remains in eternal darkness, which is deprivation and withdrawal of intellectual light.”37
Albert develops his philosophical theory of the perfection of the “anima separata” and its bliss in Liber de natura et origine animae and in the commentary on Metaphysics, in the work De intellectu et intelligibili, Book II, as well as in the second commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics, without relating it to his theological conception of beatitudo and contemplatio, which he has outlined in the Sententiae Commentary, Book III Dist. 34 Art. 2 and Book IV Dist. 49 Art. 6, as well as in his first commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics. In the Sententiae Commentary, Book IV, he discusses the difference between the theological, primarily inspired by Augustine and Boethius, view of “beatitudo secundum statum perfectionis viae and secundum statum perfectionis patriae” on the one hand, and the philosophical, as reflected by Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics and elaborated by his Greek and Arabic commentators, theory of the twofold bliss, namely “felicitas moralis” and “felicitas intellectualis”. He did not make a sharp distinction between beatitudo and felicitas. Instead, he considered beatitudo as the overarching term compared to the concept of felicitas and acknowledged its multifaceted nature in philosophical and theological interpretations concerning the status viae and the status patriae.38 He excluded an equivocation between the theological and philosophical interpretations of bliss in favor of an analogous relationship between the two. By considering bliss in the proper sense as conforming with the philosophical view of human perfection according to moral and intellectual virtue in the sense of Aristotle,39 he seems to regard the difference between the philosophical and theological views of mental bliss as less pronounced than he later expresses, for example, in the first commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics:
“It must be said that theological contemplation in some respects coincides with philosophical contemplation and in some respects differs from it; they are therefore not entirely identical. The similarity lies in the fact that in theological contemplation, there is also an unimpeded intellectual insight into the spiritual, despite the passions of the subject and doubts stemming from faith directed towards resting in God, which represents the highest bliss. However, it differs in terms of habitus, goal, and object: in terms of habitus, because theological contemplation occurs through the light infused by God; the philosopher, on the other hand, relies on the acquired habitus of wisdom. Regarding the goal, theological contemplation sets the ultimate goal in the contemplation of God in the patria, while the philosopher sets it in the vision through which he sees in via. Also, concerning the object—not insofar as it pertains to substance but in terms of mode—the philosopher contemplates God as a conclusion of a proof, whereas the theologian views Him as a being above understanding and intellect. Therefore, the mode of contemplation is different because the philosopher has the certainty of the proof upon which he relies, while the theologian relies on the first truth itself and not on a rational argument, even if he had one. This is why the theologian wonders, while the philosopher does not.”40
In his first commentary on the Ethics, Albert tended to highlight the differences between Aristotle’s positions and the theological, Platonic, and Neoplatonic interpretations of the same subjects, as seen in the question of the immortality of the human soul and the relationship of the “anima separata” to the here and now. In his theological commentaries, he sometimes adopted a critical stance towards philosophy, which can be understood as a subtle critique of Aristotle and a reference to the limits of philosophical knowledge. In such cases, he posited a theologically compatible solution by introducing the aforementioned notion of wonder. This can be seen as a counterpart to the admiratio mentioned by Aristotle at the beginning of the Metaphysics as the starting point of philosophy itself. Albert places this at the end of philosophical knowledge of God in terms of transcending and elevating the concluding reason to the divine:
“One must say that elevation (sursum agi) happens in two ways: either absolutely, as in what is concluded by proof, and in this way, the philosophers cannot be elevated to the divine; or through wonder, by proving something that reason cannot grasp, and in this way, they should be elevated to the divine. For although philosophy does not prove anything against the divine wisdom delivered by faith, it does not reach it; it has a limit up to which it can reach, and it still knows that it does not grasp the whole. Therefore, it should admire it, not oppose it, as it is philosophically proven that in God there are perfections of all kinds, that in Him is the highest simplicity, that He is His own act, and many other things of this sort that seem incompatible with the principles of reason, from which one progresses with other things. Hence, the philosopher says that the first cause surpasses language and reason.”41
Albert significantly expands the limits of philosophical knowledge in Liber de natura et origine animae and abandons his previously held Platonic view of postmortem knowledge through the forma ad res imprinted in the “anima rationalis” at creation. As has already been made clear, the concepts of soul and intellect are tightly connected in Albert’s work. Yet, Albert did not just see the doctrine of intellect as an integral part of Aristotle’s theory of soul and he went a step further by considering the doctrine of intellect as a separate scientia belonging to natural philosophy. In this regard, Albert seems to be quite innovative since he is the first medieval thinker who acknowledges the theory of intellect as an independent field and thus places the scientia de intellectu and intelligibili as a self-standing “scientia” within his natural philosophical system. Albert’s theory of intellect describes a meticulous and holistic path towards the perfection of man, while it also creates a cognitive nexus between this world and the afterlife, all of which result in justifying Albert’s famous dictum: “Man as man is the intellect alone” (homo inquantum homo solus est intellectus) [39,59].
Liber de natura et origine animae was written around 1258 which means that it discusses Albert’s mature philosophical views on the soul–intellect nexus. In this book, as we have already explained, Albert clearly argues that the cognitive capacity of the “anima separata” is tightly dependent on the intellectual perfection that one can attain during life. This “intellectual perfection” is achieved through our gradual understanding of contingent things of knowledge, a process which entails the notion of abstraction. Albert describes the attaining of knowledge through abstraction as follows:
“Another way is, according to the above statements, that the soul, now having an enlightened and strengthened intellect, can by itself reach the intellect of things. For we see that the intellect can understand things by abstracting from the phantasm while it is in the body, and when strengthened, it can reach the intellect of divine things. And in this way, we will say that just as it now is ordered towards things and therefore abstracts from the phantasms of things through its light, so, when separated, it can wholly apprehend things outside the soul, abstracting from them through its light and understanding them. And then every such intellect is determined through its comparison with the intelligible, just as now it is determined through the reflection of its intelligible upon the imagination and sense. And in this way, among separated intellects, Dionysius says there is knowledge of sensible things without sensation and immaterially. Nor is anything found that contradicts this position.”42
In order to understand the excerpt above one should take the following into consideration: for Albert, the notion of intellectual perfection is associated with the absorption of intelligible light, where the latter is augmented through our understanding of contingent things. This means that the more one understands contingent things and reality, the more intelligible light is absorbed. This act is crucial for human intellect since the process of “intellectual perfection” allows the possible intellect (intellectus possibilis) to develop into an intellectus adeptus and thus human intellect possesses the capacities of intellectuality and intelligibility. In our source, the intellectual abstraction that Albert refers to depends on achieving the state of intellectus adeptus. When achieved, the “anima separata” will be enabled to directly abstract the formal content of knowledge through perception of the worldly things.43 Yet, the separated soul possesses knowledge of things in a non-sensory and immaterial way, as Albert notes by evoking Pseudo-Dionysius. Thus, Albert underscores the importance of intellectus adeptus and it is due to intellectus adeptus that the separated soul has direct access to the sensory things, without having need of the intermediate step of sensory perception [62,63,64].
By adopting the model of intellectual abstraction, Albert simultaneously abandons the exegetical model of formae ad res which he used in his early works. At the end of Liber de natura et origine animae, Albert provides the reasons for rejecting the formae ad res model. According to him, these forms cannot provide ontologically and epistemologically valid knowledge of the objects of this world because the formae ad res do not have their origins rooted in the worldly things and thus these forms cannot become ontologically instantiated in these objects. Albert admits that some philosophers tried to overcome this difficulty by proposing universal forms of knowledge which Albert rejected as “absurd” since these universal forms could enable only a general and potential knowledge rather than a specific knowledge of things.44 On the contrary, the model of intellectual abstraction can render a human capable of “specific knowledge of things” and Albert explains its workings through an analogy:
“If someone were to ask what commonality the active intellect has with the object upon which it acts through abstraction, it must be said that the light of the active intellect shares a similarity with the forms of things, comparable to the relationship between physical light and colors. For certain embodied lights are colors, and in a similar way, certain embodied lights of the active intellect are the forms of things, as previously indicated, where it was shown that the active intellect is the first mover and actor in all of nature. This commonality suffices for abstraction; specifically, in the way that what is abstracted exists potentially, the abstracting intellect exists in actuality and is naturally alike to itself. And these principles suffice for such an activity as the abstraction of forms, which is nothing other than their removal from material existence and their reception in accordance with simple being.”45
In Albert’s view, the separated soul’s perfected state (intellectus adeptus) allows for a direct abstraction. This is possible because the intellectus agens relates to the forms in a similar way that colors relate to light. In this way, the perfected separated soul can transform all forms from their material into their intelligible mode which is in turn more suited to the separated soul’s nature. Consequently, Albert establishes an ontologically and epistemologically valid way of knowing things, while he also secures an unmediated way of knowing things.

5. Conclusions

Our short analysis on Albert’s theory of soul has primarily focused on some of his early works and Liber de natura et origine animae which contains the Dominican master’s mature views on the topic. Limited as the scope of this analysis might be, it manages to clearly present the multifaceted and dynamic character of Albert’s thought with respect to the topic of soul. Albert clearly attempted to account for a holistic theory of soul which would address the intricacies of soul from the moment we are born until the moment of soul’s separation through death and its perfected state in afterlife. In this regard, his scheme of exitus-perfectio-reductio served as a solid basis for addressing different aspects and problems of the theory of the soul. In De homine Albert argued about the origin of soul and explicated the role of God in its creation by following a creationist view. Additionally, Albert used the explanatory model of formae ad res in order to justify our knowledge of things and create a continuity of knowledge between our world and the afterlife. However, the dynamic character of Albert’s theory of soul is best portrayed in his Liber de natura et origine animae. In this book Albert delineates the stages of perfectio and reductio in a meticulous and thorough way as he argues for an “intellectual perfection” of soul in this life which affects, in turn, the cognitive state of soul in the afterlife too, only this perfection does not depend on the formae ad res model but on intellectual abstraction which renders the separated soul capable of directly accessing the forms of things.
This genuine shift in Albert’s approach to the theory of soul provides a unique insight into his system of thought. Albert was a seeker of knowledge and as such he consulted and assimilated many theological and philosophical authorities on the topic of soul. This became evident in both De homine and Liber de natura et origine animae where Albert exhibits knowledge of a great number of sources. Yet what should be mentioned is that Albert’s library was constantly changing and the books he was reading, interpreting and consulting over the years did not remain the same [65]. This gradual enrichment in terms of knowledge played a crucial role in Albert’s conception and realization of his own “intellectual perfection” which contributed to and resulted in a mature account on soul in Liber de natura et origine animae. Thus, Albert’s shift in opinion should not be seen as a surprise or an inconsistency of his work but rather as a practical reflection of the theoretical framework of soul he was working on throughout his life.
As a final remark, it is worth mentioning that Albert’s progression and evolution of theory of soul reflects his personal attitude towards the relation between theology and philosophy. In this regard, Albert conceived of the two fields not as conflicting with but rather as complementing each other. The way Albert treated the terms of beatitudo-felicitas and admiratio in reference to soul shows Albert’s tendency to “bridge” the two fields and demarcate their range of application. As a result, the emerging compatibility between theology and philosophy paved the way for Albert’s holistic theory of soul through the cognitive continuity between this world and the afterlife.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, H.A. and A.R.; methodology, H.A. and A.R.; writing—original draft preparation, H.A. and A.R.; writing—review and editing, H.A. and A.R. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

The present essay is part of the research project: Itineraries of Philosophy and Science from Baghdad to Florence: Albert the Great, his Sources and his Legacies (2023–2025), financed by the Italian Ministry of University and Research (PRIN 2022, 20225LFCMZ), in the framework of the PNRR M4C2 financed by the European Union—Next Generation EU.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Notes

1
The second part of the Summa de creaturis by Albertus Magnus, De homine, is available in the critical edition [4]; the critical edition of the first part of this Summa, transmitted under the title De quattuor coaequaevis, is currently being prepared. Both parts of this double work are available in two early prints and two non-critical complete editions by P. Jammy (Volume 19a, Lyon 1651) and S.C.A. Borgnet (Vol. 34, Paris 1895).
2
More on this below.
3
For the notion of “scientiae naturales” in the work of Albert, see: [6].
4
See: [7] (Lib. I, dist. 3 a. 33–34, pp. 136–141; dist. 8 a. 25–27, pp. 256–261); [8] (Lib. II dist. 17 a. 1–3, pp. 296–302; dist. 18 a. 8, pp. 324–325; dist. 19 a. 1–2, pp. 327–331).
5
See: [9] (c. 4, pp. 202–208).
6
See: [10] (Tr. XII, q. 68–74, pp. 1–57; tr. XIII q. 77, pp. 68–106; tr. XV q. 92–97, pp. 193–222).
7
The literature on this is extensive; see for example: [11], pp. 15–30 and [12].
8
In Albert’s Super Ethica, among the statements relevant to soul theory, there are two treatises on the human soul as a simple form (simplex forma) and on its unity in essence with its faculties. For the critical edition of the text, see [13] (Lib. I lect. 15, pp. 78.62–81.88). For the dating of the work, cf. [14] (pp. VI.11–27); for the doctrinal context and content, see [15] (pp. 81(213)–85(217), 93(225)–94(226)).
9
Among the core works of Albert’s psychological and psychophysiological writings are the commentaries on De anima [16] and on the incompletely available Parva naturalia of Aristotle, whose missing parts Albert reconstructed. Specifically, these are: De nutrimento et nutrito, De sensu et sensato, De memoria et reminiscentia, De somno et vigilia, De spiritu et respiratione, De motibus animalium, De iuventute et senectute, and De morte et vita. Currently, De nutrimento et nutrito, De sensu et sensato, and De memoria et reminiscentia are critically edited [17]; they are fully available in the two non-critical complete editions by P. Jammy, Vol. 5 [18], and A. Borgnet, Vol. 9 [19]. For more details on the manuscripts, sources, and dating of these writings, see Donati [6].
10
See: [4] (pp. 8.26–9.4).
11
Albert does not accept the matter-form composition of form and thus he avoids calling soul the form of the body. Instead, he prefers to define soul as purus actus or perfectio of the body. In De homine [4] ad. 6. 35a Albert says: “melius dicitur actus vel perfectio quam forma.” With respect to this definition, Hasse [26] and Vernier [27] have drawn clear connections between Albert and Avicenna and his De anima, while Dales [28] (p. 91), attributes the aforesaid definition to Aristotle. Given the great number of Avicenna’s quotation in Albert’s De homine, it is safe to ascertain that Albert was well aware of Avicenna’s relevant passage in the De anima [29] (pp. 19–21), which runs as follows: “Deinde dicimus quod omnis forma est perfectio, sed non omnis perfectio forma: magister enim fabricandi perfectio est civitatis et carpentarius lignorum perfectio est navis, nec tamen sunt formae civitatis vel navis. Et cuiuscumque perfectionis est essentia per se separata, ipsa certe non est forma materiae nec in materia: forma etenim quae est in materia, est forma impressa in illa et existens per illam, si consenserint ut perfectio speciei forma vocetur speciei. Sed iam consenserunt in hoc, ut haec res, scilicet anima, comparatione materiae sit forma, comparatione vero totius collectionis sit finis et perfectio, et comparatione movendi, principium efficiens et vis movens. Et quandoquidem sie est, tunc forma significat comparationem ad rem remotissimam ab essentia substantiae quae habet esse per illam, et ad rem propter quam substantia habet esse quod ipsa est et al.ia quae propter ipsam est in potentia, et ad rem cui non comparantur actiones, quae est materia: anima enim forma est ex respectu hoc scilicet quod habet esse in materia; perfectio autem significat comparationem ad rem perfectarn ex qua emanant actiones, quia perfectio est respectu speciei. Clarum est igitur quod, cum in doctrina de anima dicimus quod ipsa est perfectio, hoc plus significat eius intellectum et etiam hoc plus comprehendit omnes species animae undique, et hoc necesse est animae separatae a materia.” For Avicenna’s definition on soul, see [30,31].
12
[4], pp. 9.1–2: “res incorporea rationis capax, vivficando corpori accomodata.”
13
[4], pp. 10.59–11.14; pp. 31.45–50.65–68. Cf. [32] (pp. 23–26 and pp. 95–97, 99).
14
[4], pp. 18–28.
15
This point has also been raised by Dag Nicolaus Hasse [33] (pp. 60–69). Hasse argues that some of Albert’s early opinions on soul are either changed in his later works or assimilated as his own. It is also worth mentioning that Hasse provides a preliminary list of Albert’s references to Avicenna’s De anima which clearly shows a tendency from Albert’s part to significantly mitigate his reliance on Avicenna in his later works. For instance, De homine contains 227 explicit quotations of the Avicennan text, while the De natura et origine animae just three.
16
The first publications on the reconstruction of the thought structure of Albertus Magnus date back to the years 2000–2002, cf. [34,35,36,37]; for a more recent, partial study, cf. [38].
17
For Albert, the human soul is regarded as immaterial, incorruptible and separate substance from the body which yet has a strong dependence on it. Anzulewicz [39] has cogently shown how human soul, as an intellectual substance bears the same aforesaid characteristics, something which led Albert to argue that homo inquantum homo solus est intellectus. It is worth noting that the immateriality, incorruptibility and separability of the soul are also met in Avicenna’s De anima [40] (V 2, pp. 81–101). Both Druart [31] and Heath [41] (pp. 57–79), have argued for the existence of these characteristics of soul in the Avicenna’s relevant theory, while McGinnis [42] (pp. 117–148), and Davidson [43] (pp. 81–86), have discussed these very characteristics through the context of intellective soul.
18
See: [44] (II 3, p. 74): “Et sequitur dicere quod intellectus tantum intrat ex extrinseco et quod ipse solus est divinus, quoniam operatio eius non habet communicationem cum operatione corporali aliquo modo.” Cf. [4] (pp. 83.17–45, esp. pp. 83.36–39).
19
Cf. [4] (pp. 85.24–27): “Dicendum secundum omnes sanctos et philosophos et naturales quod vegetabile, sensibile et rationale sunt in homine substantia una et anima una et actus unus.” [4], (pp. 86.32–38): “in plantis sufficit ad vegetabile materia seminis cum virtute caelesti sine operatione masculi. In brutis autem oportet in materia esse semen masculi, quod substantificat et movet materiam, quia aliter non egrederetur animal sensibile. Sed in hominibus propter divinam virtutem ipsius intellectus exigitur dator extrinsecus ipsius animae.”
20
See: [4] (pp. 73.11–23) with the source references in the critical apparatus of the edition.
21
[4], (pp. 73.24–34): “Quod autem non generetur, sed creetur in corpore secundum Aristotelem, patet in XVI De animalibus, ubi dicit intellectualem animam non esse ab aliquo principio efficiente, quod sit in semine. Quod autem eius principium sit deus, et quod ingreditur per creationem in corpus, patet per haec verba sua quae sunt in primo De causis proprietatum elementorum: ‘Aqua viri quando cadit in matricem mulieris, decoquit eam matrix caliditate sua et commiscetur aqua illa cum sanguine matricis, donec fit frustum; deinde formatur et fit in eo spiritus vitae iussu dei’.”
22
See: [4] p. 71.60–62: “ Dicimus quod deus infundendo creat humanas animas et creando infundit eas, et omnia alia dicta reputamus deliramenta.”
23
Richard Dales [28], (p. 94), has argued that Albert’s position on the matter gets further clarified in his De natura et origine animae. According to Dales, Albert seems to adopt a thesis which is close to Thomas Aquinas as he refers to a “progression of forms” during the embryo’s development. See [23] (Tr. I, Cap. 5, pp. 13–15).
24
Cf. [4], (pp. 67.34–68.6, pp. 71.63–72.43, esp. p. 71.67–72): “Ad auctoritates autem Augustini dicendum quod opinando et opiniones aliorum sequendo talia dicit et non sic sentiendo, ut patet per auctoritates ad oppositum ex eodem loco inductas. Si tamen vellemus distinguere, diceremus quod anima duobus modis prior est corpore et corpus uno modo prius anima; est enim prius substantia et prius ratione, et hoc modo anima est ante corpus, cui dat substantiam et rationem; est etiam prius tempore, et sic corpus est prius anima, quia non infunditur ei nisi iam organizato.”
25
See: [4] p. 410.39–41 (with source references): “anima rationalis non est in corpore nisi ut perficiatur scientia et virtute, ut dicunt sancti et philosophi.” Cf. [8] (II dist. 1 a. 14, p. 41b); [24] (Lib. II c. 12, pp. 46.39–47.26); [16] (Lib. II tr. 3 c.3, pp. 100.13–19): “mutatio potentiae sensitivae ad primam perfectionem ipsius est a generante. Potentiarum enim apprehensivarum quaedam complentur prima perfectione a natura et quaedam per experimentum et studium: a natura quidem sicut potentia sensitiva ad sentire, per experimentum autem et tempus sicut intellectiva.”—Italics indicate words that Albert retained unchanged from the source in his paraphrase of Aristotle’s De anima. [38] (pp. 339–368).
26
See: [45] (Tr. I-IV, pp. 237–354); [46] (IV dist. 43–50, pp. 495–700).
27
In his early work, Albert mentions his reductionist stance towards natural philosophy and its subordination to theology in retrospect to the Summa de creaturis in the Sentences Commentary, Book II, dist. 14 a. 6, see [8] (p. 266b) (the non-critical edition was verified against the manuscripts Berlin, Staatsbibliothek Preussischer Kulturbesitz theol. lat. fol. 320, f. 40ra; Sigüenza, Bibl. del Cabildo 210, f. 203rb): “Alibi etiam disputatum est de ista materia multum et prolixe, et ibi secuti sumus dicta quorundam magistrorum theologiae, qui voluerunt opiniones naturalium ad theologiam reducere …”.
28
See: [4] (p. 18.16): “Circa diffinitionem vero Platonis de hoc quod dicitur ‘substantia incorporea’, supra disputatum est.”
29
See note 22. Cf. [45] (De resurr.).
30
For more on this topic, see: [47] (pp. 388–416).
31
Cf. [13] (Lib. I lect. 7, p. 34.42–44): “scientia, quae est de humanis, est ancilla, quia subservit alii scientiae liberae, quae est philosophia prima, quae est de deo.” [48] (p. 657–661). [49] (pp. 181–185). [50] (Lib. 11 tr. 3 c. 7, pp. 542.25–27): “Theologica autem non conveniunt cum philosophicis in principiis, quia fundantur super revelationem et inspirationem et non super rationem, et ideo de illis in philosophia non possumus disputare.” [51] (Lib. I pars 1 q. 5, pp. 15–22).
32
See: [13] (Lib. I lect. 13, pp. 71.73–79): “hoc quod animae defunctorum remaneant post mortem, non potest per philosophiam sufficienter sciri. Et supposito, quod remaneant, de statu earum et qualiter se habeant ad ea quae circa nos fiunt, omnino nihil sciri per philosophiam potest, sed haec cognoscuntur altiori lumine infuso non naturali, quod est habitus fidei.”
33
See: [23] (Tr. II c. 13, pp. 37.63–66): “Omnibus his diligenter excursis tangemus id quod secundum naturam probabilius dici potest, et non faciemus modo aliquam mentionem nisi tantum de his quae per philosophiam possunt probari.”
34
For citations in the mentioned writings and the secondary sources related to them, see [52].
35
[23] (Tr. II c. 13, pp. 37.66–78): “Dicimus igitur, quod anima rationalis non quidem fit ab intelligentia, tamen ab intelligentia recipit illuminationes. Et cum sit triplex intelligibile ipsius animae, scilicet cum tempore et cum continuo et id quod secundum sui naturam est intelligibile, primum quidem est acceptum cum sensu et secundum cum imaginatione et tertium est per intellectum simplicem acceptum. Et est ordo in intelligibilibus, quoniam per hoc intelligibile quod est cum tempore, venit anima ad id quod est cum continuo, et per id quod est cum continuo, venit ad id quod est per seipsum intelligibile.” [23], (pp. 38.42–52): “His igitur sic determinatis dicimus, quod anima rationalis differt ab intelligentia caelesti, eo quod per intelligibilia, quae sunt cum tempore et continuo, venire habet ad intelligibile, quod secundum esse et essentiam per se est intelligibile, et si est ordo in illis per se intelligibilibus, habet devenire ad primum intelligibile, quod est causa omnium aliorum, et in illo stat sicut in vertice suae sapientiae et contemplationis finalis. Propter quod omnia intelligibilia adminiculantia sunt ad primum intelligibile, sicut dicit Alfarabius et Avempeche.”
36
[50] (Lib. XI Tr. 1 c. 9, pp. 473.10–24): “Cum igitur lumen intellectus et intellectuum, sicut iam dictum est, sparsum sit in omnibus intelligibilibus, primum, quod acquirit intellectus per studium, est collectio intellectuum speculativorum in tribus theoricae partibus, quae sunt physica, mathesis et prima philosophia, sicut a principio huius sapientiae determinavimus, cetera autem quae sunt de rationibus, in grammaticis, quae ministrant intelligibilium signa, et logicis, quae dant inveniendi et accipiendi verum modum, et rhetoricis, quae ex signis aliquid persuasionis eliciunt, et poeticis, quae coniecturare docent ex integumentis. Ethica autem sunt praeparationes ex parte studentis, ne avertatur a concupiscentiis, et hic intellectus sic acceptus est speculativus.” Cf. [53] Lib. X Tr. 2 c. 3, p.628b: “Homini ergo et optimum et delectabilissimum est vita secundum intellectum speculativa: haec enim maxime est homo. Talis igitur homo felicissimus est prima et dignissima felicitate. Secundario autem et ille felix est, qui secundum aliam virtutem quae rationis inquisitivae ultimum est, habet perfectas operationes. Haec autem virtus moralis est, sicut in primo hujus scientiae libro determinatum est: secundum hanc enim sunt operationes humanae. Quaecumque enim ad invicem agimus in commutationibus et necessitatibus et omnimodis actionibus communitatum, justa sunt, vel fortiora, vel temperata.”
37
[23] (Tr. II c.13, pp. 39.24–46): “E contra autem est de his animabus quae hanc negligunt intellectus perfectionem. Sicut enim intelligibile per lumen intellectus agentis movetur ad intellectum possibilem, ita per permixtionem materiae et motus et quantitatis obscuratum et contractum non est nisi hic et nunc, et non accipit ipsum anima rationalis, nisi prout est hic et nunc. Sic autem nec liberum est, sed umbrosum et materiale, et ideo nihil luminis accipit ex ipso taliter accipiens ipsum anima. Propter quod per ipsum non habet viam ad verum intelligibile, in quo perfecte lucet anima, et ideo omni luce destitutus intellectus huiusmodi manet tenebrosus in seipso, nec est irradiabilis hic intellectus post mortem, quoniam sicut in antehabitis diximus, intellectus possibilis non est susceptibilis luminis, quod vere est lumen intellectus, nisi confortatus luminibus his quae a sensu vel cum sensu et ab imaginatione aut cum imaginatione sumuntur. Ad sensum autem et imaginationem impossibilis est regressus post mortem, et ideo talis intellectus impossibilis est ad illuminationem, sed remanet in perpetuis tenebris, quae sunt luminis intellectualis privatio et destitutio.” Cf. [38] (pp. 367–368).
38
Isabelle Moulin [54] has made some connections between Albert and Avicenna regarding the topic of happiness through theological and philosophical contemplation. In her study she argues that Albert and Avicenna share some common ground with respect to happiness through philosophical contemplation but the two authors differ significantly when it comes to the theological one. While Albert is an advocate of the latter by evoking the notion of theophania, Avicenna treats theological contemplation in a rather dismissive way. In his Metaphysica [55], in IX 7, pp. 506–507, he explicitly states: “Opus est ut certificemus hic dispositionem animarum humanarum cum sunt exutae a corporibus suis, ad quam dispositionem perveniunt. Oportet autem te scire quod promissio alia est quae fide recipitur, quia non est via ad probandum eam nisi credendo testimonio prophetae, sicut illa quae est de eo quod habebit corpus apud resurrectionem. Tu autem iam scis delectationes corporum et gaudia quid sunt. Lex enim nostra quam dedit Mahometh ostendit dispositionem felicitatis et miseriae quae sunt secundum corpus. Et alia est promissio quae apprehenditur intellectu et argumentatione demonstrativa, et prophetia approbat; et haec est felicitas et miseria animarum quae probantur argumentationibus, quamvis nostrae aestimationes debiles sint ad imaginandum eas nunc propter causas quas ego ostendam. Sapientibus vero theologis multo maior cupiditas fuit ad consequendum hanc felicitatem quam felicitatem corporum, quae quamvis daretur eis, tamen non attenderunt eam, nec appretiati sunt eam comparatione huius felicitatis quae est coniuncta primae veritati, sicut paulo post ostendam de ea. Igitur faciam sciri dispositionem huius felicitatis, et miseriae quae est ei contraria; corporalis autem felicitas iam assignata est in lege.” For more on Avicenna and afterlife, see Michot [56].
39
[46] (Lib. IV dist. 49 a. 6, p. 674b): “beatitudo dicitur multipliciter, et non aequivoce, sed secundum prius et posterius. Dicitur autem secundum statum perfectionis viae, et secundum statum perfectionis patriae. Secundum statum autem viae dicitur tripliciter, scilicet proprie, large, et per causam. Proprie autem dicitur dupliciter, scilicet secundum virtutem moralem, et secundum virtutem intellectualem: et ideo Aristoteles in Ethicis facit duos libros de felicitate: primum enim fecit de felicitate morali, secundum autem de felicitate intellectuali.” Cf. [53] (Lib. X Tr. 2 c. 3, p. 628b (Text in Note 32)).
40
[57] (Lib. X lect.16, pp. 774.80–775.13): “Dicendum, quod contemplatio theologica in aliquo convenit cum philosophica et in aliquo differt; unde non sunt omnino idem. Convenit enim in hoc quod etiam in theologica est inspectio per intellectum aliquorum spiritualium sine impedimento passionum ex parte subiecti et dubietatis ex parte fidei ordinata ad quiescendum in deo, quod est summa felicitas. Differt autem et in habitu et in fine et in obiecto. In habitu quidem, quia theologica contemplatur per lumen infusum a deo, sed philosophus per habitum sapientiae acquisitum; in fine, quia theologica poni ultimum finem in contemplatione dei in patria, sed philosophus in visione, qua videtur aliquatenus in via; in obiecto etiam non quantum ad substantiam, sed quantum ad modum, quia philosophus contemplatur deum, secundum quod habet ipsum ut quandam conclusionem demonstrativam, sed theologus contemplatur ipsum ut supra rationem et intellectum existentem. Et ideo est diversus modus contemplandi, quia philosophus habet certitudinem demonstrationis, cui innititur, sed theologus innititur primae veritati propter se et non propter rationem, etiamsi habeat ipsam, et ideo theologus miratur, sed non philosophus.”
41
[58] (Epist. septima, pp. 505.25–42): “Dicendum, quod sursum agi in aliquid est dupliciter: aut simpliciter sicut in id quod demonstratione concluditur, et sic philosophi non possunt sursum agi in divina, aut per admirationem, dum probatur aliquid in cuius comprehensionem ratio non potest, et sic oportebat eos sursum agi in divina. Quamvis enim philosophia nihil probet contra divinam veritatem, quam tradit fides, tamen non pertingit ad ipsam, sed habet aliquem terminum, usquequo devenit, et scit se tamen non totum comprehendere, et ideo debet admirari, non impugnare, sicut per philosophiam probatur, quod in deo sunt perfectiones omnium generum et quod in eo est summa simplicitas et quod ipse est sua actio et multa huiusmodi, quae non videntur se posse compati secundum principia rationis, ex quibus proceditur in aliis rebus. Et ideo dicit Philosophus, quod ‘causa prima est supra narrationem’ et rationem.”
42
[23] (pp. 43.23–40): “Alius autem modus est secundum supra dicta, quod videlicet anima iam illuminatum et confortatum intellectum habens per se possit ad intellectus rerum. Videmus enim, quod intellectus potest ad res intelligendas abstrahendo a phantasmate modo, dum est in corpore, et confortatus potest ad intellectum divinorum. Et hoc modo dicemus, quod sicut modo ordinatur super res et ideo lumine suo abstrahit a phantasmatibus rerum, ita separatus omnino potest super ipsas res extra animam existentes, ut lumine suo abstrahat ab ipsis rebus et intelligat eas, et tunc omnis talis intellectus determinatur per sui intelligibilis ad rem comparationem, sicut et nunc determinatur per reflexionem sui intelligibilis ad imaginationem et sensum. Et hoc modo apud intellectus separatos magnus dicit Dionysius esse rerum sensibilium cognitiones insensibiliter et immaterialiter. Nec aliquid invenitur quod huic positioni repugnet.”
43
Albert’s human intellection as a combination of abstraction and emanation is also met in Avicenna’s De anima [40] V 5. As Ogden [60] notes in his recent article this Avicennan theory of intellect is usually interpreted either through the lens of emanationists or that of abstractionists. Yet, Avicenna’s aforesaid text offers good arguments to account for Avicenna’s Emanated Abstraction. For more, see Ogden’s article and the bibliography included. Also cf. with Taylor’s [61] article on intellectual abstraction.
44
[23] (pp. 43.85–44.14): “Omnes autem moderni temporis existentes modum tenent Platonis circa intellectus operationes. Dicunt enim in omnibus separatis a corpore intellectibus esse formas omnium rerum ideales concreatas ipsis intellectibus, quas dicunt esse similes ideis aeternis et formis artis et per has esse intellectus rerum apud intelligentias separatas, dicentes, quod illae formae habent species similes toti ordini causarum naturae universae in superioribus et in inferioribus causis. Qualiter autem istae formae ad res comparentur, isti non possunt dicere. Adhuc autem qualiter hae formae efficiantur propriae, cum nihil omnino accipiant a rebus, isti dicere non possunt. Propter quod etiam quidam philosophorum consenserunt non esse apud animas separatas et intellectus separatos nisi universalia rerum, ita quod de nullo habent scientiam in natura propria. Haec autem scientia est valde imperfecta et est, qua habita non scitur res, sed ignorata ea res ignoratur. Et secundum hoc eorum intellectuum qui sunt omnis scientiae principia potissima, scientia esset imperfectissima omnium scientiarum, et nullam rem scient nisi solum in potentia, et hoc videtur mihi esse absurdum.”
45
[23] (pp. 43.67–82): “Si autem quis quaerat, quam communicationem habeat intellectus agens cum re, in quam agit abstrahendo, dicendum, quod talem habet lumen intellectus agentis cum formis rerum, qualem habet lux corporea cum coloribus. Quaedam enim luces incorporatae sunt colores et similiter quaedam lumina incorporata intellectus agentis sunt formae rerum, sicut patet per antedicta, in quibus ostensum est intellectum agentem esse primum movens et agens in tota natura. Et haec communio sufficit abstractioni; hoc enim modo quo abstractum est in potentia, est abstrahens in actu et connaturale sibi. Et haec principia tali sufficiunt actioni, qualis est abstractio formarum, quae nihil aliud est quam exspoliatio earum ab esse materiali et acceptio earum secundum esse simplex.”

References

  1. Lenzi, M. Alberto e Tommaso sullo statuto dell’anima umana. Arch. D’histoire Doctrin. Litt. Du Moyen Âge 2007, 74, 27–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Hellmeier, P.D. Anima et Intellectus. Albertus Magnus und Thomas von Aquin Über Seele und Intellekt des Menschen; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2011. [Google Scholar]
  3. Anzulewicz, H. Revue of Hellmeier. Theol. Rev. 2012, 108, 397–399. [Google Scholar]
  4. Anzulewicz, H.; Söder, J.R. (Eds.) Alberti Magni De Homine; Opera Omnia, 27.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  5. Fries, A.; Kübel, W.; Anzulewicz, H. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Quaestiones; Opera Omnia, 25.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1993; Quaestio de Origine Animae; pp. 215–218; Quaestio de Intellectu Animae; pp. 269–270; Quaestio de Visione Dei in Patria; pp. 96–101; Quaestio de Dotibus Sanctorum in Patria; pp. 102–111; Quaestio de Sensibus Corporis Gloriosi; pp. 111–125 and Quaestio de Aureola; pp. 126–138. [Google Scholar]
  6. Donati, S. Alberts des Großen Konzept der Scientiae Naturales: Zur Konstitution Einer Peripatetischen Enzyklopädie der Naturwissenschaften. In Albertus Magnus und der Ursprung der Universitätsidee, 1st ed.; Die Begegnung der Wissenschaftskulturen im 13. Jahrhundert und die Entdeckung des Konzepts der Bildung durch Wissenschaft; Honnefelder, L., Ed.; Berlin University Press: Berlin, Germany, 2011; pp. 354–381+524–538. [Google Scholar]
  7. Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Commentarii in I Sententiarum; Opera Omnia, 25; Vivès: Paris, France, 1893. [Google Scholar]
  8. Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Commentarii in II Sententiarum; Opera Omnia, 27; Vivès: Paris, France, 1894. [Google Scholar]
  9. Simon, P. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Dionysium De Divinis Nominibus; Opera Omnia, 37.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1972. [Google Scholar]
  10. Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Summae Theologiae Pars Secunda (Quaest. LXVIII-CXLI); Opera Omnia, 33; Vivès: Paris, France, 1895. [Google Scholar]
  11. Anzulewicz, H. The Systematic Theology of Albert the Great. In A Companion to Albert the Great; Resnick, I.M., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2013; pp. 15–67. [Google Scholar]
  12. Honnefelder, L. Albertus Magnus und die Kulturelle Wende im 13. Jahrhundert—Perspektiven auf die Epochale Bedeutung des Großen Philosophen und Theologen; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  13. Kübel, W. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Ethica. Commentum et Quaestiones, Lib. I–V; Opera Omnia, 14.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1968–1972. [Google Scholar]
  14. Kübel, W. Prolegomena. In Alberti Magni Super Ethica; Kübel, W., Ed.; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1968–1972; pp. VI–XIV. [Google Scholar]
  15. Meersseman, G. Die Einheit der menschlichen Seele nach Albertus Magnus. Divus Thomas 1932, 10, 81–94+213–226. [Google Scholar]
  16. Stroick, C. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Anima; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1968. [Google Scholar]
  17. Donati, S. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Nutrimento et Nutrito. De Sensu et Sensato Cuius Scundus Liber est De Memoria et Reminiscentia; Opera Omnia, 7.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2017. [Google Scholar]
  18. Jammy, P.; Prost, C.; Rigaud, P.C.; Delagarde, H.; Huguetan, I.A. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Parva Naturalia; Opera, 5, C. Prost: Lyon, France, 1651. [Google Scholar]
  19. Borgnet, A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Parvorum Naturalium Pars Prima; Opera Omnia, 9; Vivès: Paris, France, 1890. [Google Scholar]
  20. Meyer, E.; Jessen, C.; Reimer, G. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Die Vegetabilibus Libri VII; Typis et impensis Georgii Reimeri: Berlin, Germany, 1867. [Google Scholar]
  21. Stadler, H. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Animalibus Libri XXVI. Nach der Cölner Urschrift; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1916–1920; Volumes 1–2. [Google Scholar]
  22. Filthaut, E. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Quaestiones Super de Animalibus; Opera Omnia, 12; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1955; pp. 77–321. [Google Scholar]
  23. Geyer, B. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Liber de Natura et Origine Animae; Opera Omnia, 12; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1955; pp. 1–44. [Google Scholar]
  24. Donati, S. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Intellectu et Intelligibli; Opera Omnia, 7.2B; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2024. [Google Scholar]
  25. Hufnagel, A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Unitate Intellectus; Opera Omnia, 17.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1975; pp. 1–30. [Google Scholar]
  26. Hasse, D.N. The Early Albertus Magnus and his Arabic Sources on the Theory of the Soul. Vivarium 2008, 46, 232–252. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Vernier, J.-M. La définition de l’âme chez Avicenne et S. Albert le Grand: Étude comparative du “Liber de anima” d’Avicenne et du “De anima” de S. Albert le Grand. Rev. Des Sci. Philos. Et Théol. 1992, 76, 255–279. [Google Scholar]
  28. Dales, R. The Problem of the Ration Soul in the Thirteenth Century; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1995. [Google Scholar]
  29. Avicenna Latinus, Liber de Anima seu Sextus de Naturalibus, I–II–III; Van Riet, S., Ed.; Peeters: Louvain, Belgium; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1972. [Google Scholar]
  30. Sebti, M. La signification de la définition avicennienne de l’âme comme “perfection première d’un corps naturel organique” dans le livre I du Traité de l’âme du Sifâ’. Bull. D’études Orient. 1999, 51, 299–312. [Google Scholar]
  31. Druart, T.-A. The Human Soul’s Individuation and its Survival after the Body’s Death: Avicenna on the Causal Relation between Body and Soul. Arab. Sci. Philos. 2000, 10, 259–273. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  32. Ethier, A.-M. La double définition de l’ âme humane chez saint Albert le Grand. Études Rech. Publiées Par Le Collège Dominic. D’Ottawa 1936, 1, 79–110. [Google Scholar]
  33. Hasse, D.N. Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West. The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul 1160–1300; The Warburg Institute: London, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
  34. Anzulewicz, H. Die Rekonstruktion der Denkstruktur des Albertus Magnus. Theol. Glaube 2000, 90, 602–612. [Google Scholar]
  35. Anzulewicz, H. Die Denkstruktur des Albertus Magnus. Ihre Dekodierung und ihre Relevanz für die Begrifflichkeit und Terminologie. In L’Élaboration du Vocabulaire Philosophique au Moyen Âge; Hamesse, J., Steel, C., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2000; pp. 369–396. [Google Scholar]
  36. Anzulewicz, H. Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita und das Strukturprinzip des Denkens von Albert dem Großen. In Die Dionysius-Rezeption im Mittelalter; Boiadjiev, T., Kapriev, G., Speer, A., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2000; pp. 251–295. [Google Scholar]
  37. Anzulewicz, H. »Ab eodem in idem«. Verständnis und hermeneutische Funktion der Kreislaufformel bei Albertus Magnus. In Chemins de la Pensée Médiévale. Études Offertes à Zénon Kaluza; Bakker, P.J.J.M., Faye, E., Grellard, C., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2000; pp. 323–350. [Google Scholar]
  38. Anzulewicz, H. Zum anthropologischen Verständnis der Perfectio bei Albertus Magnus. DSTFM 2019, 30, 339–369. [Google Scholar]
  39. Anzulewicz, H. Anthropology: The Concept of Man in Albert the Great. In A Companion to Albert the Great; Brill’s Companions to Christian Tradition 38; Resnick, I., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2013; pp. 325–346. [Google Scholar]
  40. Avicenna Latinus, Liber de Anima seu Sextus de Naturalibus, IV–V; Van Riet, S., Ed.; Peeters: Louvain, Belgium; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1968. [Google Scholar]
  41. Heath, P. Allegory and Philosophy in Avicenna; University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
  42. McGinnis, J. Avicenna; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  43. Davidson, H. Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
  44. Aristotle. De Animalibus; Michel Scot’s Arabic-Latin Translations; Part Three: Books XV–XVI: Generation of Animals; van Oppenraaij, A.M.I., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1992. [Google Scholar]
  45. Kübel, W. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Resurrectione; Opera Omnia, 26; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1958; pp. 237–354. [Google Scholar]
  46. Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Commentarii in IV Sententiarum; Opera Omnia, 30; Vivès: Paris, France, 1894. [Google Scholar]
  47. Anzulewicz, H.; Rigo, C. Reductio ad esse divinum. Zur Vollendung des Menschen nach Albertus Magnus. In Ende und Vollendung. Eschatologische Perspektiven im Mittelalter; Aertsen, J.A., Pickavé, M., Eds.; W. de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2002; pp. 388–416. [Google Scholar]
  48. Crouze, R.D. St Thomas, Philosophia ancilla theologiae. In Actas del V Congreso Interncional d Filosofia Medieval; Editora Nacional: Madrid, Spain, 1979; Volume 1, pp. 657–661. [Google Scholar]
  49. Crouze, R.D. St. Thomas, St. Albert, Aristotle: Philosophia ancilla theologiae. In Tommaso d’Aquino nella Storia del Pensiero; Edizioni Domenicane Italiane: Naples, Italy, 1975; Volume 1, pp. 181–185. [Google Scholar]
  50. Geyer, B. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Metaphysica, Lib. VI–XIII; Opera Omnia, 16.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1964. [Google Scholar]
  51. Siedler, D.; Kübel, W.; Vogels, H.G. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Summa Theologiae Sive de Mirabili Scientia Dei Libri I Pars I q. 1-50A; Opera Omnia, 34.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1964. [Google Scholar]
  52. Anzulewicz, H. Eine anonyme Abhandlung An anima racionalis sit mortalis und ihr Verhältnis zu Albertus Magnus und seinem Werk. Stud. Graeco-Arab. 2024; in press. [Google Scholar]
  53. Borgnet, A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Ethicorum Lib. X; Opera Omnia 7; Vivès: Paris, France, 1891. [Google Scholar]
  54. Moulin, I. Les deux sources du bonheur humain: Contemplation intellective et vision de Dieu Avicenne, Albert le Grand. Quaestio 2015, 15, 433–445. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  55. Avicenna Latinus, Liber de Philosophia Prima Sive Scientia Divina, V–X; Van Riet, S., Ed.; Peeters: Louvain, Belgium; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1980. [Google Scholar]
  56. Michot, J. Avicenne et la destinée humaine: A propos de la résurrection des corps. Rev. Philos. Louvain 1981, 79, 453–483. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Kübel, W. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Ethica. Commentum et Quaestiones, Lib. VI–X; Opera Omnia, 14.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1987. [Google Scholar]
  58. Simon, P. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Dionysii Epistulas; Opera Omnia, 37.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1978; pp. 479–554. [Google Scholar]
  59. Anzulewicz, H. The Emergence of a Science of Intellect. Albert the Great’s De intellectu et intelligibili. In Contextualizing Premodern Philosophy; Krause, K., López-Farjeat, L.X., Oschman, A., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2023; pp. 363–392. [Google Scholar]
  60. Ogden, S. Avicenna’s Emanated Abstraction. Philos. Impr. 2020, 10, 1–26. [Google Scholar]
  61. Taylor, R. Avicenna and the Issue of Intellectual Abstraction of Intelligibles. In Philosophy of Mind in the Early and High Middle Ages; Margaret, C., Ed.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2019; pp. 56–82. [Google Scholar]
  62. Anzulewicz, H.; Krause, K. Albert der Große und sein holistisches Konzept menschlicher Erkenntnis. In Veritas et Subtilitas: Truth and Subtlety in the History of Philosophy; Iremadze, T., Jeck, U.R., Eds.; John Benjamins: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2018; pp. 157–194. [Google Scholar]
  63. Runggaldier, E. Die Menschliche Seele bei Albertus Magnus. Ein Nicht-Reduktionistischer Beitrag zum Leib-Seele-Problem (Lectio Albertina 11); Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  64. Johnston, H. Intellectual Abstraction in St. Albert. Philos. Stud. 1960, 10, 204–212. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Krause, K.; Anzulewicz, H. Albert the Great’s Interpretatio: Converting Libraries into a Scientific System. In Premodern Translation: Comparative Approaches to Cross-Cultural Transformations; Brentjes, S., Fidora, A., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2021; pp. 89–132. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Anzulewicz, H.; Rinotas, A. Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues. Philosophies 2025, 10, 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108

AMA Style

Anzulewicz H, Rinotas A. Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues. Philosophies. 2025; 10(5):108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108

Chicago/Turabian Style

Anzulewicz, Henryk, and Athanasios Rinotas. 2025. "Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues" Philosophies 10, no. 5: 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108

APA Style

Anzulewicz, H., & Rinotas, A. (2025). Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues. Philosophies, 10(5), 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop