Spiritual Loving and Mental Health: A Schelerian Perspective
Abstract
“[I]n the final analysis we should promote welfare for the sake of the dignity of man’s spiritual personality; within that dignity the crown and nucleus is the freest and purest readiness to love. It is in the way of humility, in free and loving service, that this very dignity must reach perfection. We should further the welfare of man so that he may become ripe to love and in loving sow the seed of all virtues.”
“The eternal irony of a hedonist is that he loses more pleasure, the more energetically he strives for pleasure—and not for the things that yield pleasure.”
1. Introduction
2. The Five Ideologies of the Human Being
2.1. The Fallen Man
2.2. Homo Sapiens
2.3. Homo Faber
2.4. Dionysian Man
2.5. Übermenschenidee
3. A Loving Being (Ens Amans)
4. Spirit [Geist]
5. Personalism
6. Well-Being and Mental Health
7. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | That is, a view that interprets all living things organologically with the categories of a positive, effective, idea-like form, and a negative (μὴὄν), suffering factor of being (materia). Whether the concept of the logos is indeed a Greek invention or had existed long before Plato explicated it in a text remains a discussion among scholars of antiquity. See for example, (Bos 1996). |
2 | In Scheler’s view, Hegel pointed out that only through the process of becoming does the human beings attain and is supposed to attain an increasing self-consciousness of what he is from eternity according to his idea. That is, the self-consciousness of his freedom, which is superior to instincts (drives) and nature. In this sense, Hegel denied the constancy (stability) of human reason throughout history, which Scheler saw as a tremendous progress in philosophical anthropology. Scheler’s Hegel sees a history of the subjective categorical worlds of forms and shapes of the human spirit itself [Formenwelten und Gestalten des menschlichen Geistes selbst]; not just a history of the cumulation of the works of reason [Er kennt eine Geschichte der subjektiven kategorialen Formenwelten und Gestalten des menschlichen Geistes selbst-nicht nur eine Geschichte der Kumulation der Werke der Vernunft]. This history of the human spirit is, Scheler contends, independent of the biological change in human nature, and it is the history of the becoming of self-consciousness of the eternal divinity and its eternal categorical world of ideas in man, that is, the history of the becoming of the dynamic λόγος of the Greeks. Instincts and passions are introduced in this case only as servants of the Logos, cleverly chosen instruments of the divine idea, through which it reaches a goal, establishes a harmony and a balance that no one knows. |
3 | As stated by Scheler, the first of these three naturalistic theories is the so-called economic (Marxist) conception of history primarily as class struggle and “struggle for the feeding place”. Second is the naturalistic conception of history that sees the primal instinct of reproducing the species in its qualitative and quantitative forms, which Scheler terms as the process of “blood mixing and segregation”. Third is the naturalistic conception of history as a history of power struggles—that is, the struggle for domination of states, classes, and groups within the states that determine the basic patterns of economic spiritual and cultural being and events (GW IX.133; Scheler 1958, p. 80). |
4 | “Was ist der Mensch für ein Ding?” ist die Antwort dieser Anthropologie: Der Mensch ist der auf seine bloßen Surrogate (Sprache, Werkzeug usw.) echter entfaltungsfähiger Lebenseigenschaften und -Tätigkeiten hin in krankhafter Steigerung seines Selbstgefühls dahinlebende Déserteur des Lebens überhaupt, seiner Grundwerte, seiner Gesetze, seines heiligen kosmischen Sinnes (GW IX.135). |
5 | This is a view that Scheler takes to have been inspired by Schopenhauer. |
6 | As determined by Scheler, one of the characteristics that this Dionysian theory shares with rational anthropology is the sharp ontological distinction between life and spirit. However, the concept of spirit is conceived in the Dionysian theory as nothing but the thought that characterizes technical intelligence in the same manner as positivists and pragmatists. The problem, Scheler points out, is that this technical concept of spirit cannot grasp the ontic and valid realm of value, since its objects are “ficta” and therefore it cannot open up a new realm of being to man as a logos, nor a realm of value as pure love. This technical spirit only creates more and more complicated means and mechanisms for drives, which it corrupts and brings out of their natural harmony. |
7 | For Scheler, the “transcendental reasoning” [transzendentale Schlußweise] for this philosophical anthropology states that since the being of the world itself is certainly independent of the fortuitous existence of the human being on earth and his empirical consciousness, but since there are nevertheless strict essential connections between certain classes of their spiritual acts and certain realms of being to which we gain access through these spiritual acts, then all these spiritual acts must be ascribed to the attributes of the Ground of Being, that is, spirit and impulsion. The guiding insight here is that the ultimate source of everything that exists objectively cannot by itself be objective, but is rather only a pure executable actuality of an attribute of an eternally self-creating being. [Leitende Einsicht ist dabei, daß der oberste Grund alles dessen, was gegenstandsfähig ist, selber nicht gegenstandsfähig ist, sondern nur reine vollziehbare Aktualität als Attribut des ewig sich selbst hervorbringenden Seins.] (GW IX.82–83; Scheler 1958, pp. 10–11). |
8 | This essay was an address to the German Institute of Politics [Deutsche Hochschule fur Politik] on 5 November 1927, in Berlin. (GW IX.145–170; Scheler 1958, pp. 94–1260). |
9 | Scheler writes: “The All-man in the absolute sense, of course—the idea of the human being who contains all his essential possibilities in himself—he is hardly close to us; indeed, he is as far away from us as God, who, as far as we comprehend his essence in spirit and life, is nothing but the essence of man—only in infinite form and fullness. For every world age, however, there is a relative all-man, a maximum of all-humanity that is accessible to him, a relative maximum of participation in all the highest forms of human existence.” (GW IX.151; Scheler 1958, p. 102). |
10 | (GW IX.168; Scheler 1958, pp. 122–23). |
11 | For example, the drive behind the ideology of the Dionysian man is the attempt to re-sublimate the exaggerated intellectualism of the idea of the homo sapiens in order to free the vital drives in human beings. (GW IX.156; Scheler 1958, p. 108) This re-sublimation is reactive, a move towards a counter-ideal, which is not a direct expression of the surplus of forces. (GW IX.157; Scheler 1958, p. 109) The Dionysian man is thus a countermodel of the idea of homo sapiens. This means that the ideology of the Dionysian man depends on the value content of the ideology of homo sapiens remains visible in it. For Scheler, countermodels are “in direct opposition to a prevailing model, whereby the dependence of the value-structure on the content of the model remains visible in the countermodel’s content.” (See GW II.558; Scheler 1973a, p. 572) |
12 | [Der Mensch aber ist kein Ding-er ist eine Richtung der Bewegung des Universums selbst, ja seines Grundes.] GW IX.151. |
13 | Scheler’s notion of Geist is not a reference to the Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit that reveals the historical background of pure abstract concepts on which reason is erected. In this sense, spirit itself cannot be sublated in the Hegelian Absolute Idea; only the actualized (or vitalized) spirit can be sublated. |
14 | For Scheler, a person is not the same as an embodied subjectivity or lived-body individuation of a human being, as we see, for example, in Paul Ricoeur’s view of the person, which the latter describes as “one of the things that we distinguish by means of identifying reference”, with language as the designator of individuals (Ricoeur 1992, p. 27). |
15 | “Geist ist daher Sachlichkeit, Bestimmbarkeit durch das Sosein von Sachen selbst. Geist “hat” nur ein zu vollendeter Sachlichkeit fähiges Lebewesen. Schärfer gesagt: Nur ein solches Wesen ist “Träger” des Geistes, dessen prinzipieller Verkehr mit der Wirklichkeit außerhalb seiner wie mit sich selber sich im Verhältnis zum Tiere mit Einschluß seiner Intelligenz dynamisch geradezu umgekehrt hat.” (GW IX.32). |
16 | For a detailed clarification of the distinction Scheler makes between feeling [Fulen] and feeling-states [Geful], see (Frings 1996; Steinbock 2021). Frings for examples explains that the distinction can be understood by viewing feeling as the function of the reception of feeling-states. “… feeling-states refer to a content, and feelings to the function of the reception of this content.” (Frings 1996, p. 28). |
17 | There is disagreement among contemporary hedonists regarding what constitutes pleasure, and whether it is just one basic mental state (monism) or several states (pluralism). For details of this discussion, see (Moore 2019). |
18 | See (Moore 2019). |
19 | Scheler writes, “… one can say that on Kant’s presupposition man as independent of the rational and formal moral law is an absolute egoist and an absolute sensual hedonist, and that he is this indiscriminately in all of his impulses. Of course, as Kant sees it, any ethics that is established through recourse to emotional experience [Er-leben] must for this reason be a hedonism, for apriority in the emotional sphere is entirely out of the question”. (GW II.248; Scheler 1973a, p. 241) The hedonism entailed in Scheler’s Kant has to do with the fact that Kant also erroneously presupposes that human affections and human emotions—what Scheler refers to as feeling [Fühlen]—are driven by maximising pleasure and diminishing displeasure. This means that it is inaccurate to claim that deontology does not presuppose hedonism just as in other normative ethical theories such as The Divine theory, Egoism, and Ultilitarianism. Therefore, Scheler proposes that “We must reject once and for all the presupposition of hedonism, shared by Kant, that man ‘originally’ strives for ‘pleasure’ (or even self-pleasure). In fact, no conation is originally more alien to man, and none is later acquired. This rare (and basically pathological) aberration and perversion of conation (which might have developed here and there into a socialpsychic movement), in which all things, goods, men, etc., are given only as possible and value-indifferent ‘stimulators of pleasure,’ should not be made into a ‘basic law’”. (GW II.56; Scheler 1973a, p. 36). |
20 | Scheler defined eudaemonism as “an ethics which either regards pleasure as the highest value (or the ‘highest good’) or somehow reduces the facts and ideas of the values of good and evil to pleasure and displeasure”. (GW II.246; Scheler 1973a, p. 239). |
21 | It should be noted that for Scheler, “In any striving for something, there is … a feeling directed toward some value that founds the pictorial or meaning-component of the striving. This peculiar relation is what is commonly called practical motivation. All motivation is an immediately experienced causality in the special sense of “causality of attraction” and is to be distinguished from the feeling-state from which the striving and willing issues forth”. (GW II.346; Scheler 1973a, pp. 344–45). |
22 | Full citation: “The reason for this is not that there are no pleasures other than sensible ones, or that all pleasure develops genetically from “sensible pleasure.” It is, rather, that the causes of sensible pleasure alone are immediately subject to practical control, e.g., within socioethical activities, first of all within relations of property”. (GW II.339; Scheler 1973a, p. 337). |
23 | As determined by Scheler, “the many forms of hedonism always reveal a token of “discontentment” with regard to higher values”. (GW II.114; Scheler 1973a, p. 97). |
24 | Full citation: “an advanced practical hedonism is a most certain sign of vital decadence in an entire era”. (GW II.347; Scheler 1973a, p. 345) In Scheler’s view, then, any hedonist and utilitarian ideas of well-being since they make the make the mistake of reducing valuemodality to the value ranks of the agreeable and the useful. In the same sense he would reject the rationalists make the (equally erroneous) mistake of reducing valuemodality it to intellectual values—especially the rational ones (GW II.124n; Scheler 1973a, p. 107n). |
25 | Intuitively, the most probable of the five ideology that fits this description may seem to be the “Dionysian man”, who views the vital values as the highest value rank, and ignores the values attained in the highest rank of the spirit dimension of the human being. However, elements of such decadence could also be fished out of the other ideologies of the human being. |
26 | Scheler describes four values ranks starting from the lower sensible values, vital values, intellectual values, to the highest personal value ranks. |
27 | For, it is this spiritual act of participation in the movement of the “higher-than-individual spirit” [übersingulären Geistes], that the values that structure human experience of the world are felt. This spiritual dimension of the human being cannot be controlled, and in it the person experiences the spiritual feeling and acts of preferring, loving, and hating, and feeling-states that range from humility and pride, blissfulness to despair, all of which are independent of “happiness” and “unhappiness” (GW II.125–126; Scheler 1973a, pp. 108–10). |
References
- Baring, Edward. 2019. Converts to the Real: Catholicism and the Making of Continental Philosophy. Cambridge: Havard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bos, Abraham P. 1996. Geboeid Door Plato. Het Christelijk Geloof Bekneld door het Glinsterend Pantser van de Griekse filosofie. Kampen: Kok. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1945. The Philosophical Anthropology of Max Scheler. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 6: 307–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chappell, Richard Y., and Darius Meissner. 2023. Theories of Well-Being. In An Introduction to Utilitarianism. Edited by Richard Y. Chappell, Darius Meissner and William MacAskill. Available online: https://www.utilitarianism.net/theories-of-wellbeing (accessed on 24 February 2025).
- Crisp, Roger. 2021. Well-Being. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2021 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/well-being/ (accessed on 24 February 2025).
- Davis, Zachary. 2015. Scheler on the Embodiment of Value. Thaumàzein-Rivista di Filosofia 3: 593–608. [Google Scholar]
- Dehue, Trudy. 2011. Ik maak drukte want ik ben een druktemaker. De Groene Amsterdammer, 30–33. [Google Scholar]
- Frings, Manfred S. 1980. Max Scheler: A Descriptive Analysis of the Concept of Ultimate Reality. Ultimate Reality and Meaning 3: 135–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frings, Manfred S. 1996. Max Scheler, A Concise Introduction into the World of a Great Thinker. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Frings, Manfred S. 2003. LifeTime: Max Scheler’s Philosophy of Time. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, Russel. 2024. William James. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2024 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman. vol. 44, Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2024/entries/james/ (accessed on 24 February 2025).
- Guyer, Paul, and Rolf-Peter Horstmann. 2023. Idealism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2023 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/idealism/ (accessed on 24 February 2025).
- Hackett, J. Edward. 2023. Radical Empiricism as Naturalistic Phenomenology vs. Non-naturalistic Phenomenology of Max Scheler. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 37: 503–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Huijs, Thijs, Arjan W. Braam, Renske Kruizinga, Nele Jacobs, Jennifer Reijnders, and Marianne Simons. 2024. Spirituality as a Predictor of Well-Being, Mental Distress or Both: A Four-Week Follow-Up Study in a Sample of Dutch and Belgian Adults. Religions 15: 179. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kelly, Eugene. 1997. Structure and Diversity: The Phenomenological Philosophy of Max Scheler. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [Google Scholar]
- Luther, Arthur. R. 1974. The Articulated Unity of Being in Scheler’s Phenomenology: Basic Drive and Spirit. In Max Scheler: Centennial Essays. Edited by Manfred Frings. The Hague: Martinus Nijhof, pp. 1–42. [Google Scholar]
- Moore, Andrew. 2019. Hedonism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2019 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/hedonism/ (accessed on 24 February 2025).
- Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 42–45. [Google Scholar]
- Nyaku, Kobla. 2022. Max Scheler’s Movement of Love and the Object of Religious Experience. Religions 13: 878. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ricoeur, P. 1992. Oneself As Another. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Roothaan, Angela. C. M. 2011. Geesten. Uitgebannen en Teruggekeerd in de Moderne Wereld. Meppel: Uitgeverij Boom. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 1958. Philosophical Perspectives. Translated by Oscar Haac. Boston: Beacon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 1960. On the Eternal in Man. Translated by Bernard Noble. London: SCM Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 1973a. Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. Translated by Manfred S. Frings, and Roger L. Funk. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 1973b. Selected Philosophical Essays. Translated by David Lachterman. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 1987. Person and Self-Value. Three Essays. Edited and Translated by Manfred S. Frings. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 2008. The Constitution of the Human Being. Translated by John Cutting. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 2009. The Human’s Place in the Cosmos. Translated by Manfred S. Frings. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 2015. The Past Masters Max Scheler: Gesammelte Werke und Schriften. Edited by K. Worm. Charlottesville: InteLex Corporation. Bern: Francke Verlag, 1954–1985. Electronic edn. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, F. Josef. 1974. Peace and Pacifism. In Max Scheler. Centennial Essays. Edited by Manfred Frings. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Spader, Peter. 2005. Scheler’s Ethical Personalism: Its Logic, Development, and Promise. Brooklyn: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Steinbock, Anthony J. 2021. Knowing by Heart: Loving as Participation and Critique. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa. 2019. A Phenomenologist in the United States. The Adventures of a Polish-Born American. In The Reception of Husserlian Phenomenology in North America. Edited by Michela B. Ferri and Carlo Ierna. Cham: Springer Nature, pp. 213–14. [Google Scholar]
- Weiss, Dennis. M. 1998. Max Scheler and Philosophical Anthropology. Philosophy Today 42: 235–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Williams, Thomas D., and Jan Olof Bengtsson. 2022. Personalism. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2022 ed. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/personalism/ (accessed on 24 February 2025).
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Nyaku, K. Spiritual Loving and Mental Health: A Schelerian Perspective. Religions 2025, 16, 941. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070941
Nyaku K. Spiritual Loving and Mental Health: A Schelerian Perspective. Religions. 2025; 16(7):941. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070941
Chicago/Turabian StyleNyaku, Kobla. 2025. "Spiritual Loving and Mental Health: A Schelerian Perspective" Religions 16, no. 7: 941. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070941
APA StyleNyaku, K. (2025). Spiritual Loving and Mental Health: A Schelerian Perspective. Religions, 16(7), 941. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070941