The Theodicy Challenge and the Intelligibility of the World
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. If God Is Perfectly Good, What of Evil?
God either wishes to take away evils, and is unable; or He is able, and is unwilling; or He is neither willing nor able, or He is both willing and able. If He is willing and is unable, He is feeble, which is not in accordance with the character of God; if He is able and unwilling, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God; if He is neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble, and therefore not God; if He is both willing and able, which alone is suitable to God, from what source then are evils? or why does He not remove them?(Quoted in Hick 1966, p. 5)
2.1. Three Theodicy Models
2.2. Theodicy: Two Perspectives
(…) I renounce the higher harmony altogether. It’s not worth the tears of that one tortured child (…) do not want more suffering. And if the sufferings of children go to swell the sum of sufferings which was necessary to pay for truth, then I protest that the truth is not worth such a price. (…) Too high a price is asked for harmony!(Dostoevsky 2009, p. 301; our translation)
Natural selection is the differential reproduction of alternative genetic variations, determined by the fact that some variations are beneficial because they increase the probability that the organisms having them will live longer or be more fertile than organisms having alternative variations.
There is certainly no intrinsic connection between the two. After all, a world could be utterly nomically regular and as complex as you please without having any sentient creatures at all. Such a world would be regular, and would lack natural evil altogether. As a result, there will be no way to argue that the intrinsic goodness of nomic regularity, taken on its own, is sufficient to explain animal suffering.
3. Articulating the Evil and Evolution
3.1. Classical and Modern Attitude of Mind: Why This Distinction Matters
Although what makes sense is historically and conceptually bounded, and the scientific theories produced by humans’ epistemic capacity change; nevertheless, the intelligible texture of reality persists:in the historical development of science, the awkward and unresolved tension between instrumentality and natural philosophy has yielded views of the universe that are dependent on particular human conceptions of what makes sense (2008, p. 14).
Over the centuries, human reason has grasped things from nature and given them a scientific form, taking contextual elements and shaping insights. Scientific rationality has evolved; at the same time, something intelligible has remained, and the awareness of our complex and fragile epistemic situation has grown.
3.2. Intelligibility and Evolution
3.3. Evil, Evolution, and Intelligibility Confronted
- Agnostic position: we do not know whether the world is intelligible;
- Surrender position: the search for intelligibility is not worth pursuing;
- The world is intelligible:
- Intrinsic (ontic) intelligibility: there is intrinsic intelligible structure (organization, order) of the world;
- Extrinsic (epistemic) intelligibility: we construct intelligibility out of our mental operations and impose it upon the world;
- Co-dependence of intrinsic and extrinsic intelligibility: a sort of congruence between our cognitive capacities and the order of the world;
- Deeper intelligibility: the world is intelligible to us but only to a certain degree.
3.4. Towards Deeper Intelligibility
start to look at it in the multidimensional way in which the universe as a whole, and everything within it, are found to have a meaning through an immanent intelligibility that ranges beyond the universe to an ultimate ground in the transcendent and uncreated Rationality of God.
the role of natural agency is fully recognized and, at the same time, is seen as supported by a founding divine action that does not oppose nature but rather provides it with its ultimate foundation. This perspective stresses that God usually acts to respect and protect the natural capacities of His creatures, as He has provided them with great and marvelous potentialities so that they may cooperate with God’s plans in a great variety of ways. These potentialities are never exhausted, so that new results can always be produced or expected. Now this is possible through the use of the knowledge provided by scientific progress.(Artigas 1998, p. 250; our translation)
we cannot rationally break off our relation to the intelligibility of the universe at some arbitrary point of our own choosing; otherwise it would be not existence or reality that we are determined to apprehend. This is why scientific inquiry cannot come to a halt at any point we want, but must go on questioning its questions in order to let reality disclose itself to science indefinitely. The capacity of man for this kind of indefinite, unlimited, unbounded inquiry represents that which from his side is correlated to the intelligibility that reaches out indefinitely beyond him and which cries out for, and manifests itself as capable of, explanation in relation to some transcendent source and ground of rationality.
4. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | By “theology” we mean “a study in which, along with other axioms, at least one sentence is assumed which belongs to a given Creed and which is not sustained by persons other than the believers of a given religion” (Bochenski 1965, p. 14). Theology is therefore an attempt to make intellectually understandable what are considered to be the truths of faith of a particular religion. |
2 | We would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point. |
3 | We would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point and referring us to Darwin’s correspondence. |
References
- Alexander, Denis R. 2018. Is There Purpose in Biology? Oxford: Lion Hudson. [Google Scholar]
- Artigas, Mariano. 1992a. Three levels of interaction between science and philosophy. Idealizator IV: Intelligibility in Science 26: 123–44. [Google Scholar]
- Artigas, Mariano. 1992b. Filosofía de la Ciencia Experimental. La Objetividad y la Verdad en las Ciencias, 3rd ed. Pamplona: EUNSA. [Google Scholar]
- Artigas, Mariano. 1998. La Mente del Universo. Pamplona: EUNSA. [Google Scholar]
- Artigas, Mariano. 2017. Umysł Wszechświata. Edited by Piotr Roszak. Toruń: Wydawnictwo Naukowe UMK. [Google Scholar]
- Ayala, Francisco J. 2007. Darwin’s Gift to Science and Religion. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barbour, Ian G. 1997. Religion and Science: Historical and Contemporary Issues. New York: HarperCollins. [Google Scholar]
- Blumenberg, Hans. 1984. La Leggibilità del Mondo. Il Libro Come Metafora Della Natura. Bologna: Il Mulino. [Google Scholar]
- Bochenski, Joseph M. 1965. The Logic of Religion. New York: New York University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Conti, Lino. 2004. L’infalsificabile Libro Della Natura. Perugia: Porziuncola. [Google Scholar]
- Darwin Correspondence Project. n.d. “Letter no. 2814”. Available online: https://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/letter/?docId=letters/DCP-LETT-2814.xml (accessed on 12 September 2023).
- Davies, Paul. 2004. The Cosmic Blueprint: New Discoveries in Nature’s Creative Ability to Order the Universe. Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dear, Peter. 2008. The Intelligibility of Nature: How Science Makes Sense of the World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dostoevsky, Fyodor. 2009. Bracia Karamazow. Translated by Adam Pomorski. Kraków: Znak. [Google Scholar]
- Einstein, Albert. 1960. Physics and reality. In Ideas and Opinions. Edited by Carl Seelig. New York: Crown Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Heller, Michał. 2008. Sens Życia i sens Wszechświata. Studia z Teologii Współczesnej. Tarnów: Biblos. [Google Scholar]
- Hick, John. 1966. Evil and the God of Love. Basingstoke: Macmillan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hooykaas, Reijer. 2000. Religion and the Rise of Modern Science. Vancouver: Regent College Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Mancini, Héctor L. 2014. Comments on Mariano Artigas’ scientific worldview. Scientia et Fides 2: 59–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marcacci, Flavia, and Michał Oleksowicz. 2023. The world as a gift: Scientific change and intelligibility for a theology of science. Religions 14: 572. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matthen, Mohan, and André Ariew. 2002. Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. Journal of Philosophy 99: 55–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McGrath, Alister E. 2001. A Scientific Theology. Volume 1: Nature. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Millstein, Roberta L. 2006. Natural selection as a population-level causal process. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56: 627–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Murray, Michael J. 2008. Nature Red in Tooth and Claw: Theism and the Problem of Animal Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oleksowicz, Michał. 2014. Dyskusja nad argumentem “God of the gaps”. Scientia et Fides 2: 99–123. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oleksowicz, Michał, and Tomasz Huzarek. 2021. Forgiveness and the naturalistic approach to religion: A contextual view of the problem of evil. Religions 12: 756. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pabjan, Tadeusz. 2018. Świat Najlepszy z Możliwych? O dobroci Boga i Pochodzeniu zła. Kraków: Copernicus Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peacocke, Arthur R. 1971. Science and the Christian Experiment. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pedersen, Olaf. 1990. Historical interaction between science and religion. In Science and Religion. Edited by Jan Fennema and Iain Paul. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 139–60. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, Ted. 2018. Science and religion: Ten models of war, truce, and partnership. Theology and Science 16: 11–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Richerson, Peter J., and Morton H. Christiansen, eds. 2013. Cultural Evolution: Society, Technology, Language, and Religion. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rose, Margaret, and David Adams. 1989. Evidence for pain and suffering in other animals. In Animal Experimentation. Edited by Gill Langley. London: Palgrave. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosenberg, Stanley P., ed. 2018. Finding Ourselves after Darwin: Conversations on the Image of God, Original Sin, and the Problem of Evil. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, Robert J. 2002. Science and theology, dialogue between. In Interdisciplinary Encyclopedia of Religion and Science. Edited by Giuseppe Tanzella-Nitti, Ivan Colagé and Alberto Strumia. Rome: Pontifical University of the Holy Cross. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schneider, John R. 2020. Animal Suffering and the Darwinian Problem of Evil. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Skipper, Robert A., and Roberta L. Millstein. 2005. Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: Natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 327–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Sober, Elliott. 1984. The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sollereder, Bethany N. 2019. God, Evolution, and Animal Suffering: Theodicy without a Fall. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Southgate, Christopher. 2008. The Groaning of Creation: God, Evolution, and the Problem of Evil. Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stróżewski, Władysław. 2008. Byt i sens. In Metafizyka i Teologia. Debata u Podstaw. Edited by Robert J. Woźniak. Kraków: WAM, pp. 13–31. [Google Scholar]
- Szocik, Konrad, and Hans van Eyghen. 2021. Revising Cognitive and Evolutionary Science of Religion. Basel: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Torrance, Thomas F. 2001. Reality and Scientific Theology. Eugene: Wipf and Stock Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Wray, K. Brad. 2018. Resisting Scientific Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Życiński, Józef. 2014. Transcendencja i Naturalizm. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Oleksowicz, M.; Kłosowski, M. The Theodicy Challenge and the Intelligibility of the World. Religions 2023, 14, 1513. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14121513
Oleksowicz M, Kłosowski M. The Theodicy Challenge and the Intelligibility of the World. Religions. 2023; 14(12):1513. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14121513
Chicago/Turabian StyleOleksowicz, Michał, and Michał Kłosowski. 2023. "The Theodicy Challenge and the Intelligibility of the World" Religions 14, no. 12: 1513. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14121513
APA StyleOleksowicz, M., & Kłosowski, M. (2023). The Theodicy Challenge and the Intelligibility of the World. Religions, 14(12), 1513. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14121513