Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Concept and Origin of the Rational Soul in Albert’s Early Work
3. Hermeneutic Aspects Concerning Albert’s Development on His Teaching on the Topic of Soul
4. Transformations in Albert’s Conception of the “Anima Rationalis”
“Philosophically, there can be no sufficient knowledge as to whether the souls of the deceased survive death. Even if they do survive, nothing philosophical can be known about their state and their relation to what happens to us; this is known only through a higher, infused, non-natural light, which is the habitus of faith.”32
“After all this has been carefully considered, we will discuss what can naturally be said with greater probability. And we will now mention only what can be philosophically proven.”33
“We say that although the rational soul does not originate from intelligence, it nonetheless receives illuminations from intelligence. Since there are three kinds of intelligibles for the soul, namely the one related to time and space and that which is intelligible by its nature, the first is received together with sensory perception, the second with imagination, and the third through the simple intellect. And there is an order of intelligibles, in that through the intelligible associated with time, the soul reaches what is associated with space, and through what is associated with space, it reaches what is intelligible by itself.”35
“The opposite applies, however, to souls that neglect this perfection of the intellect. Just as the intelligible is moved towards the possible intellect by the light of the active intellect, so it is darkened and contracted by the mixture with matter, movement, and size, by the ‘here and now’, and the rational soul receives it only as it is ‘here and now’. It is therefore not free but shadowed and material, and thus the soul receiving it in this manner does not receive any light from it at all. Consequently, the soul has no access to the true intelligible, in which the soul perfectly shines, and thus such an intellect deprived of all light remains dark within itself and is unable to shine after death. As we have said previously, the possible intellect is only capable of receiving light that is truly the light of the intellect when it is strengthened by the lights received from sensory perception or with sensory perception and from imagination or with imagination. A return to sensory perception and imagination is, however, impossible after death; thus, such an intellect is incapable of illumination and remains in eternal darkness, which is deprivation and withdrawal of intellectual light.”37
“It must be said that theological contemplation in some respects coincides with philosophical contemplation and in some respects differs from it; they are therefore not entirely identical. The similarity lies in the fact that in theological contemplation, there is also an unimpeded intellectual insight into the spiritual, despite the passions of the subject and doubts stemming from faith directed towards resting in God, which represents the highest bliss. However, it differs in terms of habitus, goal, and object: in terms of habitus, because theological contemplation occurs through the light infused by God; the philosopher, on the other hand, relies on the acquired habitus of wisdom. Regarding the goal, theological contemplation sets the ultimate goal in the contemplation of God in the patria, while the philosopher sets it in the vision through which he sees in via. Also, concerning the object—not insofar as it pertains to substance but in terms of mode—the philosopher contemplates God as a conclusion of a proof, whereas the theologian views Him as a being above understanding and intellect. Therefore, the mode of contemplation is different because the philosopher has the certainty of the proof upon which he relies, while the theologian relies on the first truth itself and not on a rational argument, even if he had one. This is why the theologian wonders, while the philosopher does not.”40
“One must say that elevation (sursum agi) happens in two ways: either absolutely, as in what is concluded by proof, and in this way, the philosophers cannot be elevated to the divine; or through wonder, by proving something that reason cannot grasp, and in this way, they should be elevated to the divine. For although philosophy does not prove anything against the divine wisdom delivered by faith, it does not reach it; it has a limit up to which it can reach, and it still knows that it does not grasp the whole. Therefore, it should admire it, not oppose it, as it is philosophically proven that in God there are perfections of all kinds, that in Him is the highest simplicity, that He is His own act, and many other things of this sort that seem incompatible with the principles of reason, from which one progresses with other things. Hence, the philosopher says that the first cause surpasses language and reason.”41
“Another way is, according to the above statements, that the soul, now having an enlightened and strengthened intellect, can by itself reach the intellect of things. For we see that the intellect can understand things by abstracting from the phantasm while it is in the body, and when strengthened, it can reach the intellect of divine things. And in this way, we will say that just as it now is ordered towards things and therefore abstracts from the phantasms of things through its light, so, when separated, it can wholly apprehend things outside the soul, abstracting from them through its light and understanding them. And then every such intellect is determined through its comparison with the intelligible, just as now it is determined through the reflection of its intelligible upon the imagination and sense. And in this way, among separated intellects, Dionysius says there is knowledge of sensible things without sensation and immaterially. Nor is anything found that contradicts this position.”42
“If someone were to ask what commonality the active intellect has with the object upon which it acts through abstraction, it must be said that the light of the active intellect shares a similarity with the forms of things, comparable to the relationship between physical light and colors. For certain embodied lights are colors, and in a similar way, certain embodied lights of the active intellect are the forms of things, as previously indicated, where it was shown that the active intellect is the first mover and actor in all of nature. This commonality suffices for abstraction; specifically, in the way that what is abstracted exists potentially, the abstracting intellect exists in actuality and is naturally alike to itself. And these principles suffice for such an activity as the abstraction of forms, which is nothing other than their removal from material existence and their reception in accordance with simple being.”45
5. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The second part of the Summa de creaturis by Albertus Magnus, De homine, is available in the critical edition [4]; the critical edition of the first part of this Summa, transmitted under the title De quattuor coaequaevis, is currently being prepared. Both parts of this double work are available in two early prints and two non-critical complete editions by P. Jammy (Volume 19a, Lyon 1651) and S.C.A. Borgnet (Vol. 34, Paris 1895). |
2 | More on this below. |
3 | For the notion of “scientiae naturales” in the work of Albert, see: [6]. |
4 | |
5 | See: [9] (c. 4, pp. 202–208). |
6 | See: [10] (Tr. XII, q. 68–74, pp. 1–57; tr. XIII q. 77, pp. 68–106; tr. XV q. 92–97, pp. 193–222). |
7 | |
8 | In Albert’s Super Ethica, among the statements relevant to soul theory, there are two treatises on the human soul as a simple form (simplex forma) and on its unity in essence with its faculties. For the critical edition of the text, see [13] (Lib. I lect. 15, pp. 78.62–81.88). For the dating of the work, cf. [14] (pp. VI.11–27); for the doctrinal context and content, see [15] (pp. 81(213)–85(217), 93(225)–94(226)). |
9 | Among the core works of Albert’s psychological and psychophysiological writings are the commentaries on De anima [16] and on the incompletely available Parva naturalia of Aristotle, whose missing parts Albert reconstructed. Specifically, these are: De nutrimento et nutrito, De sensu et sensato, De memoria et reminiscentia, De somno et vigilia, De spiritu et respiratione, De motibus animalium, De iuventute et senectute, and De morte et vita. Currently, De nutrimento et nutrito, De sensu et sensato, and De memoria et reminiscentia are critically edited [17]; they are fully available in the two non-critical complete editions by P. Jammy, Vol. 5 [18], and A. Borgnet, Vol. 9 [19]. For more details on the manuscripts, sources, and dating of these writings, see Donati [6]. |
10 | See: [4] (pp. 8.26–9.4). |
11 | Albert does not accept the matter-form composition of form and thus he avoids calling soul the form of the body. Instead, he prefers to define soul as purus actus or perfectio of the body. In De homine [4] ad. 6. 35a Albert says: “melius dicitur actus vel perfectio quam forma.” With respect to this definition, Hasse [26] and Vernier [27] have drawn clear connections between Albert and Avicenna and his De anima, while Dales [28] (p. 91), attributes the aforesaid definition to Aristotle. Given the great number of Avicenna’s quotation in Albert’s De homine, it is safe to ascertain that Albert was well aware of Avicenna’s relevant passage in the De anima [29] (pp. 19–21), which runs as follows: “Deinde dicimus quod omnis forma est perfectio, sed non omnis perfectio forma: magister enim fabricandi perfectio est civitatis et carpentarius lignorum perfectio est navis, nec tamen sunt formae civitatis vel navis. Et cuiuscumque perfectionis est essentia per se separata, ipsa certe non est forma materiae nec in materia: forma etenim quae est in materia, est forma impressa in illa et existens per illam, si consenserint ut perfectio speciei forma vocetur speciei. Sed iam consenserunt in hoc, ut haec res, scilicet anima, comparatione materiae sit forma, comparatione vero totius collectionis sit finis et perfectio, et comparatione movendi, principium efficiens et vis movens. Et quandoquidem sie est, tunc forma significat comparationem ad rem remotissimam ab essentia substantiae quae habet esse per illam, et ad rem propter quam substantia habet esse quod ipsa est et al.ia quae propter ipsam est in potentia, et ad rem cui non comparantur actiones, quae est materia: anima enim forma est ex respectu hoc scilicet quod habet esse in materia; perfectio autem significat comparationem ad rem perfectarn ex qua emanant actiones, quia perfectio est respectu speciei. Clarum est igitur quod, cum in doctrina de anima dicimus quod ipsa est perfectio, hoc plus significat eius intellectum et etiam hoc plus comprehendit omnes species animae undique, et hoc necesse est animae separatae a materia.” For Avicenna’s definition on soul, see [30,31]. |
12 | [4], pp. 9.1–2: “res incorporea rationis capax, vivficando corpori accomodata.” |
13 | |
14 | [4], pp. 18–28. |
15 | This point has also been raised by Dag Nicolaus Hasse [33] (pp. 60–69). Hasse argues that some of Albert’s early opinions on soul are either changed in his later works or assimilated as his own. It is also worth mentioning that Hasse provides a preliminary list of Albert’s references to Avicenna’s De anima which clearly shows a tendency from Albert’s part to significantly mitigate his reliance on Avicenna in his later works. For instance, De homine contains 227 explicit quotations of the Avicennan text, while the De natura et origine animae just three. |
16 | |
17 | For Albert, the human soul is regarded as immaterial, incorruptible and separate substance from the body which yet has a strong dependence on it. Anzulewicz [39] has cogently shown how human soul, as an intellectual substance bears the same aforesaid characteristics, something which led Albert to argue that homo inquantum homo solus est intellectus. It is worth noting that the immateriality, incorruptibility and separability of the soul are also met in Avicenna’s De anima [40] (V 2, pp. 81–101). Both Druart [31] and Heath [41] (pp. 57–79), have argued for the existence of these characteristics of soul in the Avicenna’s relevant theory, while McGinnis [42] (pp. 117–148), and Davidson [43] (pp. 81–86), have discussed these very characteristics through the context of intellective soul. |
18 | |
19 | Cf. [4] (pp. 85.24–27): “Dicendum secundum omnes sanctos et philosophos et naturales quod vegetabile, sensibile et rationale sunt in homine substantia una et anima una et actus unus.” [4], (pp. 86.32–38): “in plantis sufficit ad vegetabile materia seminis cum virtute caelesti sine operatione masculi. In brutis autem oportet in materia esse semen masculi, quod substantificat et movet materiam, quia aliter non egrederetur animal sensibile. Sed in hominibus propter divinam virtutem ipsius intellectus exigitur dator extrinsecus ipsius animae.” |
20 | See: [4] (pp. 73.11–23) with the source references in the critical apparatus of the edition. |
21 | [4], (pp. 73.24–34): “Quod autem non generetur, sed creetur in corpore secundum Aristotelem, patet in XVI De animalibus, ubi dicit intellectualem animam non esse ab aliquo principio efficiente, quod sit in semine. Quod autem eius principium sit deus, et quod ingreditur per creationem in corpus, patet per haec verba sua quae sunt in primo De causis proprietatum elementorum: ‘Aqua viri quando cadit in matricem mulieris, decoquit eam matrix caliditate sua et commiscetur aqua illa cum sanguine matricis, donec fit frustum; deinde formatur et fit in eo spiritus vitae iussu dei’.” |
22 | See: [4] p. 71.60–62: “ Dicimus quod deus infundendo creat humanas animas et creando infundit eas, et omnia alia dicta reputamus deliramenta.” |
23 | Richard Dales [28], (p. 94), has argued that Albert’s position on the matter gets further clarified in his De natura et origine animae. According to Dales, Albert seems to adopt a thesis which is close to Thomas Aquinas as he refers to a “progression of forms” during the embryo’s development. See [23] (Tr. I, Cap. 5, pp. 13–15). |
24 | Cf. [4], (pp. 67.34–68.6, pp. 71.63–72.43, esp. p. 71.67–72): “Ad auctoritates autem Augustini dicendum quod opinando et opiniones aliorum sequendo talia dicit et non sic sentiendo, ut patet per auctoritates ad oppositum ex eodem loco inductas. Si tamen vellemus distinguere, diceremus quod anima duobus modis prior est corpore et corpus uno modo prius anima; est enim prius substantia et prius ratione, et hoc modo anima est ante corpus, cui dat substantiam et rationem; est etiam prius tempore, et sic corpus est prius anima, quia non infunditur ei nisi iam organizato.” |
25 | See: [4] p. 410.39–41 (with source references): “anima rationalis non est in corpore nisi ut perficiatur scientia et virtute, ut dicunt sancti et philosophi.” Cf. [8] (II dist. 1 a. 14, p. 41b); [24] (Lib. II c. 12, pp. 46.39–47.26); [16] (Lib. II tr. 3 c.3, pp. 100.13–19): “mutatio potentiae sensitivae ad primam perfectionem ipsius est a generante. Potentiarum enim apprehensivarum quaedam complentur prima perfectione a natura et quaedam per experimentum et studium: a natura quidem sicut potentia sensitiva ad sentire, per experimentum autem et tempus sicut intellectiva.”—Italics indicate words that Albert retained unchanged from the source in his paraphrase of Aristotle’s De anima. [38] (pp. 339–368). |
26 | |
27 | In his early work, Albert mentions his reductionist stance towards natural philosophy and its subordination to theology in retrospect to the Summa de creaturis in the Sentences Commentary, Book II, dist. 14 a. 6, see [8] (p. 266b) (the non-critical edition was verified against the manuscripts Berlin, Staatsbibliothek Preussischer Kulturbesitz theol. lat. fol. 320, f. 40ra; Sigüenza, Bibl. del Cabildo 210, f. 203rb): “Alibi etiam disputatum est de ista materia multum et prolixe, et ibi secuti sumus dicta quorundam magistrorum theologiae, qui voluerunt opiniones naturalium ad theologiam reducere …”. |
28 | See: [4] (p. 18.16): “Circa diffinitionem vero Platonis de hoc quod dicitur ‘substantia incorporea’, supra disputatum est.” |
29 | See note 22. Cf. [45] (De resurr.). |
30 | For more on this topic, see: [47] (pp. 388–416). |
31 | Cf. [13] (Lib. I lect. 7, p. 34.42–44): “scientia, quae est de humanis, est ancilla, quia subservit alii scientiae liberae, quae est philosophia prima, quae est de deo.” [48] (p. 657–661). [49] (pp. 181–185). [50] (Lib. 11 tr. 3 c. 7, pp. 542.25–27): “Theologica autem non conveniunt cum philosophicis in principiis, quia fundantur super revelationem et inspirationem et non super rationem, et ideo de illis in philosophia non possumus disputare.” [51] (Lib. I pars 1 q. 5, pp. 15–22). |
32 | See: [13] (Lib. I lect. 13, pp. 71.73–79): “hoc quod animae defunctorum remaneant post mortem, non potest per philosophiam sufficienter sciri. Et supposito, quod remaneant, de statu earum et qualiter se habeant ad ea quae circa nos fiunt, omnino nihil sciri per philosophiam potest, sed haec cognoscuntur altiori lumine infuso non naturali, quod est habitus fidei.” |
33 | See: [23] (Tr. II c. 13, pp. 37.63–66): “Omnibus his diligenter excursis tangemus id quod secundum naturam probabilius dici potest, et non faciemus modo aliquam mentionem nisi tantum de his quae per philosophiam possunt probari.” |
34 | For citations in the mentioned writings and the secondary sources related to them, see [52]. |
35 | [23] (Tr. II c. 13, pp. 37.66–78): “Dicimus igitur, quod anima rationalis non quidem fit ab intelligentia, tamen ab intelligentia recipit illuminationes. Et cum sit triplex intelligibile ipsius animae, scilicet cum tempore et cum continuo et id quod secundum sui naturam est intelligibile, primum quidem est acceptum cum sensu et secundum cum imaginatione et tertium est per intellectum simplicem acceptum. Et est ordo in intelligibilibus, quoniam per hoc intelligibile quod est cum tempore, venit anima ad id quod est cum continuo, et per id quod est cum continuo, venit ad id quod est per seipsum intelligibile.” [23], (pp. 38.42–52): “His igitur sic determinatis dicimus, quod anima rationalis differt ab intelligentia caelesti, eo quod per intelligibilia, quae sunt cum tempore et continuo, venire habet ad intelligibile, quod secundum esse et essentiam per se est intelligibile, et si est ordo in illis per se intelligibilibus, habet devenire ad primum intelligibile, quod est causa omnium aliorum, et in illo stat sicut in vertice suae sapientiae et contemplationis finalis. Propter quod omnia intelligibilia adminiculantia sunt ad primum intelligibile, sicut dicit Alfarabius et Avempeche.” |
36 | [50] (Lib. XI Tr. 1 c. 9, pp. 473.10–24): “Cum igitur lumen intellectus et intellectuum, sicut iam dictum est, sparsum sit in omnibus intelligibilibus, primum, quod acquirit intellectus per studium, est collectio intellectuum speculativorum in tribus theoricae partibus, quae sunt physica, mathesis et prima philosophia, sicut a principio huius sapientiae determinavimus, cetera autem quae sunt de rationibus, in grammaticis, quae ministrant intelligibilium signa, et logicis, quae dant inveniendi et accipiendi verum modum, et rhetoricis, quae ex signis aliquid persuasionis eliciunt, et poeticis, quae coniecturare docent ex integumentis. Ethica autem sunt praeparationes ex parte studentis, ne avertatur a concupiscentiis, et hic intellectus sic acceptus est speculativus.” Cf. [53] Lib. X Tr. 2 c. 3, p.628b: “Homini ergo et optimum et delectabilissimum est vita secundum intellectum speculativa: haec enim maxime est homo. Talis igitur homo felicissimus est prima et dignissima felicitate. Secundario autem et ille felix est, qui secundum aliam virtutem quae rationis inquisitivae ultimum est, habet perfectas operationes. Haec autem virtus moralis est, sicut in primo hujus scientiae libro determinatum est: secundum hanc enim sunt operationes humanae. Quaecumque enim ad invicem agimus in commutationibus et necessitatibus et omnimodis actionibus communitatum, justa sunt, vel fortiora, vel temperata.” |
37 | [23] (Tr. II c.13, pp. 39.24–46): “E contra autem est de his animabus quae hanc negligunt intellectus perfectionem. Sicut enim intelligibile per lumen intellectus agentis movetur ad intellectum possibilem, ita per permixtionem materiae et motus et quantitatis obscuratum et contractum non est nisi hic et nunc, et non accipit ipsum anima rationalis, nisi prout est hic et nunc. Sic autem nec liberum est, sed umbrosum et materiale, et ideo nihil luminis accipit ex ipso taliter accipiens ipsum anima. Propter quod per ipsum non habet viam ad verum intelligibile, in quo perfecte lucet anima, et ideo omni luce destitutus intellectus huiusmodi manet tenebrosus in seipso, nec est irradiabilis hic intellectus post mortem, quoniam sicut in antehabitis diximus, intellectus possibilis non est susceptibilis luminis, quod vere est lumen intellectus, nisi confortatus luminibus his quae a sensu vel cum sensu et ab imaginatione aut cum imaginatione sumuntur. Ad sensum autem et imaginationem impossibilis est regressus post mortem, et ideo talis intellectus impossibilis est ad illuminationem, sed remanet in perpetuis tenebris, quae sunt luminis intellectualis privatio et destitutio.” Cf. [38] (pp. 367–368). |
38 | Isabelle Moulin [54] has made some connections between Albert and Avicenna regarding the topic of happiness through theological and philosophical contemplation. In her study she argues that Albert and Avicenna share some common ground with respect to happiness through philosophical contemplation but the two authors differ significantly when it comes to the theological one. While Albert is an advocate of the latter by evoking the notion of theophania, Avicenna treats theological contemplation in a rather dismissive way. In his Metaphysica [55], in IX 7, pp. 506–507, he explicitly states: “Opus est ut certificemus hic dispositionem animarum humanarum cum sunt exutae a corporibus suis, ad quam dispositionem perveniunt. Oportet autem te scire quod promissio alia est quae fide recipitur, quia non est via ad probandum eam nisi credendo testimonio prophetae, sicut illa quae est de eo quod habebit corpus apud resurrectionem. Tu autem iam scis delectationes corporum et gaudia quid sunt. Lex enim nostra quam dedit Mahometh ostendit dispositionem felicitatis et miseriae quae sunt secundum corpus. Et alia est promissio quae apprehenditur intellectu et argumentatione demonstrativa, et prophetia approbat; et haec est felicitas et miseria animarum quae probantur argumentationibus, quamvis nostrae aestimationes debiles sint ad imaginandum eas nunc propter causas quas ego ostendam. Sapientibus vero theologis multo maior cupiditas fuit ad consequendum hanc felicitatem quam felicitatem corporum, quae quamvis daretur eis, tamen non attenderunt eam, nec appretiati sunt eam comparatione huius felicitatis quae est coniuncta primae veritati, sicut paulo post ostendam de ea. Igitur faciam sciri dispositionem huius felicitatis, et miseriae quae est ei contraria; corporalis autem felicitas iam assignata est in lege.” For more on Avicenna and afterlife, see Michot [56]. |
39 | [46] (Lib. IV dist. 49 a. 6, p. 674b): “beatitudo dicitur multipliciter, et non aequivoce, sed secundum prius et posterius. Dicitur autem secundum statum perfectionis viae, et secundum statum perfectionis patriae. Secundum statum autem viae dicitur tripliciter, scilicet proprie, large, et per causam. Proprie autem dicitur dupliciter, scilicet secundum virtutem moralem, et secundum virtutem intellectualem: et ideo Aristoteles in Ethicis facit duos libros de felicitate: primum enim fecit de felicitate morali, secundum autem de felicitate intellectuali.” Cf. [53] (Lib. X Tr. 2 c. 3, p. 628b (Text in Note 32)). |
40 | [57] (Lib. X lect.16, pp. 774.80–775.13): “Dicendum, quod contemplatio theologica in aliquo convenit cum philosophica et in aliquo differt; unde non sunt omnino idem. Convenit enim in hoc quod etiam in theologica est inspectio per intellectum aliquorum spiritualium sine impedimento passionum ex parte subiecti et dubietatis ex parte fidei ordinata ad quiescendum in deo, quod est summa felicitas. Differt autem et in habitu et in fine et in obiecto. In habitu quidem, quia theologica contemplatur per lumen infusum a deo, sed philosophus per habitum sapientiae acquisitum; in fine, quia theologica poni ultimum finem in contemplatione dei in patria, sed philosophus in visione, qua videtur aliquatenus in via; in obiecto etiam non quantum ad substantiam, sed quantum ad modum, quia philosophus contemplatur deum, secundum quod habet ipsum ut quandam conclusionem demonstrativam, sed theologus contemplatur ipsum ut supra rationem et intellectum existentem. Et ideo est diversus modus contemplandi, quia philosophus habet certitudinem demonstrationis, cui innititur, sed theologus innititur primae veritati propter se et non propter rationem, etiamsi habeat ipsam, et ideo theologus miratur, sed non philosophus.” |
41 | [58] (Epist. septima, pp. 505.25–42): “Dicendum, quod sursum agi in aliquid est dupliciter: aut simpliciter sicut in id quod demonstratione concluditur, et sic philosophi non possunt sursum agi in divina, aut per admirationem, dum probatur aliquid in cuius comprehensionem ratio non potest, et sic oportebat eos sursum agi in divina. Quamvis enim philosophia nihil probet contra divinam veritatem, quam tradit fides, tamen non pertingit ad ipsam, sed habet aliquem terminum, usquequo devenit, et scit se tamen non totum comprehendere, et ideo debet admirari, non impugnare, sicut per philosophiam probatur, quod in deo sunt perfectiones omnium generum et quod in eo est summa simplicitas et quod ipse est sua actio et multa huiusmodi, quae non videntur se posse compati secundum principia rationis, ex quibus proceditur in aliis rebus. Et ideo dicit Philosophus, quod ‘causa prima est supra narrationem’ et rationem.” |
42 | [23] (pp. 43.23–40): “Alius autem modus est secundum supra dicta, quod videlicet anima iam illuminatum et confortatum intellectum habens per se possit ad intellectus rerum. Videmus enim, quod intellectus potest ad res intelligendas abstrahendo a phantasmate modo, dum est in corpore, et confortatus potest ad intellectum divinorum. Et hoc modo dicemus, quod sicut modo ordinatur super res et ideo lumine suo abstrahit a phantasmatibus rerum, ita separatus omnino potest super ipsas res extra animam existentes, ut lumine suo abstrahat ab ipsis rebus et intelligat eas, et tunc omnis talis intellectus determinatur per sui intelligibilis ad rem comparationem, sicut et nunc determinatur per reflexionem sui intelligibilis ad imaginationem et sensum. Et hoc modo apud intellectus separatos magnus dicit Dionysius esse rerum sensibilium cognitiones insensibiliter et immaterialiter. Nec aliquid invenitur quod huic positioni repugnet.” |
43 | Albert’s human intellection as a combination of abstraction and emanation is also met in Avicenna’s De anima [40] V 5. As Ogden [60] notes in his recent article this Avicennan theory of intellect is usually interpreted either through the lens of emanationists or that of abstractionists. Yet, Avicenna’s aforesaid text offers good arguments to account for Avicenna’s Emanated Abstraction. For more, see Ogden’s article and the bibliography included. Also cf. with Taylor’s [61] article on intellectual abstraction. |
44 | [23] (pp. 43.85–44.14): “Omnes autem moderni temporis existentes modum tenent Platonis circa intellectus operationes. Dicunt enim in omnibus separatis a corpore intellectibus esse formas omnium rerum ideales concreatas ipsis intellectibus, quas dicunt esse similes ideis aeternis et formis artis et per has esse intellectus rerum apud intelligentias separatas, dicentes, quod illae formae habent species similes toti ordini causarum naturae universae in superioribus et in inferioribus causis. Qualiter autem istae formae ad res comparentur, isti non possunt dicere. Adhuc autem qualiter hae formae efficiantur propriae, cum nihil omnino accipiant a rebus, isti dicere non possunt. Propter quod etiam quidam philosophorum consenserunt non esse apud animas separatas et intellectus separatos nisi universalia rerum, ita quod de nullo habent scientiam in natura propria. Haec autem scientia est valde imperfecta et est, qua habita non scitur res, sed ignorata ea res ignoratur. Et secundum hoc eorum intellectuum qui sunt omnis scientiae principia potissima, scientia esset imperfectissima omnium scientiarum, et nullam rem scient nisi solum in potentia, et hoc videtur mihi esse absurdum.” |
45 | [23] (pp. 43.67–82): “Si autem quis quaerat, quam communicationem habeat intellectus agens cum re, in quam agit abstrahendo, dicendum, quod talem habet lumen intellectus agentis cum formis rerum, qualem habet lux corporea cum coloribus. Quaedam enim luces incorporatae sunt colores et similiter quaedam lumina incorporata intellectus agentis sunt formae rerum, sicut patet per antedicta, in quibus ostensum est intellectum agentem esse primum movens et agens in tota natura. Et haec communio sufficit abstractioni; hoc enim modo quo abstractum est in potentia, est abstrahens in actu et connaturale sibi. Et haec principia tali sufficiunt actioni, qualis est abstractio formarum, quae nihil aliud est quam exspoliatio earum ab esse materiali et acceptio earum secundum esse simplex.” |
References
- Lenzi, M. Alberto e Tommaso sullo statuto dell’anima umana. Arch. D’histoire Doctrin. Litt. Du Moyen Âge 2007, 74, 27–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hellmeier, P.D. Anima et Intellectus. Albertus Magnus und Thomas von Aquin Über Seele und Intellekt des Menschen; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Revue of Hellmeier. Theol. Rev. 2012, 108, 397–399. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H.; Söder, J.R. (Eds.) Alberti Magni De Homine; Opera Omnia, 27.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Fries, A.; Kübel, W.; Anzulewicz, H. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Quaestiones; Opera Omnia, 25.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1993; Quaestio de Origine Animae; pp. 215–218; Quaestio de Intellectu Animae; pp. 269–270; Quaestio de Visione Dei in Patria; pp. 96–101; Quaestio de Dotibus Sanctorum in Patria; pp. 102–111; Quaestio de Sensibus Corporis Gloriosi; pp. 111–125 and Quaestio de Aureola; pp. 126–138. [Google Scholar]
- Donati, S. Alberts des Großen Konzept der Scientiae Naturales: Zur Konstitution Einer Peripatetischen Enzyklopädie der Naturwissenschaften. In Albertus Magnus und der Ursprung der Universitätsidee, 1st ed.; Die Begegnung der Wissenschaftskulturen im 13. Jahrhundert und die Entdeckung des Konzepts der Bildung durch Wissenschaft; Honnefelder, L., Ed.; Berlin University Press: Berlin, Germany, 2011; pp. 354–381+524–538. [Google Scholar]
- Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Commentarii in I Sententiarum; Opera Omnia, 25; Vivès: Paris, France, 1893. [Google Scholar]
- Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Commentarii in II Sententiarum; Opera Omnia, 27; Vivès: Paris, France, 1894. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, P. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Dionysium De Divinis Nominibus; Opera Omnia, 37.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Summae Theologiae Pars Secunda (Quaest. LXVIII-CXLI); Opera Omnia, 33; Vivès: Paris, France, 1895. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. The Systematic Theology of Albert the Great. In A Companion to Albert the Great; Resnick, I.M., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2013; pp. 15–67. [Google Scholar]
- Honnefelder, L. Albertus Magnus und die Kulturelle Wende im 13. Jahrhundert—Perspektiven auf die Epochale Bedeutung des Großen Philosophen und Theologen; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Kübel, W. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Ethica. Commentum et Quaestiones, Lib. I–V; Opera Omnia, 14.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1968–1972. [Google Scholar]
- Kübel, W. Prolegomena. In Alberti Magni Super Ethica; Kübel, W., Ed.; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1968–1972; pp. VI–XIV. [Google Scholar]
- Meersseman, G. Die Einheit der menschlichen Seele nach Albertus Magnus. Divus Thomas 1932, 10, 81–94+213–226. [Google Scholar]
- Stroick, C. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Anima; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Donati, S. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Nutrimento et Nutrito. De Sensu et Sensato Cuius Scundus Liber est De Memoria et Reminiscentia; Opera Omnia, 7.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Jammy, P.; Prost, C.; Rigaud, P.C.; Delagarde, H.; Huguetan, I.A. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Parva Naturalia; Opera, 5, C. Prost: Lyon, France, 1651. [Google Scholar]
- Borgnet, A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Parvorum Naturalium Pars Prima; Opera Omnia, 9; Vivès: Paris, France, 1890. [Google Scholar]
- Meyer, E.; Jessen, C.; Reimer, G. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Die Vegetabilibus Libri VII; Typis et impensis Georgii Reimeri: Berlin, Germany, 1867. [Google Scholar]
- Stadler, H. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Animalibus Libri XXVI. Nach der Cölner Urschrift; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1916–1920; Volumes 1–2. [Google Scholar]
- Filthaut, E. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Quaestiones Super de Animalibus; Opera Omnia, 12; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1955; pp. 77–321. [Google Scholar]
- Geyer, B. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Liber de Natura et Origine Animae; Opera Omnia, 12; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1955; pp. 1–44. [Google Scholar]
- Donati, S. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Intellectu et Intelligibli; Opera Omnia, 7.2B; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2024. [Google Scholar]
- Hufnagel, A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Unitate Intellectus; Opera Omnia, 17.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1975; pp. 1–30. [Google Scholar]
- Hasse, D.N. The Early Albertus Magnus and his Arabic Sources on the Theory of the Soul. Vivarium 2008, 46, 232–252. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vernier, J.-M. La définition de l’âme chez Avicenne et S. Albert le Grand: Étude comparative du “Liber de anima” d’Avicenne et du “De anima” de S. Albert le Grand. Rev. Des Sci. Philos. Et Théol. 1992, 76, 255–279. [Google Scholar]
- Dales, R. The Problem of the Ration Soul in the Thirteenth Century; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna Latinus, Liber de Anima seu Sextus de Naturalibus, I–II–III; Van Riet, S., Ed.; Peeters: Louvain, Belgium; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Sebti, M. La signification de la définition avicennienne de l’âme comme “perfection première d’un corps naturel organique” dans le livre I du Traité de l’âme du Sifâ’. Bull. D’études Orient. 1999, 51, 299–312. [Google Scholar]
- Druart, T.-A. The Human Soul’s Individuation and its Survival after the Body’s Death: Avicenna on the Causal Relation between Body and Soul. Arab. Sci. Philos. 2000, 10, 259–273. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ethier, A.-M. La double définition de l’ âme humane chez saint Albert le Grand. Études Rech. Publiées Par Le Collège Dominic. D’Ottawa 1936, 1, 79–110. [Google Scholar]
- Hasse, D.N. Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West. The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul 1160–1300; The Warburg Institute: London, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Die Rekonstruktion der Denkstruktur des Albertus Magnus. Theol. Glaube 2000, 90, 602–612. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Die Denkstruktur des Albertus Magnus. Ihre Dekodierung und ihre Relevanz für die Begrifflichkeit und Terminologie. In L’Élaboration du Vocabulaire Philosophique au Moyen Âge; Hamesse, J., Steel, C., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2000; pp. 369–396. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita und das Strukturprinzip des Denkens von Albert dem Großen. In Die Dionysius-Rezeption im Mittelalter; Boiadjiev, T., Kapriev, G., Speer, A., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2000; pp. 251–295. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. »Ab eodem in idem«. Verständnis und hermeneutische Funktion der Kreislaufformel bei Albertus Magnus. In Chemins de la Pensée Médiévale. Études Offertes à Zénon Kaluza; Bakker, P.J.J.M., Faye, E., Grellard, C., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2000; pp. 323–350. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Zum anthropologischen Verständnis der Perfectio bei Albertus Magnus. DSTFM 2019, 30, 339–369. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Anthropology: The Concept of Man in Albert the Great. In A Companion to Albert the Great; Brill’s Companions to Christian Tradition 38; Resnick, I., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2013; pp. 325–346. [Google Scholar]
- Avicenna Latinus, Liber de Anima seu Sextus de Naturalibus, IV–V; Van Riet, S., Ed.; Peeters: Louvain, Belgium; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Heath, P. Allegory and Philosophy in Avicenna; University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- McGinnis, J. Avicenna; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, H. Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. De Animalibus; Michel Scot’s Arabic-Latin Translations; Part Three: Books XV–XVI: Generation of Animals; van Oppenraaij, A.M.I., Ed.; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Kübel, W. (Ed.) Alberti Magni De Resurrectione; Opera Omnia, 26; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1958; pp. 237–354. [Google Scholar]
- Borgnet, S.C.A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Commentarii in IV Sententiarum; Opera Omnia, 30; Vivès: Paris, France, 1894. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H.; Rigo, C. Reductio ad esse divinum. Zur Vollendung des Menschen nach Albertus Magnus. In Ende und Vollendung. Eschatologische Perspektiven im Mittelalter; Aertsen, J.A., Pickavé, M., Eds.; W. de Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2002; pp. 388–416. [Google Scholar]
- Crouze, R.D. St Thomas, Philosophia ancilla theologiae. In Actas del V Congreso Interncional d Filosofia Medieval; Editora Nacional: Madrid, Spain, 1979; Volume 1, pp. 657–661. [Google Scholar]
- Crouze, R.D. St. Thomas, St. Albert, Aristotle: Philosophia ancilla theologiae. In Tommaso d’Aquino nella Storia del Pensiero; Edizioni Domenicane Italiane: Naples, Italy, 1975; Volume 1, pp. 181–185. [Google Scholar]
- Geyer, B. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Metaphysica, Lib. VI–XIII; Opera Omnia, 16.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Siedler, D.; Kübel, W.; Vogels, H.G. (Eds.) Alberti Magni Summa Theologiae Sive de Mirabili Scientia Dei Libri I Pars I q. 1-50A; Opera Omnia, 34.1; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. Eine anonyme Abhandlung An anima racionalis sit mortalis und ihr Verhältnis zu Albertus Magnus und seinem Werk. Stud. Graeco-Arab. 2024; in press. [Google Scholar]
- Borgnet, A. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Ethicorum Lib. X; Opera Omnia 7; Vivès: Paris, France, 1891. [Google Scholar]
- Moulin, I. Les deux sources du bonheur humain: Contemplation intellective et vision de Dieu Avicenne, Albert le Grand. Quaestio 2015, 15, 433–445. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Avicenna Latinus, Liber de Philosophia Prima Sive Scientia Divina, V–X; Van Riet, S., Ed.; Peeters: Louvain, Belgium; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Michot, J. Avicenne et la destinée humaine: A propos de la résurrection des corps. Rev. Philos. Louvain 1981, 79, 453–483. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kübel, W. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Ethica. Commentum et Quaestiones, Lib. VI–X; Opera Omnia, 14.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, P. (Ed.) Alberti Magni Super Dionysii Epistulas; Opera Omnia, 37.2; Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 1978; pp. 479–554. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H. The Emergence of a Science of Intellect. Albert the Great’s De intellectu et intelligibili. In Contextualizing Premodern Philosophy; Krause, K., López-Farjeat, L.X., Oschman, A., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2023; pp. 363–392. [Google Scholar]
- Ogden, S. Avicenna’s Emanated Abstraction. Philos. Impr. 2020, 10, 1–26. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, R. Avicenna and the Issue of Intellectual Abstraction of Intelligibles. In Philosophy of Mind in the Early and High Middle Ages; Margaret, C., Ed.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2019; pp. 56–82. [Google Scholar]
- Anzulewicz, H.; Krause, K. Albert der Große und sein holistisches Konzept menschlicher Erkenntnis. In Veritas et Subtilitas: Truth and Subtlety in the History of Philosophy; Iremadze, T., Jeck, U.R., Eds.; John Benjamins: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2018; pp. 157–194. [Google Scholar]
- Runggaldier, E. Die Menschliche Seele bei Albertus Magnus. Ein Nicht-Reduktionistischer Beitrag zum Leib-Seele-Problem (Lectio Albertina 11); Aschendorff: Münster, Germany, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Johnston, H. Intellectual Abstraction in St. Albert. Philos. Stud. 1960, 10, 204–212. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Krause, K.; Anzulewicz, H. Albert the Great’s Interpretatio: Converting Libraries into a Scientific System. In Premodern Translation: Comparative Approaches to Cross-Cultural Transformations; Brentjes, S., Fidora, A., Eds.; Brepols: Turnhout, Belgium, 2021; pp. 89–132. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Anzulewicz, H.; Rinotas, A. Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues. Philosophies 2025, 10, 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108
Anzulewicz H, Rinotas A. Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues. Philosophies. 2025; 10(5):108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108
Chicago/Turabian StyleAnzulewicz, Henryk, and Athanasios Rinotas. 2025. "Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues" Philosophies 10, no. 5: 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108
APA StyleAnzulewicz, H., & Rinotas, A. (2025). Albert the Great on Soul: Some Hermeneutical Issues. Philosophies, 10(5), 108. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10050108