As noted in the introduction, this is the first analysis of relative clauses in Mende in the generative tradition of which I am aware.
10 As such, the following sections provide a detailed description and analysis of their structure. I analyze relative clauses in Mende under a Kaynian (D+CP) approach (
Kayne 1994), arguing that the head of the relative clause originates inside of a CP complement to a head in the DP functional structure, and raises to SpecDP. As I show below, this is strikingly similar to what is found in ordinary DPs.
In (29a), a relativized subject
nyapuisia ‘the girls’ as the head of the relative clause is shown. The object and verb follow, with temporal and locative adjuncts occurring post-verbally. Mende RCs do not have a relative pronoun, and relativized subjects do not have a resumptive pronoun. Differing from a matrix clause, it is ungrammatical for a neutral marker (
lɔ) to surface on the verb. In (29b), a relativized object is shown, which precedes the clause. In contrast to relativized subject in (29a), the 3rd person plural resumptive pronoun
ti surfaces in the object position, resuming the object
tɛisia ‘the chickens.’ The verb is marked for past tense, but, again, no neutral marker can appear.
11(29) | a. | Subject Relativization | |
| | nyàpú-í-sìài | [ti | tá | tέ-í-sìà | màjíá |
| | girl-def-pl | | 3pl.hab | chicken-def-pl | sell |
| | (*l ) | wàtì | gbí | nj p wá | hùn] |
| | nm | time | all | market | at |
| | ‘The girls who always sell the chickens at the market.’ |
| b. | Object Relativization | |
| | tέ-í-sìàj | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíj | yèyá-nì |
| | chicken-def-pl | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | buy-prf |
| | (*l ) | nj p wá | hùn] | |
| | nm | market | at | |
| | ‘The chickens that the girls bought at the market.’ |
Having argued that the head of the relative clause begins within the clause, I next show that the relative clause is a CP. Evidence for this includes the presence of topic and focus constructions in the left periphery of the relative clause. In (31a), the head of the relative clause is the subject of the matrix clause, while (31b) is a topic construction and (31c) is a focus construction. In
Section 2.4, I argued that both topics and focus constructions occur in the left periphery, and these data show that left peripheral constructions can occur in a relative clause. We can conclude, therefore, that the relative clause is, in fact, a CP.
(31) | | Relative clause left periphery |
| a. | nyàpú-í-sìài | [Kpànâ | tìi | l -nì | kpàà | hùn |
| | girl-def-pl | Kpana | 3pl.rp | see-pst | farm | on |
| | gbóí] | tí | mbè-í | m l -ì | l | |
| | yesterday | 3pl.sm | rice-def | burn-pst | nm | |
| | ‘The girls that Kpana saw yesterday on the farm burned the rice.’ |
| b. | nyàpú-í-sìài, | [gbóí | vá, | Kpànâ | tíi | l -nì |
| | girl-def-pl | yesterday | for | Kpana | 3pl.rp | see-prf |
| | kpàà | hùn] | tí | mbè-í | m l -ì | l |
| | farm | on | 3pl.sm | rice-def | burn-pst | nm |
| | ‘The girls, as for yesterday, Kpana saw them on the farm (they) burned the rice.’ |
| c. | nyàpú-í-sìài | [kpáá | hùn | mìà | Kpànâ | tìi | |
| | girl-def-pl | farm | on | foc.l | Kpana | 3pl.rp | |
| | l -nì | nà | gbóí] | tí | mbè-í | m l -ì | l |
| | see-pst | loc | yesterday | 3pl.sm | rice-def | burn-pst | nm |
| | ‘The girls, it is on the farm that Kpana saw them yesterday (they) burned the rice.’ |
4.2.1. The Derivation of Relative Clauses
The derivation of a relative clause is set out in (45). The relativized nominal (‘NP’) begins within the CP. The NP raises to SpecCP, and it subsequently raises into the specifier of a relative phrase (RelP) (as proposed by
Collins 2015). Paralleling the structure laid out in (28), I suggest, instead, that it is the Num head that selects the Relative Phrase with the NP raising into the DP left periphery, via SpecNumP before surfacing in SpecDP. In the remainder of this section, I motivate this analysis.
(32) | Derivation of a relative clause |
| |
I want to briefly point out that the tree in (32) does not capture the full derivation. Crucially, under this analysis the DP head of the relative clause is not a constituent. I propose that relative clause constructions in Mende are derived when the CP portion of the clause raises into the specifier of a functional phrase that I call an ExtraP (see
Section 2.2 for a similar argument for CP complements). The DP remnant then raises into a higher position. This can be seen in the following data, where in (33a) the object appears in a pre-verbal position, with the CP portion remaining post-verbal. Though not as clearly evident, I propose that a similar process yields the word order in (33b). I discuss ‘extraposition’ in greater detail in the following section.
(33) | a. | Object-modifying RC | | | | |
| | Kpànâ | njè-í-sìài | màjìà-í | l | [ti | tí | ngì | lέ-ngá | gbálè-nì] |
| | Kpana | goat-def-pl | sell-pst | nm | | 3pl.sm | 3sg | chicken-pl | hurt-pst |
| | ‘Kpana sold the goats that hurt his chickens.’ |
| b. | Subject-modifying RC | | | |
| | nyàpú-í-sìài | [ti | tí | njé-í-sìà | g k -ní] | tí | káté-í | kpàyà-í | l |
| | girl-def-pl | | 3pl.sm | goat-def-pl | find-pst | 3pl.sm | fence-def | strengthen-pst | nm |
| | ‘The girls who found the goats strengthened the fence.’ |
I turn next to reconstruction effects to argue that the head of the relative clause originates within the clause. The first evidence that I consider is reflexive binding. In (34a) and (34b), the DO is bound by the subject, with the object in (34a) being non-reflexive, while the object in (34b) is reflexive. In both cases, it is a possessive construction. In (34c), the nominal constituent containing the reflexive
ta kpe ‘himself’ is the head of the relative clause and has raised into a pre-verbal position, with the relative clause in a post-verbal position. In this position,
ta kpe ‘himself’ can take either
Kpana or
John as antecedent. Since
ta kpe can be understood as referring to
John, we can conclude that it reconstructs into the relative clause. In other words, in regards to binding, it behaves as if it were in its canonical position between the subject and verb of the relative clause. In (34d), the reflexive surfaces in the left periphery of the matrix clause, but can reconstruct into the c-command domain of
John (as indicated by the subscripts).
(34) | | Reconstruction effects: reflexive binding |
| a. | J ni | [ngìj/Kpànâj | nὲnέ-í-sìà | gbá | kòló | má] | ndàlá-í | l |
| | John | 3sg/Kpana | shadow-def-pl | stuck | paper | on | draw-pst | nm |
| | ‘John drew pictures of him/Kpana’ | | |
| b. | J ni | {[tá | kpé]i | nὲnέ-í-sìà | gbá | |
| | John | 3sg | self | shadow-def-pl | stuck | |
| | kòló | má} | ndàlá-í | l | | |
| | paper | on | draw-pst | nm | | |
| | ‘John drew pictures of himself.’ |
| c. | Kpànâj | {[tá | kpé]i/j | nὲnέ-í-sìà | gbá | kòlò |
| | Kpana | 3sg | self | shadow-def-pl | stuck | paper |
| | má}k | l -í | l | [J ni | tìk | ndálá-nì |
| | on | see-pst | nm | John | 3pl.rp | draw-pst |
| | ‘Kpana saw pictures of himself that John drew.’ |
| d. | {[tá | kpé]i/j | nέnέ-í-sìà | gbá | kòlò | mà}k | |
| | 3sg | self | shadow-def-pl | stuck | paper | on | |
| | mìà | Kpànâj | tìk | l -nì | [J ni | tìk | ndálá-nì] |
| | foc.l | Kpana | 3pl.rp | see-pst | John | 3pl.rp | draw-pst |
| | ‘It is pictures of himself that Kpana saw that John drew.’ |
Further evidence for the promotion analysis comes from quantifier scope. In (35a), it is scopally ambiguous. Under the subject wide scope reading, every boy works on a possibly different book (∀ > ∃). When the object takes a wide scope, this corresponds to a situation in which there is a particular book that every boy worked on (∃ > ∀). In (35b), the direct object of the RC-internal verb has been relativized (and the RC extraposed so that it follows the matrix verb). Crucially, (35b) is still scopally ambiguous. Specifically, ‘book’ can reconstruct into a relative clause and scope under the RC-internal subject. (The wide scope reading of ‘book’ would be expected from its surface position). Given the evidence from binding and quantifier scope, I conclude that the promotion analysis is on the right track for Mende.
(35) | | Quantifier scope | |
| a. | híndólópò | gbí | tí | k l | jèwé-í | l |
| | boy | all | 3pl.sm | book | write-pst | nm |
| | ‘Every boy wrote a book.’ (√ A book x, such that every boy wrote x ∃ > ∀ √ Every boy x wrote a possibly different book y ∀ > ∃) |
| b. | Kpànâ | k l | yèyá-í | l | [híndólòpò | gbí | tí | sèwè-nì] |
| | Kpana | book | buy-pst | nm | boy | all | 3pl.sm | write-pst |
| | ‘Kpana bought a book that every boy wrote.’ (√ A book x, such that every boy wrote x ∃ > ∀ √ Every boy x wrote a possibly different book y ∀ > ∃) |
4.2.2. Relative Clause Extraposition as Stranding
In order to more fully understand the process, in this section I explore the distribution of subject and object relative clauses in Mende. Crucially, I will argue that relative clauses always extrapose in Mende.
I begin by setting out in the following examples the position of object and subject- modifying relative clauses.
12 In the object-modifying relative clauses in (36), the head of the RC functions as the direct object of the matrix clause. The DO/head of the RC surfaces pre-verbally, with the actual RC occurring post-verbally. In both (36a) and (36b), the subject marker in the RC agrees in number with the RC subject and in tense/aspect with the RC verb. In (36a), a subject relativizing clause, there is no resumptive pronoun for the head of the clause
nyapuisia ‘the girls’, which surfaces as the clausal direct object above the verb, while in (36b), an object relativizing clause, the 3rd person plural resumptive pronoun
ti surfaces in the canonical direct object position of the head of the RC.
(36) | | Object-modifying RC |
| a. | Kpànâ | nyàpú-í-sìài | màlé-í | l | [ti |
| | Kpana | girl-def-pl | meet-pst | nm | |
| | tá | tέ-í-sìà | màjíà | wátí | gbí] |
| | 3pl.hab | chicken-def-pl | sell | time | all |
| | ‘Kpana met the girls who always sell the chickens.’ |
| b. | Kpànâ | wátí | gbí | à | tέ-í-sìàj | vàwé | l |
| | Kpana | time | all | 3sg.hab | chicken-def-pl | disturb | nm |
| | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíj | yéyà-nì | nj p wá | hùn] | |
| | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | buy-pst | market | at | |
| | ‘Kpana always disturbs the chickens that the girls bought at the market.’ |
In (37a), a grammatical construction with a pre-verbal DP object and post-verbal modifying RC is shown, which I argue results from stranding. In (37b), it is shown that it is ungrammatical for the DP and RC to both surface pre-verbally, while (37c) shows that they cannot both follow the verb.
(37) | | Stranded RC modifier of a DP object | | |
| a. | Pìtá | nìké-í-sìài | mὲní-í | l | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíi | g k -nì] |
| | Peter | cow-def-pl | hear-pst | nm | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | find-pst |
| | ‘Peter heard the cows that the girls found.’ | | |
| b. | *Pìtá | nìké-í-sìài | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíi | g k -nì] | mὲní-í | l |
| | Peter | cow-def-pl | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | find-pst | hear-pst | nm |
| | ‘Peter heard the cows that the girls found.’ | | |
| c. | *Pìtá | mὲní-í | l | nike-i-siai | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíi | g k -nì] |
| | Peter | hear-pst | nm | cow-def-pl | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | find-pst |
| | ‘Peter heard the cows that the girls found.’ | | |
Consider next the data in (38), in which the Relative Clause CP can surface either in a position to the left or right of the aspectual adverb
kpɔ ‘already.’ If the CP surfaces above the adverb, I assume that it has raised out of the verb phrase. In either case, the CP is stranded below the surface position of the verb.
(38) | CP raising | | | | | |
| Pìtá | nìké-í-sìài | mὲní-í | l | {kp } | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíi | g k -nì] | {kp } |
| Peter | cow-def-pl | hear-pst | nm | already | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | find-pst | already |
| ‘Peter already heard the cows that the girls found.’ | | | | |
The structure of an object-modifying relative clause is laid out in (39) with the source and surface position of the relativized constituent underlined. The head of the relative clause has raised into a pre-verbal position, while the relative clause CP is stranded.
(39) | Object-modifying relative clause |
| S SM O V {X] [RC] {X} | | | |
In the following example, I suggest a derivation for how the surface structure of a direct object-modifying relative clause surfaces in Mende. Consider (40), in which the head of the relative clause
nyapu ‘girl’ merges within the relative CP. It raises through SpecCP and SpecRelP into SpecNumP then SpecDP. The CP portion of the relative clause, which is a constituent, subsequently raises into the specifier of the Extraposition Phrase.
13 I refer to this extraposition phrase above the vP as ExtraP
l. This leaves the derived DP to remnant movement, raising for Case into SpecKaseP.
(40) | a. | Kpànâ | nyàpú-í-sìài | màlé-í | l | [ti | tá | tέ-í-sìà |
| | Kpana | girl-def-pl | meet-pst | nm | | 3pl.hab | chicken-def-pl |
| | màjíà | wátí | gbí] | | | | |
| | sell | time | all | | | | |
| | ‘Kpana met the girls who always sell the chickens.’ |
| b. | DP and CP Raising from an Object-Modifying Relative Clause |
| | |
This analysis aligns with
Kayne’s (
1994, p. 121) proposal that relative clauses remain stranded in a non-Case marked position below the normal Case-marked positions, with the verb raising above this position, as well (c.f.
Bianchi 1999).
I turn next to subject-modifying relative clauses. In (41), the head of the RC
nyapuisia ‘the girls’ functions as the matrix subject. The modifying RC follows the subject and is in turn followed by the subject marker of the matrix clause. The direct object, verb, and any post-verbal material follow. Note in (41a), with a subject relativizing clause, that the subject marker in the RC
ta agrees with the matrix subject (the promoted subject of the RC) and encodes habitual aspect. The matrix subject marker
ti surfaces after the relative clause and agrees with the matrix subject. In (41b), with an object relativizing clause, the subject marker of the RC
ti agrees with the number of the RC subject and the tense of the verb, while the clausal subject marker
ta agrees in number with the matrix subject and in habitual aspect with the matrix verb. As expected, the resumptive pronoun
ti occurs in the direct object position in the relative clause from which the clausal subject raised.
(41) | | Subject-modifying relative clauses |
| a. | nyàpú-í-sìài | [ti | tá | tέ-í-sìà | màjíá | wátí |
| | girl-def-pl | | 3pl.hab | chicken-def-pl | sell | time |
| | gbí] | tí | Kpànâ | màlé-í | l | |
| | all | 3pl.sm | Kpana | meet-pst | nm | |
| | ‘The girls who always sell the chickens met Kpana.’ |
| b. | tὲ-í-sìài | [nyàpú-í-sìà | tí | tíi | yèyà-nì | nj p wá | hùn] |
| | chicken-def-pl | girl-def-pl | 3pl.sm | 3pl.rp | buy-pst | market | at |
| | tá | Kpànâ | vàwé | l | wátí | gbí | |
| | 3pl.hab | Kpana | disturb | nm | time | all | |
| | ‘The chickens that the girls bought at the market always disturb Kpana.’ |
Similar to object-modifying relative clauses, the head of a subject-modifying relative clause raises out of the clause into a higher position. Being the matrix subject, I argue that it raises into SpecFinP. The surface structure of a subject-modifying relative clause is laid out in (42).
(42) | Subject-modifying relative clause |
| S [RC] SM O V {X} |
In (43), it is shown that an adverb can intervene between the subject and the relative clause, and I conclude that the DP and relative CP have split.
(43) | Stranded RC modifier of subject | | |
| nyàpú-í-sìài | {kp } | [ti | tá | tὲ-í-sìà | màjíá | wátí |
| girl-def-pl | already | | 3pl.hab | chicken-def-pl | sell | time |
| gbí] | tí | Kpànâ | màlé-í | l | | |
| all | 3pl.sm | Kpana | meet-pst | nm | | |
| ‘The girls who always sell the chickens (already) met Kpana.’ | |
In this construction, the subject is in SpecFinP with the relative clause intervening between the subject
nyapuisia and the matrix subject marker
ti. I propose the following derivation (leaving out the adverb for simplicity). The DP subject (including the RC) raises from the vP into SpecSubjP, triggering agreement with the Subj head. At this point, similar to the object-modifying relative clause, the CP portion of the relative clause raises into an extraposition phrase (SpecExtraP
h). The DP subject then raises into SpecFinP, yielding the surface word order.
(44) | a. | nyàpú-í-sìài | [ti | tá | tέ-í-sìà | màjíá | wátí |
| | girl-def-pl | | 3pl.hab | chicken-def-pl | sell | time |
| | gbí] | tí | Kpànâ | màlé-í | l | |
| | all | 3pl.sm | Kpana | meet-pst | nm | |
| | ‘The girls who always sell the chickens met Kpana.’ |
| b. | Derivation of subject-modifying RC |
| | |
In summary, I have shown a parallel process for both object- and subject-modifying relative clauses. In both instances, the CP portion of the relative clause raises into an extraposition phrase, leaving the DP portion to raise into its surface position (SpecKaseP for the object and SpecFinP for the subject).
Baltin (
1981,
2006) argues that constituents extraposed from subjects adjoin to IP, while constituents extraposed from objects adjoin to VP. He argues that an extraposed phrase adjoins to the first maximal phrase that dominates its phrase of origin (
Baltin 2006, p. 241). While my analysis does not support this assertion, it does seem that in Mende the extraposition phrases are adjoined at the positions for which he argues.
4.2.3. Relative Clause Mixed Islands
Having established the distribution of subject- and object-modifying relative clauses, I turn next to their status as mixed islands. Consider the subject-modifying relative clauses in (45), in which the head of the relative clause is promoted from within the clause to the matrix subject position. The DP (including the relative clause) raises to SpecSubjP, triggering agreement with the Subject Marker. The relative clause CP then raises into SpecExtraP
h, while the matrix subject raises into SpecFinP.
(45) | a. | nìké-í-sìài | [hùmám -í | tìi | hùmá-ngá] | tí | lùgbá-ì | l |
| | cow-def-pl | thief-def | 3pl.sm | steal-prf | 3pl.sm | stumble-pst | nm |
| | pὲlέ-í | hùn | | | | |
| | road-def | on | | | | | |
| | ‘The cows that the thief stole stumbled on the road.’ | |
| b. | Subject-modifying RC | |
| | |
In this type of construction, the subject of the relative clause can be wh-questioned and move out of the relative clause and into the left peripheral focus position.
(46) | yèi | míà | nìké-í-sìàj | [ìi | tìj | hùmá-ngá] |
| who | foc.l | cow-def-pl | 3sg.rp | 3pl.rp | steal-prf |
| tíi | lùgbá-ní | pὲlὲ-í | hùn | | |
| 3pl.sm | stumble-pst | road-def | on | | |
| ‘Who is it that stole the cows that stumbled on the road?’ |
In (62), the wh-questioned subject of the relative clause moves into SpecFocP, with a resumptive pronoun surfacing in its pre-movement position. In this construction, the relative clause is not an island.
(47) | Movement out of subject-modifying RC |
| |
Consider next a subject-modifying RC (bracketed in (48a)) in an embedded clause (in curly brackets). In (48b), partial movement to the left periphery of the embedded clause is shown, while (48c) shows that wh-word can move to the clausal left periphery.
(48) | | Embedded clause with subject-modifying RC: partial and full movement |
| a. | Mὲlí | mὲní-í | {kὲ | nìké-í-sìài | [hùmám -í | tíi |
| | Mary | hear-pst | c | cow-def-pl | thief-def | 3pl.rp |
| | hùmá-ngá] | tí | lùgbá-ì | l | pὲlὲ-í | hùn} |
| | steal-prf | 3pl.sm | stumble-pst | nm | road-def | on |
| | ‘Mary heard that the cows that the thief stole stumbled on the road.’ |
| b. | Mὲlí | mὲní-í | {kὲ | yèj | míà | nìké-í-sìài | [ìj |
| | Mary | hear-pst | c | who | foc.l | cow-def-pl | 3sg.rp |
| | tíi | hùmá-ngá] | tí | lúgbà-nì | pὲlὲ-í | hùn} | |
| | 3pl.rp | steal-prf | 3pl.sm | stumble-pst | road-def | on | |
| | ‘Mary heard that it was who that stole the cows that stumbled on the road?’ |
| c. | yèj | míà | Mὲlí | mὲní-í | {kὲ | nìké-í-sìài | [ìj |
| | who | foc.l | Mary | hear-pst | c | cow-def-pl | 3sg.rp |
| | tìi | hùmá-ngá] | tí | lúgbà-nì | pὲlὲ-í | hùn} | |
| | 3pl.rp | steal-prf | 3pl.sm | stumble-pst | road-def | on | |
| | ‘Who is x such that Mary heard that x stole the cows that stumbled on the road?’ |
In contrast to the subject-modifying relative clause, movement out of an object-modifying relative clause is not sanctioned. As noted above, the DP head of an object-modifying relative clause obligatorily moves into a pre-verbal position for Case assignment.
14 The relative CP moves into SpecExtraP
l, remaining below the verb, as it does not need to raise for Case. This structure is shown in (49).
(49) | a. | Kpànâ | [kúlé-í-sìà]i | wúá-ì | l | [màhé-í | tìi | yéyá-nì] |
| | Kpana | cloth-def-pl | wash-pst | nm | chief-def | 3pl.rp | buy-pst |
| | ‘Kpana washed the clothes that the chief bought.’ | |
| b. | Object-modifying relative clause | |
| | |
In contrast to subject-modifying clauses, movement out of an object-modifying relative clause is blocked, as seen in (50) with the analysis in (51). The head of the RC raises into SpecKaseP with the relative CP stranded in SpecExtraP
l. In this construction, the relative clause is an island.
(50) | *yèi | míà | Kpànâ | [kúlé-í-sìà]j | wúá-nì | [ìi | tìj | yéyá-nì] |
| who | foc.l | Kpana | cloth-def-pl | wash-pst | 3sg.rp | 3pl.rp | buy-pst |
| ‘Who is it that Kpana washed the clothes that he bought?’ |
(51) | *Movement out of an object-modifying RC |
| |
This same pattern occurs in partial- and full-movement constructions. In (52a), the verb
mɛni ‘hear’ takes a CP complement (in curly brackets) containing an object-modifying relative clause (bracketed). Partial movement out of the relative clause to the embedded clause left periphery is blocked (52b), as is movement out of the RC to the matrix left periphery (52c).
(52) | | Embedded clause with an object-modifying RC: partial and full movement |
| a. | Mὲlí | mὲní-í | l | {kὲ | Kpànâ | [kúlé-í-sìà]i |
| | Mary | hear-pst | nm | c | Kpana | cloth-def-pl |
| | wúá-ì | l | [màhé-í | tìi | yéyá-nì]} | |
| | wash-pst | nm | chief-def | 3pl.rp | buy-pst | |
| | ‘Mary heard that Kpana washed the clothes that the chief bought.’ |
| b. | *Mὲlí | mὲní-í | l | {kὲ | yèj | míà |
| | Mary | hear-pst | nm | c | who | foc.l |
| | Kpànâ | [kúlé-í-sìà]i | wúá-nì | [ìj | tìi | yéyá-nì]} |
| | Kpana | cloth-def-pl | wash-pst | 3sg.rp | 3pl.rp | buy-pst |
| | Intended: Who is x such that Mary heard that Kpana washed the clothes that x bought? |
| c. | *yèi | míà | Mὲlí | mὲní-í | {kὲ | Kpànâ |
| | who | foc | Mary | hear-pst | c | Kpana |
| | [kúlé-í-sìà]j | wúá-ì | l | [ìi | tìj | yéyá-nì]} |
| | cloth-def-pl | wash-pst | nm | 3sg.rp | 3pl.rp | buy-pst |
| | Intended: Who is x such that Mary heard that Kpana washed the clothes that x bought? |
The previous data highlight an asymmetry between subject-modifying and object-modifying relative clauses in regards to their status as islands. While movement is possible out of subject-modifying relative clauses, it is blocked for object-modifying RCs. As such, I refer to them as mixed islands, since their status as an island is dependent on the position of the relative clause within the matrix clause. When the relative clause CP is in SpecExtraPh, which immediately dominates SubjP, extraction is possible. On the other hand, when it is in SpecExtraPl, movement is blocked.
In both cases, the relative clause is in SpecExtraP, and, as such, it is the position of the extraposition clause which determines whether movement out of the RC is permitted. This can be seen in comparing the structures in (53a), where the subject-modifying RC is in SpecExtraP
h and (53b), where the object-modifying RC is in SpecExtraP
l.
(53) | a. | Subject-Modifying configuration |
| | |
| b. | Object-Modifying configuration |
| | |
Extraction out of relative clauses has been indicated in the literature, particularly in African (
Kandybowicz et al. 2021,
2023;
Schurr et al. 2024;
Murphy and Korsah, forthcoming) and Mainland Scandinavian languages (
Engdahl 1997;
Kush et al. 2013,
2019;
Müller 2014,
2015). Studies indicate that there is an A-bar movement from relative clauses (
Christensen and Nyvad 2014;
Lindahl 2014,
2017,
2022), and there is consensus that relative clauses are weak islands in various languages, including Danish (
Müller and Eggers 2022) and Swedish (
Lindahl 2014), as well as English (
Vincent et al. 2022) and Hebrew (
Sichel 2018). However, acceptability ratings have been shown to be low (
Poulsen 2008;
Müller 2015,
2019). Factors such as the embedding verb (
Erteschik-Shir 1973;
Lindahl 2022), whether the sentence is existential or not (
Kush et al. 2021;
Lindahl 2022;
Vincent et al. 2022), as well as the content of what is extracted (
Müller and Eggers 2022) influence acceptability.
While both Mainland Scandinavian and Mende allow for extraction out of relative clauses, the contexts in which it is permitted vary. For Mainland Scandinavian, factors include the embedding verb, whether the clause is existential or not, and the content of what is fronted. In Mende, the factor seems to be syntactic. Movement out of subject-modifying RCs is sanctioned, and it is otherwise blocked. Mende does not fit the traditional notion of a weak island, in the sense that some phrase types can be moved out while others cannot (
Szabolcsi and den Dikken 2002), and it therefore seems to represent a unique island variety cross-linguistically. Further research on other types of relative clauses in Mende, as well as the structure and distribution of relative clauses in other Mande languages might prove insightful.
In this section, I have sought to describe the structure and distribution of relative clauses in Mende. I have argued that they obligatorily raise, so that the head of the clause can move as a constituent into a higher position (either SpecKaseP or SpecFinP.) The relative clause raises first into SpecExtraP before the DP head of the clause remnant moves into its higher position. I have shown that while wh-movement is possible out of a subject-modifying RC, it is blocked out of object-modifying RCs. Therefore, subject-modifying RCs do not have the status of (strong/weak) islands in Mende.