A New Way of “Thinking” Consciousness: Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, and Neo-Materialism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Nietzsche and Perspectivism
In all willing it is absolutely a question of commanding and obeying, on the basis, as already said, of a social structure composed of many “souls”. Hence a philosopher should claim the right to include willing-as-such within the sphere of morals—morals being understood as the doctrine of the relations of supremacy under which the phenomenon of “life” comes to be.(Beyond Good and Evil (Nietzsche 1966, p. 27))
2.1. The Invention of the Subject
2.2. Perspectivism as Kantian Transcendental Philosophy
2.3. Perspectivism Is Not a Relativism or Nihilism
Let us be on guard against the dangerous old conceptual fiction that posited a ‘pure, willing, painless, timeless knowing subject’; let us guard against the snares of such contradictory concepts as ‘pure reason’, ’absolute spirituality’, ‘knowledge in itself’ they always demand that we should think of an eye that is completely unthinkable, an eye turned in no particular direction, in which the active and interpreting forces, through which alone seeing becomes seeing something, are supposed to be lacking; these always demand of an eye an absurdity and a nonsense. There is only a perspective seeing, only a perspective ‘knowing’; and the more affects we allow to speak about one thing, the more eyes, different eyes, we can use to observe one thing, the more complete will our ‘concept’ of this thing, our ‘objectivity’ be.
This is the essence of phenomenalism and perspectivism as I understand them: Owing to the nature of animal consciousness, the world of which we can become conscious is only a surface- and sign-world, a world that is made common and meaner (in German ver(all)gemeinert, a pun on general and mean that does not work in English); whatever becomes conscious becomes by the same token shallow, thin, relatively stupid, general, sign, herd signal; all becoming conscious involves a great and thorough corruption, falsification, reduction to superficialities, and generalization. Ultimately, the growth of consciousness becomes a danger; and one who lives among the most conscious Europeans even knows that it is a disease.
3. Wittgenstein and the Form/s of Life
“Once a label gets on something, it becomes an “it”, like it is no longer alive”.(“What N.Y. Couples Fight About” Morcheeba Charango 2002)
3.1. Logical/Pictorial Form in the Tractatus
3.2. Some Remarks on Logical Form
3.3. Form of Life in the Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein 1968)
And to imagine a language means imagining a form of life.
Here the term “language-game” is meant to bring into prominence the fact that the speaking of a language is part of a life-form.(Ibid., p. 23)
“So you are saying that human agreement decides what is true and what is false?”—It is what human beings say that is true and false; and they agree in the language they use. That is not agreement in opinions but in form of language.(Ibid., p. 243)
Can only those hope who can talk? (Only those who have mastered the use of a language. That is to say, the phenomena of hope are mode of this complicated form of life. (If a concept refers to a character of human handwriting, it has no application to beings that do not write.)(Ibid., p. 174)
What has to be accepted, the given, is—so one could say—form of life.(Ibid., p. 226)
a matter of our sharing routes of interest and feeling, modes of response, senses of humor and of significance and of fulfillment, of what is outrageous, of what is similar to what else, what a rebuke, what forgiveness, of when an utterance is an assertion, when an appeal, when an explanation—all the whirl of organism Wittgenstein calls ‘form of life.’ Human Speech and activity, sanity and community, rest upon nothing more, but nothing less, than this.
any attempt to say what our form of life is like will itself be part of the form of life; it can have no more than the meaning it gets within the context of its use. As we try to stretch ourselves to say something philosophical, we end up saying things that are, strictly speaking, false. Let us say that a person is minded in a certain way, if he has the perceptions of salience, routes of interest, feelings of naturalness in following a rule, etc. that constitute being part of a certain form of life.
4. New Materialism
4.1. Nietzsche and (Neo-)Materialism
4.2. Jane Bennett and Vital Materialism
[…] linger in those moments during which they find themselves fascinated by objects, taking them as clues to the material vitality that they share with them. This sense of a strange and incomplete commonality with the out-side may induce vital-materialists to treat nonhumans—animals, plants, earth, even artifacts and commodities—more carefully, more strategically, more ecologically(ibid. pp. 17–18).
4.3. Impersonal Matter
5. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | This was recounted by Georges Didi-Huberman in The Surviving Image (Didi-Huberman 2002). Philippe-Alain Michaud also quotes the passage in Aby Warburg and the Image in Motion (Michaud 2004, p. 171). |
2 | Compare this with Donna Haraway’s new ideas on symbiosis and symbiogenesis in Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene (Haraway 2016, p. 49). She points out that the Anthropocene, the age that put the human in the center, has “proven unable to think well about sympoiesis, symbiosis, symbiogenesis, development […]” and she describes the new age of the Chthulucene in which this can be effected. The symbiogenesis is the crossing of a human child and an animal and the Camille Stories are the join of a human child and a monarch butterfly over five generations. The speculative fabulation and its brainchild Camille came from a writing workshop in a speculative fabulation. In this narration, the species do not merely live together—symbiosis—but are crossed or joined—symbiogenesis—and Haraway speculates about the “many surprises […] that emerged from the relations of the living and the dead […]” (Haraway 2016, p. 8). |
3 | This kind of thinking or knowing from the senses and in the medial in which we are creators and participants in the patterns we assemble is also the gist of my book on Guessing—Raten. Wissen aus dem Sinnlich-Medialen, in which I elaborate on an account of thinking that has its foundation not in cognition or logical inference—as in deduction and induction—but in sensible intuition or abduction. It is the work of making patterns in thinking through assembling, putting together, comparing, and through pattern recognition that becomes, at the same time, a recognition and invention of the connection rather than a mere cognition. (Cf. Moser 2025). |
4 | We, at the same time, recognize and invent, and this can be expressed in the future perfect. I write about participation and resemblance in my article on mimesis and methexis: “Mimesis und Methexis. Ähnlichkeit und Teilhabe” (Moser 2020). While we are a part of what we think about and can thus recognize it, we must, at the same time, guess at the similarities, meaning we have to invent them, before we can recognize them. |
5 | Donna Haraway: Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Experimental Futures: Technological Lives, Scientific Arts, Anthropological Voices. Introduction, fn 5. |
6 | Brian Lightbody also defends an anti-relativist reading by contending that Nietzsche aims to determine which perspectives are more insightful or life-affirming (Lightbody 2017). This would not be Haraway’s prerogative, since the question of “life”, as in “life-forms”, is itself unstable in her reading of perspectivism. She wants to speculate about crossing species and thus life-forms. |
7 | Kerger quotes Nietzsche’s paragraph 632 from 1885/1886. Nietzsche wrote before in paragraph 551 (March to June 1888) that “Our ‘understanding of an event’ has consisted in our ‘inventing a subject […]’ (Nietzsche 1968, p. 296). |
8 | (Gerhardt 1992, pp. 260–81). See also the article “Perspektiven und Formen des Lebens. Nietzsche und Wittgenstein” by Nuria Boronat (Boronat 2009, pp. 69–73). |
9 | Wittgenstein introducess the duck–rabbit aspect change in Philosophical Investigations Part II, xi. |
10 | In a footnote, Meyer says that Augenschein should be translated as “appearance”. I translate it as “(ocular) evidence” to make the connection clearer (Meyer 2014, p. 241). |
11 | Meyer is close here to Paul Katsafanas, who in (Katsafanas 2016) underlines that Nietzsche says, “we could think, feel, will and remember, and we could also ‘act’ in every sense of the word, and yet none of this would have to ‘enter our consciousness’” (Meyer 2014, p. 354). |
12 | Here is where sensible constellations come in and, as we will see, this is so before we name it. |
13 | What I show in Kant, Wittgenstein and the Performativity of Thought. Palgrave Macmillan, 2021 is that the Tractatus must already be read in a pragmatic way (Moser 2021). In addition to that performativity there is also an inner projection taking place within each act of thinking that Wittgenstein describes at the beginning of the Tractatus and that involves an act of imagination. |
14 | Here, Rudder Baker discusses Saul Kripke’s Rule-Following problem in which he states that nothing about me can guarantee why I mean “this” by something I say (Kripke 1984). |
15 | Compare this to Beatrice Longuenesse’s use of the term “mindedness” to describe the transcendental categories we deploy. She argues that logic is nothing more but the reflection that we have made on our concepts (Longuenesse 1998). |
16 | While Eagleton must be credited for reading both Nietzsche and Wittgenstein as materialists, he is—unfortunately—not at all interested in neo-materialism and simply discredits it when he writes that “it is a strangely immaterial brand of materialism”. He claims that new materialism regards matter as “a sort of materiality without substance, as fluid and protean as the post-structuralist notion of textuality” and his rant culminates in calling this new materialism a species of post-structuralism in “wolf’s clothing” (Eagleton 2016, p. 11). What Eagleton tries to hold on to by describing the new materialisms in this way is the difference of human beings being alive in a world of meaning with an ability to achieve ends. But one could hold against this that it is Eagleton’s materialism that is not full-blown since he puts matter in its own corner. He writes: “Matter may be alive, but it is not alive in the sense that human beings are. It cannot despair, embezzle, murder, or get married. […] Particles of matter do not move within a world of meaning, as people do […] Matter may be self-activating, but this is not the same as achieving one’s ends. Matter has no ends to achieve”. p. 11. Eagleton is caught in a dualism, making a clear distinction between mind and matter. |
17 | An example of this is Rahel Jaeggi’s book (Jaeggi 2018), as discussed earlier. |
References
- Agamben, Giorgio. 2005. The Coming Community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Alloa, Immanuel. 2017. Post-Truth or: Why Nietzsche Is Not Responsible for Donald Trump. Available online: https://thephilosophicalsalon.com/post-truth-or-why-nietzsche-is-not-responsible-for-donald-trump/ (accessed on 8 January 2025).
- Bennett, Jane. 2010. Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boronat, Nuria Sara Miras. 2009. Perspektiven und Formen des Lebens. Nietzsche und Wittgenstein. In Was Ist Leben? Festtage Für Volker Gerhardt Zum 65. Geburtstag. Edited by Simon Springmann and Asmus Trautsch. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp. 69–73. [Google Scholar]
- Brusotti, Marco, and Sabine Mainberger. 2017. Kunst des Vergleichens. Warburg, Wittgenstein und die Serendipity morphologischer Reihen. In Der Vergleichende Blick: Formanalyse in Natur- und Kulturwissenschaften. Edited by Matthias Bruhn and Gerhard Scholtz. Berlin: Reimer, pp. 209–38. [Google Scholar]
- Cavell, Stanley. 1962. The Availability of Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy. The Philosophical Review 71: 67–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cole, Alyson, and Estelle Ferrarese. 2018. How Capitalism Forms Our Lives. Journal for Cultural Research 22: 105–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Coole, Diana H., and Samantha Frost, eds. 2010. New Materialisms: Ontology, Agency, and Politics. Durham and London: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Didi-Huberman, Georges. 2002. L’image Survivante. Histoire de l’art et temps des fantomes selon Aby Warburg. Paris: Les Editions de Minuit. [Google Scholar]
- Didi-Huberman, Georges. 2017. The Surviving Image. Phantoms of Time and Time of Phantoms. Aby Warburg’s History of Art. Translated by Harvey L. Mendelsohn. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Eagleton, Terry. 2016. Materialism. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ferber, Rafael. 1993. ‘Lebensform ‘ oder ‘Lebensformen‘? Zwei Addenda zur Kontroverse zwischen N. Garver und R. Haller. In Akten des 15. Internationalen Wittgenstein-Symposions. Edited by Klaus Puhl. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, vol. 2, pp. 270–76. [Google Scholar]
- Garver, Newton. 1990. Form of Life in Wittgenstein’s Later Work. Dialectica 44: 175–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gerhardt, Volker. 1992. Die Perspektive des Perspektivismus. In Perspektiven Des Perspektivismus: Gedenkschrift Zum Tode Friedrich Kaulbachs. Edited by Norbert Herold. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, pp. 260–81. [Google Scholar]
- Haller, Rudolf. 1988. Form of Life or Forms of Life. In Questions on Wittgenstein. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, Donna. 2016. Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Experimental Futures: Technological Lives, Scientific Arts, Anthropological Voices. Durham and London: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jaeggi, Rahel. 2018. Critique of Forms of Life. Cambridge, MA and London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Katsafanas, Paul. 2016. The Nietzschean Self: Moral Psychology, Agency, and the Unconscious. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kerger, Henry. 2003. Zum Verhältnis von Norm und Regel bei Nietzsche, Wittgenstein und Ihering. In Theorie des Rechts und der Gesellschaft. Festschrift für Werner Krawietz zum 70. Geburtstag. Edited by Manuel Atienza, Ernesto Garzón Valdés, Michael Schulte, Boris Topornin and Dieter Wyduckel. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp. 189–216. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, Saul A. 1984. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lear, Jonathan. 1982. Leaving the World Alone. The Journal of Philosophy 79: 382–403. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lightbody, Brian. 2017. Nietzsche’s Will to Power Naturalized. Translating the Human into Natuer and Nature into the Human. Lexington: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Longuenesse, Beatrice. 1998. Kant and the Capacity to Judge: Sensibility and Discursivity in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Löffler, Davor. 2013. Leben im Futur II Konjunktiv. Über das Phänomen der Atmosphäre und dessen Bedeutung im Zeitalter der technischen Immersion. In Jahrbuch Immersiver Medien. 2013. Atmosphären: Gestimmte Räume und sinnliche Wahrnehmung. Marburg: Schüren, pp. 23–37. [Google Scholar]
- Majetschak, Stefan. 2006. Philosophie als Arbeit an sich selbst. Wittgenstein, Nietzsche and Paul Ernst. In Wittgensteins “Grosse Maschinenschrift”: Untersuchungen zum philosophischen Ort des Big Typescripts (TS 213) Im Werk Ludwig Wittgensteins. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Meyer, Matthew. 2014. Reading Nietzsche Through the Ancients: An Analysis of Becoming, Perspectivism, and the Principle of Non-Contradiction. Monographien und Texte zur Nietzsche-Forschung, Bd. 66. Boston: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
- Michaud, Philippe-Alain. 2004. Aby Warburg and the Image in Motion. New York: Zone Books. [Google Scholar]
- Miner, Robert. 2017. Gay Science and the Practice of Perspectivism. In Nietzsche and Montaigne. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Moser, Aloisia. 2020. Mimesis und Methexis. Ähnlichkeit und Teilhabe. In Zeich(n)En.Setzen: Bedeutungsgenerierung Im Mäandern Zwischen Bildern Und Begriffen. Linzer Beiträge Zur Kunstwissenschaft und Philosophie, Band 11. Bielefeld: Transcript, pp. 167–84. [Google Scholar]
- Moser, Aloisia. 2021. Kant, Wittgenstein, and the Performativity of Thought. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Moser, Aloisia. 2025. Ábránd: Raten. Wissen aus dem Sinnlich-Medialen. Bielefeld: Transcript. [Google Scholar]
- Nehamas, Alexander. 1983. Immanent and Transcendent Perspectivism in Nietzsche. Nietzsche Studien 12: 473–90. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1783. On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense. Translated by Walter Kaufmann, and Daniel Breazeale. Available online: https://jpcatholic.edu/NCUpdf/Nietzsche.pdf (accessed on 8 May 2025).
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1966. Beyond Good and Evil. Prelude to a Philosophy of a Future. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1968. The Will to Power. Translated by Walter Kaufmann, and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1974. The Gay Science: With a Prelude in Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- Orlie, Melissa A. 2010. Impersonal Matter. In New Materialisms: Ontology, Agency, and Politics. Edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost. Durham and London: Duke University Press, pp. 116–36. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 2006. Theaetetus. Plato: In Twelve Volumes. 7 Theaetetus. Sophist. Edited by Harold North Fowler. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rudder Baker, Lynne. 1984. III. On the Very Idea of a Form of Life. Inquiry 27: 277–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Takagi, Shunichi, and Pascal F. Zambito. 2023. Introduction. In Wittgenstein and Nietzsche. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Teichmueller, Gustav. 2007. Die wirkliche und die scheinbare Welt: Neue Grundlegung der Methaphysik. Reprint. Edition Classic. Saarbrücken: VDM Verlag Müller. [Google Scholar]
- Warburg, Aby. 2020. Bilderatlas Mnemosyne: The Original. Edited by Roberto Ohrt and Axel Heil. Berlin: Hatje-Canty Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Wilcox, John T. 1974. Truth and Value in Nietzsche. A Study of His Metaethics and Epistemology. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1929. Some Remarks on Logical Form. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary 9: 162–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1968. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1992. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by David F. Pears, and Brian F. McGuinness. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Moser, A. A New Way of “Thinking” Consciousness: Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, and Neo-Materialism. Religions 2025, 16, 611. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050611
Moser A. A New Way of “Thinking” Consciousness: Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, and Neo-Materialism. Religions. 2025; 16(5):611. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050611
Chicago/Turabian StyleMoser, Aloisia. 2025. "A New Way of “Thinking” Consciousness: Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, and Neo-Materialism" Religions 16, no. 5: 611. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050611
APA StyleMoser, A. (2025). A New Way of “Thinking” Consciousness: Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, and Neo-Materialism. Religions, 16(5), 611. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050611