The Dreamer and Their Authenticity in the Zhuangzi
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Dreamer and Their Identity
How, then, do I know that delighting in life is not a delusion? How do I know that in hating death I am not like an orphan who left home in youth and no longer knows the way back? Lady Li was a daughter of the border guard of Ai. When she was first captured and brought to Qin, she wept until tears drenched her collar. But when she got to the palace, sharing the king’s luxurious bed and feasting on the finest meats, she regretted her tears. How do I know that the dead don’t regret the way they used to cling to life? ‘If you dream of drinking wine, in the morning you will weep. If you dream of weeping, in the morning you will go hunting.’ While dreaming you don’t know it’s a dream. You might even interpret a dream in your dream—and then you wake up and realize it was all a dream. Perhaps a great awakening would reveal all of this to be a vast dream. And yet, fools imagine they are already awake—how clearly and certainly they understand it all! This one is a lord, they decide, that one is a shepherd—what prejudice! Confucius and you are both dreaming! And when I say you’re dreaming, I’m dreaming too.
In the field of the dream (…) what characterizes the images is that it shows. (…) Look up some description of a dream, any one (…)—place it in its co-ordinates, and you will see that this it shows is well to the fore. So much is it to the fore, with the characteristics in which it is co-ordinated—namely, the absence of horizon, the enclosure, of that which is contemplated in the waking state, and, also, the character of emergence, of contrast, of stain, of its images, the intensification of their colours. (…) The person does not see where it is leading, he follows.
But the very image that the subject makes present through his behavior and that is constantly reproduced in it, is ignored by him, in both senses of the word: he does not know that things image explains what he repeats in his behavior, whether he considers it to be his own or not; and he refuses to realize (meconait) the importance of this image when he evokes the memory it represents.
This is what might be called its elementary cell [the graph- aut.]. In it is articulated what I have called the “button tie” (…) The diachronic function of this button tie can be found in a sentence, insofar as a sentence closes its signification only with its last term, each term being anticipated in the construction constituted by the other terms and, inversely, sealing their meaning by its retroactive effect. But the synchronic structure is more hidden, and it is this structure that brings us to the beginning.
The phantasy is the support of desire; it is not the object that is the support of desire. The subject sustains himself as desiring in relation to an ever more signifying ensemble. This is apparent enough in the form of scenario it assumes, in which the subject, more or less recognizable, is somewhere, split, divided, generally double, in his relation to the object, which usually does not show its true face either.
You temporarily get involved in something or other and proceed to call it “myself”—but how can we know if what we call “self” has any self to it? You dream you are a bird and find yourself soaring in the heavens, you dream you are a fish and find yourself submerged in the depths. I cannot even know if what I’m saying now is a dream or not. An upsurge of pleasure does not reach the smile it inspires, a burst of laughter does not reach the jest that evoked it. But when you rest securely in your place in the sequence, however things are arranged, and yet separate each passing transformation from the rest, then you enter into the clear oneness of Heaven. (Ziporyn 2009, p. 89)
If the function of the dream is to prolong the sleep, if the dream, after all, may come some near to the reality that causes it, can we not say that it might correspond to this reality without emerging from sleep? (…) The question that arises … is—What is it that wakes the sleeper? Is it not in the dream, another reality?”
3. The True Person and The Problem of Dreams
The Genuine Human Beings of old slept without dreaming and awoke without worries. Their food was plain but their breathing was deep. The Genuine Human Beings breathed from their heels, while the mass of men breathe from their throats. Submissive and defeated, they gulp down their words and just as soon vomit them back up. Their preferences and desires run deep, but the Heavenly Impulse is shallow in them. The Genuine Human Beings of old understood nothing about delighting in being alive or halting death. They emerged without delight, submerged again without resistance. Swooping in they came and swooping out they went, that and no more. They neither forgot where they came from nor asked where they would go. Receiving it, they delighted in it. Forgetting about it, they gave it back. This is what it means not to use the mind to push away the Course, not to use the Human to try to help the Heavenly. Such is what I’d call being a Genuine Human Being.”
If we follow whatever has so far taken shape, fully formed, in our minds making that our teacher, who could ever be without the teacher? The mind comes to be what it is by taking possession of whatever it selects out of the process of alternation -but does that mean it has to truly understand that process? The fool takes something up from it too. But to claim that there are any such things as “right” and “wrong” before they come to be fully formed in someone’s mind in this way—that is like saying you left for Yue today and arrived there yesterday. This is to regard to nonexistent as existent. The existence of the nonexistent is beyond the understanding of even divine sage-king Yu—so what possible sense could it make to someone like me?
Subject = being → no-subject = being → (no-subject = being) = being → [no-subject = being) = being] = being →…
The subject constitutes himself only by subtracting himself from it and by decompleting is essentially, such that he must, one and the same time count himself here and function only as a lack here.
The subject, at each stage, becomes what he was (to be) before that, and he will have been is only announced in the future perfect tense.
In the Phantasy, the subject is frequently unperceived, but he is always there, whether in the dream or in any of the more or less developed forms of day-dreaming. The subject situated himself as determined by the phantasy.
… getting it is a matter of the time, coming and losing it is just something else to follow along with. Content in the time and finding one’s place in the process of following along, joy and sorrow are unable to seep in. This is what the ancients called the Dangle and Release. We cannot release ourselves-being beings, we are always tried up by something. But it has long been the case that mere beings cannot overpower Heaven.
4. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Allinson, Robert E. 2012. Snakes and Dragons, Rat’s Liver and Fly’s Leg: The Butterfly Dream Revisited. Dao 11: 530–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Combs, Steven C. 2005. The Dao of Rhetoric. New York: State University Press. [Google Scholar]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul J. 2016. Guo Xiang on Self-So Knowledge. Asian Philosophy 26: 119–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul J. 2017. Imagination in the Zhuangzi: The Madman of Chu’s Alternative to Confucian Cultivation. Asian Philosophy 27: 30–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul J., Hans Rudolf Kantor, and Hans Georg Moeller. 2018. Incongruent Names: A Theme in the History of Chinese Philosophy. Dao Journal of Comparative Philosophy 17: 1–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eyers, Tom. 2012. Lacan and the Concept of the Real. London: Palgrave Mamillan. [Google Scholar]
- Flanders, Sara. 1993. The Dream Discourse Today. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Freud, Sigmund. 2010. Interpretations of the Dreams. Translated by James Strachery. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Freud, Sigmund. 2015. A General Introduction to Psychoanalysis. London: Dodo Collections. [Google Scholar]
- Gaskins, Robert W. 1997. The Transformation of Things. A Reanalysis of Chuang Tzu’s Butterfly Dream. Journal of Chinese Philosophy 24: 107–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lacan, Jacques. 1966. Au-de la du Principe de Realite, Ecrits. Paris: Edition du Seuil. [Google Scholar]
- Lacan, Jacques. 1973. Les Quatre Concepts Fondamentaux De La Psychoanalyse. Paris: Editions du Seuil. [Google Scholar]
- Lacan, Jacques. 1979. The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis. New York: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Lacan, Jacques. 2005. Ecrits. A selsction. Translated by Alan Sheridan. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Lacan, Jacques. 2007. Ecrits. Translated by Bruce Fink. New York: Norton & Company. [Google Scholar]
- Moeller, Hans Georg, and Paul J. D’Ambrosio. 2017. Genuine Pretending: On The Philosophy of the Zhuangzi. New York: Columbia Univeristy Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moeller, Hans Georg. 1999. Zhuangzi’s Dream of the Butterfly: A Daoist Interpretation. Philosophy East and West 49: 439–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moeller, Hans Georg. 2017. On second-order observation and genuine pretending: Coming to terms with society. Thesis Eleven 143: 28–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nancy, Jean Luc. 2009a. Identity and Trembling, in The Birth to Presence. Translated by Brian Holmes. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nancy, Jean Luc. 2009b. The Fall of Sleep. Translated by Charlotte Mandell. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pagel, James F. 2008. The Limits of Dream. Oxford: Academic Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rock, Andrea. 2004. The Mind at Night. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Van Haute, Philippe. 2002. Against Adaptation. Lacan’s Subversion of the Subject. Translated by Paul Crowe, and Miranda Vankert. New York: Other Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook. 2009. Zhuangzi. The Essential Writing. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. [Google Scholar]
1 | In the Western philosophical tradition, many Authors are focused on the topic of dreaming as it relates to issue in the relation mind and body. For example, Descartes asked whether you can be sure that you are not at this moment only dreaming that you are awake. Kant claimed that the madman is a waking dreamer. Compare this to the idea that: “Sleep, perhaps, has never been philosophical” (Nancy 2009a, p. 13). “There is no phenomenology of sleep, for it shows of itself only its disappearance, its burrowing and its concealment. But by concealing itself, it brings, on the other hand, the possibility, further and stronger than any phenomenality, of a disposition of intentions and aims as well as the fulfillment of sense”. (Nancy 2009b, p. 13). |
2 | In the literature concerning the dreams it is possible to find scientific analyses based on the function of the brain and psychoanalytic interpretations. Very often, both explanations function in opposition. See for example: (Rock 2004; J. F. Pagel 2008; S. Flanders 1993). |
3 | In the article I will not discuss perhaps the most paradigmatic passage about the dreams in the Zhuangzi, namely the butterfly allegory. Lacan explained the butterfly parable in one of his Seminars (see Lacan 1979, p. 76). It would probably require an entire article to adequately deal with this issue. For expert philosophical treatments of the butterfly dream, see (Gaskins 1997; Moeller 1999; Allinson 2012). |
4 | In the context of the transformation an influential explanation of the butterfly dream is given by Hans-Georg Moeller, whose analysis is decidedly different from dominant interpretation of skepticism or relativism. In Moeller’s interpretation Zhuang Zhou does not remember his dream, and as a consequence it is not possible to decide which instance is the reality and which one is a dream (see: Moeller 1999, pp. 439–50). As Moeller explains: “The segments are separated from each other by a sharp distinction -and this is precisely the reason they can be seamlessly connected with each other. The sharply distinguished segments constitute a continuous and perfectly connected whole just because they have nothing in common with each other. What is continuous is the process from segment to segment: each segment is complete in itself precisely because no part of it is transferred to the following segment” (Moeller 1999, p. 443). |
5 | Lacan distinguishes three stages or orders on which the subject functions: the Real, the Symbolic, and the Imaginary. He presented relations between these stages in the form of borromean rings. Each ring represents one stage. For secondary sources about the three orders, see, for example, (Eyers 2012; P. Van Haute 2002). |
6 | P. J. D’Ambrosio, H. R. Kantor and H. G. Moeller argue that incongruity between names and actualities or names and things is a constant theme in the history of Chinese thought. (See: P. J. D’Ambrosio et al. 2018). |
7 | Lacan saw a triadic relation between need, demand, and desire. Needs concern the biological level. A demand is its expression in the form of a request. A desire is a surplus irreducible to either. As he wrote “The desire begins to take shape in the margin in which demand becomes separated from need.” (Lacan 2005, p. 237). |
8 | It’s very interesting that these two creatures occur very often in the Zhuangzi in the context of a dream. |
9 | A new and innovative philosophical interpretation of the zhenren is offered by H. G. Moeller and P. D’Ambrosio (see: Moeller and D’Ambrosio 2017). Their True Person is strongly correlated with the creation of new terminology concerning identity. By this intervention, the authors present a fresh understanding of the term True Person. In this context, see also, H. G. Moeller (2017); P. J. D’Ambrosio (2017); P. J. D’Ambrosio (2016). For other, “classical” interpretations of the zhenren, see, for example, S. C. Combs 2005, pp. 37–43. |
10 | Moeller writes: “What is Daoistic is not the blurring of the borderlines between the segments, between (the two) Zhuang Zhou (s) and the butterfly, between being awake and dreaming, between life and death, nor the doubts about one’s “real I”, but rather the belief that the authenticity of each segment of a whole is guaranteed by the very fact that the segments are not connected to each other by any continuous bridge between them. It is un-Daoistic to believe that life and death are about the same and not clearly divided from each other: rather, life and death are as different, from the Daoist point of view, as they can possibly be” (Moeller 1999, p. 443). |
© 2019 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Bonar, B.A. The Dreamer and Their Authenticity in the Zhuangzi. Religions 2019, 10, 75. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020075
Bonar BA. The Dreamer and Their Authenticity in the Zhuangzi. Religions. 2019; 10(2):75. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020075
Chicago/Turabian StyleBonar, Barbara Aniela. 2019. "The Dreamer and Their Authenticity in the Zhuangzi" Religions 10, no. 2: 75. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020075
APA StyleBonar, B. A. (2019). The Dreamer and Their Authenticity in the Zhuangzi. Religions, 10(2), 75. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020075