Previous Article in Journal
The Role of RPA and Data Analysis in the Transformation of the Insurance and Banking Industries
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Review

Federalism: A Comprehensive Review of Its Evolution, Typologies, and Contemporary Issues

Department of Political Science and International Relations, Izmir University of Economics, 35330 Izmir, Turkey
Encyclopedia 2025, 5(4), 156; https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5040156
Submission received: 22 July 2025 / Revised: 26 September 2025 / Accepted: 29 September 2025 / Published: 30 September 2025
(This article belongs to the Section Social Sciences)

Abstract

This study is intended to conduct a comprehensive review of federalism. This study starts from the institutional aspect and analyzes how federalism, as a compound structure, divides power between the central and local governments. Then, this study mentions that federalism also has its normative connotations, which are traceable to the theological concept of a covenant. We also elaborate on how the success of the United States’ federalism strengthened its institutional aspect while overshadowing the older covenant tradition. Next, this study presents a typological framework of federalism, introducing concepts such as coming-together federalism and holding-together federalism; dual federalism and cooperative federalism; decentralization and non-centralization; and asymmetrical federalism, non-territorial autonomy, and consociationalism, presidential and parliamentary federalism, as well as democratic federalism and authoritarian federalism/facade federalism. Next, this study compares monist federalism with multinational federalism. Then, this study examines the specific applications of federalism in fiscal, environmental, health-care, and social-welfare policies. By reviewing the history, theoretical origins, institutional development, and contemporary manifestations of federalism, this study provides a roadmap for scholars in the field of federal studies. Finally, this study also puts forward several testable hypotheses, aiming to provide operational research agendas for future studies.

1. Introduction

As a “compound” form of government [1,2,3,4], federalism is widely used in countries that wish to maintain local autonomy within a unified national framework, as a tool for regional integration, and sometimes as a mechanism for conflict management [5,6]. In general, federalism combines a central government with regional sub-governments—provinces, states, cantons, territories, etc.—within a single political system and divides power between the two levels [2,7,8]. This arrangement is not merely a power distribution but provides constitutional legitimacy to each level of government [9]. Within the two government levels, federalism is always caught in the internal tensions between federal centralization and local autonomy [10,11].
On the other hand, the success of federalism largely depends on its ability to manage these internal tensions as political environments change [12,13]. Based on differentiated contexts, federalism has also developed derivative concepts—whether for resisting tyranny on the minority, namely defensive federalism [14]; for managing diversity [5,15,16]; or for safeguarding national welfare [17,18]. This study also focuses on the performance of federalism in specific policy areas, in fiscal, environmental, and social aspects.
In this review, Section 2 mainly elaborates on two ways of understanding federalism: as a political institution and as a political norm. It also shows how the later success of the American model reinforced its institutional aspect while overshadowing the normative dimension. Section 3 provides a typology of federal arrangements: coming-together federalism and holding-together federalism; dual federalism and cooperative federalism; decentralization and non-centralization; asymmetrical federalism; non-territorial autonomy and consociationalism; presidential federalism and parliamentary federalism; democratic federalism and authoritarian federalism/facade federalism; and monist federalism and multinational federalism. Section 4 focuses on the manifestations of federalism in finance, the environment, health, and social welfare. Section 5 concludes.
In this paper, besides the theoretical discussion, several comparative observations of federalism are listed (with a focus on the United States, Canada, Belgium, Spain, etc.). Given the limitations of space and the availability of materials, federal or quasi-federal practices in Africa, Latin America, and Asia have not been comprehensively covered in this paper. This paper acknowledges the limitations of the study and suggests greater geographical diversity in the conclusion.
This paper also attempts to integrate the following threads into a multidimensional perspective. First is the institutional dimension, which emphasizes the constitutional division of power and functions. Second is the normative/covenant dimension, which highlights the legitimacy of federalism as a contract and a community. Third is the dimension of normative pluralism and interactive practice, where we briefly mention how legal pluralism/constitutional pluralism has inspired cross-level procedural dialogue. Moreover, this paper attempts to raise several research questions that have not been fully addressed and to point out directions for follow-up research: How do the multiple ports of entry of cross-level rules change the political accessibility of minority groups? What are the long-term effects of asymmetrical arrangements and non-territorial autonomy in reducing the risk of violent separatism? In the context of increasing globalization and transnational rules, how does federalism interlock with international/regional constitutional pluralism and affect policy outcomes? After a comprehensive review of the entire paper, I will summarize several testable propositions in the conclusion for future researchers to refer to.
Although this paper attempts to cover the main dimensions of federalism research, it must be acknowledged that any topic is worth a separate study. What we provide is a panorama, a compass, for researchers of federalism. From this paper, we can understand the basic research questions in this field and continue to promote in-depth communication in this area. Before proceeding with the main text, readers may refer to Table 1 below for a quick reference to the terms frequently used in the text.

2. Understanding Federalism: Institutions or Norms

2.1. Federalism as a Mode of Political Institutions

Many scholars treat federalism first and foremost as a way of organizing political institution: the joining of otherwise independent entities into a single system while each still keeps its basic political integrity [2]. Its basic requirement is the constitutional division of power between the federation and its constituent units, allowing each level to enjoy autonomy in specific areas [19]. In this perspective, the most influential brief definition is to define federalism as the combination of self-rule and shared rule [2,20,21]. This expression highly condenses the institutional characteristics of federalism. On the other hand, it can lead researchers to mistakenly regard some institutional features (such as bicameralism, political decentralization mechanisms) as the essence of federalism [21].
A more cautious understanding of this definition is as follows: First, two or more levels of government are recognized at the constitutional level. Second, each level of government can be independently accountable to the people and possess substantial power [21,22]. Policies are not simply issued by federal government. Each level within the federal system have the power to participate in the formulation of policies at its own level [2].
The Achaean League in ancient Greece can be regarded as an early (con)federation. Its city-states cooperated in security and foreign affairs while maintaining autonomy [23,24], demonstrating a clear division of power between the central (league) and the constituent polities (city-states). The early Latin League and later the foedera system incorporated various city-states into the Roman framework through treaties (foedus), granting them autonomy and obligations for common defense [25]. This is also the source of Althusius’ later tracing of federalism to foedus. In the medieval period, in the Hanseatic League and the Holy Roman Empire, their member cities or principalities retained considerable autonomy while addressing trade and security conflicts through common institutions [26]. Similarly, in the early modern times, an Indigenous alliance in North America—the Haudenosaunee (Iroquois) Confederacy, developed a cross-tribal quasi-federal structure, establishing collective defense and diplomatic mechanisms while preserving tribal autonomy [27]. Although these ancient and early-modern cases do not fully meet the standards of modern federations, they all reflect a similar logic of institutional arrangement. That is, by seeking a balance between self-rule and shared rule to achieve cooperation.
However, the “federal” organizations just listed are closer to what we would today call a confederation, rather than a federation [28]. Their overriding aim was to protect the autonomy of the constituent unites rather than to build a strong central authority. Actually, for a very long time, “federal” and “confederal” were used interchangeably. It was not until the founding years of the United States, which we will later discuss, that the difference between the two were reinterpreted clear.
Confederation usually refers to a loose alliance among sovereign states: member states retain sovereignty, have a check on the power of the center. The membership is often revocable. Moreover, the authority of the central government usually derives from the continuing consent of the member states. By contrast, a federation is a constitutionalized double constitutionalism, the center and the constituent units coexist under the constitution. Kenneth Clinton Wheare explicitly pointed out that the core principle of federalism is the coexistence of two levels of government, each independent and coordinate [29]. The distribution of powers is guaranteed constitutionally, and there are institutionalized dispute resolution mechanisms (such as a constitutional court). In short, the extent of central authority is not the only criterion for determining a federation. The key is whether there is a constitutionalized distribution of powers and institutionalized arbitration. If a central power is entirely dependent on the constituent units’ consent at any time, then the system is closer to a confederation. If the central power is written in the constitution and protected (by the judiciary), then it is closer to a federation.
But if a more relaxed definition of federalism is adopted, then a confederation can also be regarded as a form of federalism. William Riker [30] defined federalism as an arrangement in which two levels of government exercise power over the same citizens in the same political community at the same time. Daniel J. Elazar [2,31] emphasized the diverse expressions of a “federal covenant,” arguing that from formal federations to confederations, and even certain special autonomy systems, they can all be included in the broad category of federalism. Under this relaxed perspective, there exist federal political systems with varying degrees of power distribution all over the world: From formal federations (such as the United States, Germany) to confederations (for example, the Commonwealth of Independent States), associated states (the Compact of Free Association between the Marshall Islands and the United States), federacies (Finland-Aland), condominiums (Andorra under the joint administration of France and Spain), unions, leagues, and even autonomy arrangements. Although these systems differ significantly, they all reflect institutional arrangements based on the covenantal combination of self-rule and shared rule. Within this institutional structure, the key element is dual recognition. That is, both the central and local governments recognize each other’s legitimacy and boundaries of power at the institutional level [32]. This in fact requires that federalism as an institutional structure be supported by at least a kind of normative interpretation. That is the content of our next two sub-sections.

2.2. Legal and Constitutional Pluralism: Between Institutions and Norms

In addition to historical practices of federalism, recent studies of legal pluralism and constitutional pluralism have also provided a complementary perspective for understanding federalism. Legal pluralism, which acknowledges the coexistence of multiple normative orders within the same society area. They influence each other through procedural and discursive channels in practice. Recognizing this multi-sourced normative orders provides a basis for understanding federal multi-level governance. Specifically, legal pluralism shifts the focus from constitutional power division to the overlap and dialogue between institutions. Erin Ryan [33] regards federalism as a manifestation of legal pluralism, emphasizing that in a multi-level system, different legal domains (federal, state, local) influence policy through complementary and competitive institutional channels. Paul Schiff Berman [34,35] uses a similar theoretical framework to illustrate how federalism and transnational rules interact through multiple legal domains. In this regard, Judith Resnik’s [36] discussion of federalism’s “multiple ports of entry” indicates that voices unheard in one forum might be heard in a different level. Thus, multiple ports of entry is itself a normative democratic discourse, rather than merely an institutional arrangement. Heather Gerken [37] further reminds us that in many practical aspects (especially at the local administration), the form of power is manifested as “voice” rather than full “sovereignty.” This also partially challenges the procedural understanding of federalism as merely an institutional arrangement and power division.
At the same time, constitutional pluralism, which was systematized by some scholars in the context of EU studies [38] provides another path: it does not advocate for the search for a final constitutional authority, but rather focuses on the procedural competition and coordination of different constitutional orders in practice. Some EU constitutional pluralism literature indicates that constitutional pluralism does not necessarily lead to conflict. On the contrary, procedural dialogue between institutions can become a mechanism for maintaining legitimacy and resolving conflicts [39,40]. Transplanting this idea into the study of federalism is conducive to understanding the relationship between “federal” and “confederal,” as well as between states and transnational governance, as a matter of dialogue, translation, and procedural legitimacy, rather than just a question of power division.
These modern discussions also produce a constructive academic dialogue with early ideas of multi-layered federalism such as that of Althusius to be mentioned: Gunther Teubner’s [41] societal constitutionalism emphasizes that social institutions outside the state also engage in quasi-constitutional norm-building. Nico Krisch [42], Berman [34,35] and others’ discussions on global legal pluralism expand the scope of observation to transnational spaces, showing that the same action is increasingly subject to the joint regulation of multiple national, sub-national and non-national norms. This is very similar to Althusius’ explanation of federalism that we will mention next.
Mentioning legal pluralism/constitutional pluralism in federalism discourse, in fact, can be seen as a kind of integration at the intersection of federalism in terms of institution and normativity, a transition from institutional arrangement to normative understanding. It puts the questions of how power is divided and who has sovereignty into the procedural dialogue between institutions about who can speak and how they are heard, by emphasizing the multi-sourced nature of norms. This in fact implies the normativity behind federalism as an institution and procedure. It makes us understand that federalism is not only a map of power distribution, but also a field that constantly generates political legitimacy. The formation of this field requires a covenant, which was seen by early federal scholars as one aspect of the normative requirements of federalism.

2.3. Federalism as a Norm and the Covenantal Tradition

As mentioned, in addition to being an institutional framework, federalism also carries a profound normative dimension. It is not only about the distribution of power but also reflects a concept of order rooted in covenant. In this dimension, the first to provide a systematic exposition were the Calvinist theologians of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, Johannes Althusius [43,44,45]. Althusius derived the etymological origins of federation from the Latin term “foedus,” denoting a “covenant” or “pact” [46] (p. 35) [47]. He elaborated a federal theory centered on reciprocal obligations among symbiotic associations (consociatio symbiotica).
In Althusius’s view, society is a chain of associations [48,49]: families form villages, villages form towns, towns form provinces, provinces form states, and states ultimately merge into an empire [46,47,50]. The nature of politics is the art of associating, the science of living together. The federation is the external manifestation of the nature of politics. As Althusius states:
“Politics is the art of associating (consociandi) men for the purpose of establishing, cultivating, and conserving social life among them. Whence it is called ’symbiotics.’ The subject matter of politics is therefore association (consociatio), in which the symbiotes pledge themselves each to the other, by explicit or tacit agreement, to mutual communication of whatever is useful and necessary for the harmonious exercise of social life” [51].
(p. 12)
Althusius regarded the Holy Roman Empire as a decentralized federation in which power was distributed to autonomous, smaller polities [52,53]. He insisted that sovereignty lies with the autonomous entity, not the center. Therefore, in the face of the rise of centralization, federalism is a legitimate form to resist tyranny [54]. This stance contrasts sharply with the absolute sovereignty advocated by Jean Bodin around the same time [55,56].
In this perspective, Althusius’s federal thought is a normative challenge to the modern state sovereignty model. In Althusius’s view, authority does not come from the top, but it is granted by covenantal communities at all levels. The highest body is merely an “agent” acting on behalf of multiple associations. Its legitimacy is derived from the consensus and covenant among the constituent members [54,57].
This tradition has two profound impacts on contemporary federalism. First, it laid the intellectual foundation for the principle of subsidiarity. This principle has become one of the core norms of the European Union’s multilevel governance. It advocates that decisions should be made at the level closest to the citizens, with higher authorities intervening only when lower levels are unable to adequately address the issue [58,59]. This principle was later incorporated into Article 5 of the Treaty of Lisbon by the European Union, and it is seen as a key tool for reconciling members’ autonomy [60].
Second, Althusius’ thought also inspired the concept of federal liberty. Hüglin interprets federalism as “primarily a horizontal process of communication,” from the grassroots level, from “a plurality of groups or communities which all possess their own rights and obligations” [61] (p. 279). Liberty within federalism thus no longer merely means being free from central government’s intervention, but means that citizens can participate in politics at different levels and in different associations [62]. Federalism is not only an institutional design to prevent centralization, but also a moral normativity that promotes civic virtue in public participation. This largely resonates the republican idea of liberty [63,64]. In this sense, some scholars argue that Althusius became a precursor to later theories of popular sovereignty and constitutionalism [65,66,67], while some scholars dispute this [68,69,70].
If the covenant tradition provides a normative foundation for federalism, then the early modern “social contract” tradition offers another, considering its influence in the United State. It sometimes complements and sometimes is tension with the covenantal theory. The social contract thinkers, most prominently Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, articulated contractual theory of political legitimacy grounded in agreement among individuals [71,72,73]. Their core concern was the source of legitimate authority, and how individuals confer power to political institutions. However, the theories of these theorists are to a certain extent distinguished from the Althusius’ pattern. Hobbes argues that a single, absolute sovereign is the guarantee of peace [71]. Thus, his pattern is essentially centralized and not conducive to dispersed sovereignty [74]. In contrast, Locke’s social contract theory establishes political authority on the basis of individual consent to form a government to protect life, liberty, and property [72]. His framework can be understood as compatible with institutional arrangements for the separation of powers and checks and balances [75]. Rousseau’s concept of the general will emphasizes collective unity and popular sovereignty [73]. It may favor the concentrated expression of the public will, thus it is theoretically in conflict with pluralistic, conceptions of authority [76].
How do these currents interact in the formation of modern federal orders, especially in the American case to be mentioned? The American Founders drew unevenly on the social-contract tradition, while also being heir to covenantal traditions circulating in colonial New England (Puritan covenant theology and compacts such as Winthrop’s “city upon a hill” and various colonial compacts). On the one hand, The theories of Hobbes and Rousseau at least partially inspired the idea of building a centralized federation to resolve interstate conflicts and avoid factional tyranny. And Lockean doctrines of consent and natural rights were particularly influential in protecting the individual rights in the rhetoric of the federalists [77,78]. On the other hand, the language of compacts and mutual commitments as a form of political covenant persisted, giving rise to compact theories of union that emphasized state consent and reserved powers [79,80]. Thus, American federalism is best read as a hybrid: commitments to individual rights, combined with concerns about state reserved powers from covenantal idioms that justified plural sovereignties and inter-state compacts.
Elazar’s modern reinterpretation explicitly confirmed and promoted Althusius’s idea of the foedus etymological origin of federalism, defining its covenantal meaning as the normative basis of federalism [81,82,83]. He also borrowed the Hebrew concept of brit (covenant) and continued to interpret federalism as a mutual commitment and a covenantal relationship based on trust [83,84]. For Elazar, the development from covenant to federation has gone through three stages. (i) The covenant tradition was initially traced back to the ancient covenant between the Israelites and God. (ii) Later, this covenant gradually evolved into a contract between people, witnessed by God. The witnessing God is not an external guarantor but a co-signer—almost a tripartite covenant. (iii) In early modern times, this covenant has manifested as a contract between people and the political community, which is the basis for Althusius’s discussion of his federal and consociational theory [2]. From this perspective, federations survive not merely because of constitutional design, but also because of covenantal ethos: respect for the autonomy of constituent units with willingness to shoulder common obligations [84,85,86]. But a full account must also acknowledge that the social contract tradition, especially Locke’s restraint on centralized power and Rousseau’s emphasis on unity. Their theories centered on individual consent, rights, and the notion of the people as ultimate source of authority, provide resources for debates over popular sovereignty, constitutional supremacy, and the allowable degree of decentralization [79,80]. It can both support and contest federal arrangements. Recognizing the plurality of these intellectual antecedents helps explain why federalism has been variously mobilized in the tension between local autonomy and national unity.

2.4. The American Founding: Reforging Federalism Towards Institutions

If there is a country that has established the template for modern federalism, it is undoubtedly the United States. At the end of the 18th century, the main task facing the American Founders was to establish a more solid governance arrangement among the thirteen former British colonies to address issues of finance, national defense, and interstate coordination [87]. The political space at the time was still confined to the Atlantic coastal region. Most of inland North America was the habitation of the indigenous peoples, and there were still contests from colonial powers such as Britain, France and Spain. It was under these internal and external difficulties that the Founders began to explore the form of uniting. Their first attempt was the Articles of Confederation—a document that was more like a loose agreement of friendship [77]. Under the Articles, the states retained almost all the power: Congress could not levy taxes, could not repay the war debt, and could not prevent rural uprisings like Shays’ Rebellion. By the mid-1780s, the political system was on the brink of bankruptcy [88].
In 1787, representatives from the states gathered in Philadelphia, ostensibly to amend the Articles of Confederation [89]. However, propelled by the Federalists—whose arguments are preserved in the Federalist Papers [77]—the delegates abandoned the old charter and drafted a new Constitution that granted the central government more power than expected [30,90,91,92]. The new federal government could levy taxes, coin money, and exercise direct authority over citizens. Through the Supremacy Clause, federal laws established their authority over state regulations.
This change sparked intense controversy. On one hand, the “Anti-Federalists”, named by the Federalist for their opponents, loudly protested. They warned that a distant super government would swallow the states [93]. Under the Articles of Confederation, membership was voluntary and the central authority was weak; now the federal government claimed ultimate authority. On the other hand, the states still retained extensive autonomy—enacting most criminal and civil laws, holding elections, and even setting voting rules [90,94]. James Madison once summarized that the federal government’s powers were few and defined, while the states’ powers were many and undefined [77]. The Tenth Amendment, ratified in 1791, emphasized this point: any power not granted to the central government by the Constitution was reserved to the states—or the people themselves [95].
Ultimately, the federal arrangement was seen as a “middle way,” sandwiched between unitary systems—where everything is centralized in the center—and confederal systems—where everything is left to the constituent parts [96,97]. Although the term “federalism” never appears in the Constitution, it became an unwritten rule for establishing the new nation. The federal government had to have enough power to prevent states from abusing their authority, but it could not be so strong that it became a despotic tyrant itself.
The Founders—especially Madison—were not particularly worried that the president of the federal center would become a tyrant. They were more concerned about majorities at the local level infringing on the minorities. Therefore, they believed that only by establishing a large republic and a system of divided powers could any one faction be prevented from controlling the entire system [98,99,100,101,102]. Judged by its results, the design worked. American federalism remains one of the most outstanding practices of federalism as an institutional arrangement [4,103].
However, this successful model, to some extent, obscured people’s understanding of the older vision of federalism. The American system, which emphasizes enumerated powers, dual sovereignty, and separation of powers, overshadowed the covenantal tradition of federalism: a consociational federation of associations, shared rather than divided powers, as described by Althusius. Some critics pointed out that American federalists rarely focused on town halls, parishes, or any places where citizens could govern face-to-face [104,105,106]. It leads ultimately to a nation that speaks with one voice [97]. In fact, the Founders quietly replaced the old meaning of federalism with a new one—redefining the term “federal”: federalism was no longer a cooperative community among diverse associations/communities, but a division of power between the central and state governments.
Building a centralized political organism was the Founders’ goal [107], and those who advocated for deeper decentralization of sovereignty to local communities—in a sense, the true Althusian federalists—were stigmatized as “Anti-Federalists” and thus excluded from the mainstream narrative [99,108,109]. This manipulation of terminology, even today, still complicates the basic definition, which discussions of federalism have to face.

3. Types, Variants, and Diversity of Federalism

In this section, we will demonstrate the diverse classifications of federalism from various dimensions. This classification always has hybrids and exceptions; thus, this section does not attempt to exhaust all possibilities but merely focuses on the types most widely discussed in academia.

3.1. Coming-Together Federalism and Holding-Together Federalism

Federalism can be divided into two types based on its establishment path: coming-together federalism and holding-together federalism.
Coming-together federalism is formed by multiple independent political entities voluntarily uniting for strategic reasons. The constituent units usually have strong autonomy and symmetry. For example, the establishment of the United States was a product of 13 colonies uniting to counter external threats [30,110,111]. Canada and Switzerland also exhibit similar characteristics [112,113,114]. Although the European Union is not a federal state, its structure still has the characteristics of a coming-together federation [113,115].
Holding-together federalism is a federal arrangement implemented top-down by a unified nation facing challenges of diversity in language, ethnicity, culture, etc. In this model, the initial central government usually has greater power [110,111], and federalization is more seen as a political compromise [116]. India can be regarded as a holding-together federation. Its federal structure tried to regulate internal religious and linguistic diversity [117]. Spain’s 1978 Constitution, while promoting democratization, granted high autonomy to autonomous regions to ease separatism in Catalonia and the Basque Country [118,119]. Belgium is also a typical example of moving towards holding-together federalism to maintain national unity. It evolves from a unitary system to a complex federalism of multilingual communities [120,121].
It should be noted that although we previously mentioned that coming-together federations have greater autonomy of constituent units and holding-together federations tend to retain a stronger central government, in practice, this description is only based on the initial conditions. Later developments can easily deviate from early expectations. For example, although the United States and Switzerland were initially coming-together federal systems, the power of the U.S. federal government has far exceeded the framework originally designed [122,123]. However, Switzerland still maintains a relatively loose weak federal system. Similarly, Spain and Belgium—both holding-together federal systems—have actually pushed the entire country towards extensive decentralization under the continuous national demand for autonomy [119,120,124,125,126].

3.2. Dual Federalism and Cooperative Federalism

Based on how powers are divided and shared, federalism can be distinguished as dual federalism and cooperative federalism [12,123,127,128,129].
Dual federalism is characterized by a clear division of powers between levels of government. Each level operates independently within its own sphere, with relatively little intervention and cooperation between them. This federal structure has been vividly described as “layer-cake federalism” [130,131] since its powers are divided into distinct layers. The United States adopted this model in its early years. The Tenth Amendment emphasized that powers not delegated to the federal government by the Constitution should be reserved to the states [122].
However, as the complexity of governance increased, the limitations of dual federalism gradually became apparent, especially in dealing with cross-regional challenges such as economic crises, climate change, or environmental issues [132]. In contrast, a more collaborative federal framework developed, namely cooperative federalism. Under this model, the federal and state governments collaborate within overlapping responsibility, sharing resources. This model is commonly referred to as “marble-cake federalism” because the powers of the federal and state governments are intermingled and indistinguishable [110,131,132,133]. It looks much like the mixed, interwoven marble patterns on a marble cake.
In the United States, the rise of cooperative federalism can be traced back to the New Deal era of Roosevelt, when the administration provided a lot of financial support to local governments, and cooperated in many construction projects [123,128,133,134]. The European Union is also considered to be evolving towards cooperative federalism in environmental governance and financial issues [135]. The shift from dual federalism to cooperative federalism reflects the adaptability of federalism. The boundaries between federal and local entities are no longer rigid, but are increasingly trending towards functional integration [116].

3.3. Decentralization and Non-Centralization

Decentralization and non-centralization constitute another dimension of federal polities, revealing different starting points and evolutionary paths of power [2,136,137,138,139,140,141,142]. Although these two terms are likely to be confused in everyday language, they have distinct meanings in political analysis.
In a decentralized federal system, there is a presumption of an existing central authority that later devolves power to subordinate units [137]. This structure implies a logic that the center may—at least formally—retain ultimate sovereignty [137]. However, in practice, re-centralization may be difficult to achieve. In some countries, decentralization is seen as a response to ethnic plurality and democratization. Take Spain as an example: the 1978 Constitution established that Spain would adopt a quasi-federal model [143,144,145,146]. Spain’s fifty provinces are reconstructed into seventeen autonomous communities (ACs) [147]. The central government retains power in defense and foreign affairs; the autonomous communities have extensive jurisdiction over housing, transportation, environmental protection, roads, welfare, and social services [148] through the charters Estatutos de Autonomía [149].
In contrast, non-centralization means that the system is designed from the outset without a single, dominant center [114]. The federal government is created by the constituent units, and it is the constituent units, not the federal government, that are the dominant actors [136,142]. The U.S. federalism in the beginning strictly limited the federal government’s power to specific areas. The current federal systems of Switzerland and Canada also show similar patterns of high autonomy and power non-centralization among the constituent units [150].

3.4. Monist Federalism and Multinational Federalism

As we have already seen, the forms, purposes, and practices of federalism vary across different situations, illustrating its inclusiveness. The most direct manifestation of this inclusiveness is in how it deals with issues of ethnic plurality. Such research has become one of the most active fields within federal studies [151,152]. Currently, the rise of multinational federations is increasingly seen as a reflection on the U.S.-dominated monist federalism. The former emphasizes institutional differences based on group identity, while the latter tends to construct national identity through the uniformity and universality.

3.4.1. Monist Federalism: The United States as Example

For a long time, the United States has been seen as a paradigm of a mono-national federation, aiming to construct a unified American national identity. In practice, U.S. federalism is oriented towards reducing differences between states and emphasizing a single identity for all citizens [153,154,155,156]. As McGarry and OíLeary [157] pointed out, the U.S. federal system views subnational units as administrative entities, rather than political expressions of specific ethnic communities. This logic is typically reflected in the Federalist Papers, as John Jay once said:
“Providence has been pleased to give this one connected country to one united people—a people descended from the same ancestors, speaking the same language, professing the same religion, attached to the same principles of government, very similar in their manners and customs…” [77].
(p. 15)
This federalism embodies a form of liberal monism. It maintains national unity through individualism, civic equality, and the universality of law, rather than by recognizing the unique identities of ethnic groups and communities [5,158].
This is in stark contrast to multinational federations such as Canada, Spain, and Belgium. The latter explicitly recognize and institutionalize the existence of several “peoples” (demoi) or “nations” with unique identities within the country [157]. The United States, however, does not acknowledge the existence of multiple demoi within its borders. Instead, it deliberately avoids the institutional expression of ethnic differences by emphasizing individual freedoms and rights [159]. This constitutes the unique feature of the U.S. federal system as a monist federalism.

3.4.2. Multinational Federalism: Belgium and Canada as Examples

Many contemporary federalism scholars advocate for greater attention to multinational federal approaches [123,160]. They strive to transcend the dominance of monist identity, calling for the recognition the legitimacy of different ethnic groups, no longer marginalizing the heterogeneity of linguistic, racial, and cultural minorities [5,16,113,161,162,163].
Canada and Belgium are widely seen as such paradigms of contemporary multinational federalism. Both countries explicitly accommodate ethnic plurality through federal asymmetry, consociational mechanisms, and a degree of non-territorial autonomy [164,165,166,167]. Because the focus of this sub-section is to elaborate on the differences between monist and multinational federalism, we will only briefly mention the concepts of asymmetry, non-territoriality, and consociationalism here, with detailed introductions provided in the next sub-section.
Canada has been shaped by both English and French cultures since its founding [168,169,170]. Responding to the demands of the French-speaking community has been a major driving force in the evolution of Canadian federalism. The federal system currently has provided multi-level protection for the French-speaking community. The Official Languages Act stipulates that federal agencies must provide services in both English and French [171]. Different provinces also provide different levels of protection to the French-speaking community in terms of education and culture. In Quebec, the federal constitutional arrangements continuously respond to Quebec’s unique identity demands [15,172,173,174]. And New Brunswick is the only officially bilingual province in Canada as stipulated by the constitution. Ontario has ensured French language rights to public services in designated areas through the French Language Services Act. Manitoba has established the bilingual status of English and French. There are also sizable French-speaking communities in other provinces (such as the Acadians), and their language and cultural rights are partially protected through education, judicial and cultural policies.
At the same time, the indigenous peoples of Canada and their treaty rights are recognized and protected at the constitutional level. Section 35 of the Constitution Act, 1982, confirms indigenous and treaty rights; the three northern territories (Yukon, Northwest Territories, Nunavut) have a population structure dominated by indigenous people, and have formed a unique governance model through rights agreements and self-government systems. Within them, the establishment of Nunavut in 1999 is particularly typical. The French-speaking autonomy model represented by Quebec, across other provinces, and the indigenous self-government practices based on treaties, all together shape the pluralistic pattern of Canadian federalism.
In contrast, Belgium has adopted a path of gradual constitutional reform [175,176]. From the establishment of cultural communities in 1970 to full federalization in 1993, Belgium’s federal structure is a typical model combining non-territorial and territorial autonomy [177,178]. The country is territorially divided into three regions—Flanders, Wallonia, and Brussels—each exercising power over its own economic, transportation, construction, financial, and foreign trade affairs. Additionally, there are three language communities—French, Flemish, and German [179,180]. The language communities are responsible for language, education, and cultural affairs [11,181].
Academic research suggests that multinational federations are more stable when dealing with deeply divided societies, as they can reduce cultural assimilation pressures on minority groups. Compared to unitary mono-national federations, they more readily acknowledge cultural plurality, explicitly recognizing the existence of several “peoples” or “demoi” within the country [175]. This acceptance of multiple ethnicities, in return, allows for more complex federal arrangements, such as the previously mentioned constitutional asymmetry, consociationalism, and non-territorial autonomy [182].
However, complex multinational federal arrangements also bring challenges. They require maintaining high levels of dialogue and institutional adjustment, otherwise, they may become risk points for identity politics struggles [15,164,172,183].
Table 2 below summarizes the main differences between typical mono-national/monist federations (the United States) and multinational federations (Canada, Belgium).

3.5. Innovative Concepts in Multinational Federalism

As we have slightly mentioned above, in the field of multinational federalism, scholars have proposed a number of innovative concepts to deal with the challenges of the growing aspects of ethnic diversity. Among them, asymmetry, non-territoriality, and consociationalism have become the key concepts.

3.5.1. Asymmetrical Federalism

Asymmetrical federalism is an innovation that provides tailored autonomy to prevent secession or deep-rooted conflicts. Under asymmetrical federalism, different regions or provinces enjoy varying degrees of autonomy [6,72,108,130,133,150,173,174]. Specifically, certain provinces are allowed to have more rights than others [16,82]. These arrangements usually reflect their unique historical, cultural, or political factors.
Today, asymmetrical federalism is mainly divided into two types: de facto asymmetry, caused by natural resources, population, and fiscal endowments, also known as political asymmetry, and de jure asymmetry, or constitutional asymmetry, referring to the asymmetry confirmed by the constitution and laws in terms of legislative power, representation in central institutions, and others [85,142,185,186,187,188].
Canada and Spain are prominent examples. In Canada, Quebec enjoys a special status due to its unique cultural and linguistic identity [117,185,189,190]. Although the Canadian federal government has given French and English equal status, many Quebecers are still not satisfied. They think this “equality” policy ignores their unique identity and historical status [191,192]. Quebecers demand constitutional recognition as a “distinct society” and an asymmetrical federal status [193,194].
The original intention of asymmetrical arrangements is to recognize differences and reduce ethnic tensions. But its side effects have also gradually emerged. Not only in Canada [195,196], but also in Spain [147,197,198], there is dissatisfaction caused by asymmetrical arrangements. Granting a unique asymmetrical status to specific groups often comes at the expense of other “majority” groups. Moreover, it may further marginalize minorities within minority groups [199]. For example, in Quebec, Canada, English speakers have become disadvantaged in language, education, and administrative affairs because they live in Quebec, which asymmetrically favors French speakers [200,201]. Asymmetrical federalism, if not well-managed, may evolve into some kind of identity politics, thereby undermining its original intention [202]. Thus, maintaining asymmetrical federalism requires not only institutional arrangements and power distribution, but also continuous dialogue.

3.5.2. Non-Territorial Autonomy

Non-territorial autonomy (NTA) provides another flexible federal tool: it grants cultural, linguistic, and religious groups the right to self-governance without redrawing territorial boundaries [203,204,205,206,207,208]. This institutional arrangement is particularly suitable for communities whose members are dispersed and cannot easily form clear territorial concentrations [209,210]. Through non-territorial autonomy, these cultural, linguistic, or religious communities can manage their own schools, culture, and language affairs while remaining within the existing unit, thus avoiding territorial disputes and the risk of secession [199,211,212,213]. For some scholars, non-territorial autonomy is indeed conducive to multinational federalism [214].
The language communities in Belgium, which will be mentioned later, are often seen as a model of non-territorial autonomy [180,203,215,216]. The French-speaking and Dutch-speaking (Flemish) communities, as well as the German-speaking community, in the country enjoy autonomy in cultural and educational affairs. In recent years, the discussion on non-territorial autonomy in dealing with ethnic pluralism has attracted more and more attention, especially in managing cross-border migrant communities [217,218].
However, non-territorial autonomy also has its inherent limitations. Some state functions, such as policing, military, immigration, and infrastructure construction, are still difficult to devolve to communities in a non-territorial manner [199,219,220]. This means that non-territorial autonomy is often seen as a complementary rather than an alternative mode to territorial autonomy [207,221,222]. In addition, non-territorial autonomy may also face problems such as ambiguous identity and difficulty in defining membership [199].

3.5.3. Consociationalism

Consociationalism is another power-sharing mechanism that is often used in conjunction with federalism. Federalism provides the institutional structure, while consociationalism, in addition to institutions, also carries the meaning of “norm” [1]. Together, they form an institutional combination for governing fragmented societies [223]. Consociationalism typically has four key characteristics: grand coalition cabinets, mutual veto power over major decisions, proportional representation in public offices, and segmented autonomy that allows cultural communities to retain their own rules [224]. This mechanism is particularly suitable for countries divided by deep ethnic, religious, or linguistic cleavages. In these countries, majority-rule democracy often fails to maintain political stability. Only through negotiation and compromise among the elites of the divided groups, can a fragile protection of pluralism be achieved [1,164,225].
Belgium is especially a well-known example, where its federalization process, including its non-territorial federal arrangements, is the product of institutionalized consociationalism [120,164,226]. Some scholars also point out that the EU, to some extent, has characteristics of consociationalism [226].
In recent years, consociationalism has also attracted attention in post-conflict national reconstruction. For example, the Dayton Agreement in Bosnia and Herzegovina [227], post-war reconstruction in Iraq [228], and the Taif Agreement in Lebanon [229], all partially reflect the principles of consociationalism. However, there are indeed criticisms that this elite-dominated governance model may reinforce ethnic identities, weaken national identity, and suppress civil society [223,230,231].

3.6. Presidential Federalism and Parliamentary Federalism

Another dimension that needs to be mentioned is the coupling of forms of government (presidential or parliamentary) with federalism. This dimension affects the interaction patterns of the executive, legislative and political parties within the federal system.
The United States is usually regarded as the first modern federal country with a typical presidential system. Under this system, the president, as the independently elected executive head, is separate from Congress. They check and balance each other. The dynamics of federal power show a multiple interaction: between the president and Congress, between state governments and the federal government, and between the two parties [30,232]. This system often leads to a more decentralized policy-making process, with a higher possibility of legislative deadlock when there is a divided government [110].
In contrast, Canada and Australia represent the paradigm of parliamentary federalism, where executive power derives from a parliamentary majority. Canada’s federal constitution of 1867 is the first example of parliamentary federalism [233]. Some scholars argue that Canada constitutes a Canadian model with stronger parliamentary and executive coordination, different from the presidential model of the United States [234,235]. In this system, policy formulation and implementation are better coordinated [13,236]. Party discipline is strong, and the policy objectives of the cabinet and the parliamentary majority usually remain consistent. It enables the central government to more efficiently promote federal legislation and budgetary arrangements [237]. However, strong central executive power may also weaken the political power of states [236].
Distinguishing these two types of federalism in perspectives of executive-legislative relations helps understand why federal constitution can produce different consequences of power implementation. For example, presidential federalism tends to emphasize the role of judicial review in resolving federal conflicts. However, parliamentary federalism relies more on the executive head and inter-governmental mechanisms [122].

3.7. Democratic Federalism and Authoritarian Federalism

The relationship between federalism and democracy is also a hot theme in federalism studies. For Burgess and Gagnon, federalism is a democratic principle aimed at maintaining a unified political community while ensuring local participation and autonomy [160]. Other scholar also mention that federalism is not only about institutional design, but also an embodiment of democratic governance concepts, with multi-level governance, citizen participation as its intrinsic mechanisms [238].
From the perspective of comparative politics, some scholars distinguish federalism into democratic federalism and authoritarian federalism [8,239]. Some scholars refer to those systems that merely have a federal decentralization structure in form but are in fact authoritarian as facade federalism [240]. Democratic federalism emphasizes the independence of multi-level governments, electoral competition, and fair judiciary. Authoritarian federalism, on the other hand, retains the external form of a federation but lacks an independent judicial system, free party competition, and effective local autonomy. The federal form thus becomes a tool for the center to consolidate power and distribute resources.
Democratic federalism expands the space for citizen participation. Canadian political philosopher Charles Taylor holds that federal systems decentralize decision-making to local levels, to “allow units to exist which are closer to the people governed” [241] (p. 7). This is particularly suitable for regions with high social heterogeneity, enabling politics to more closely match the diverse needs of society [110,242].
Lower federal levels—such as municipalities and town halls—can serve as platforms for cultivating political leaders, especially from groups previously excluded from political life, like women, young people, and ethnic minorities [243]. These local institutions provide citizens with more accessible avenues for public participation, such as joining grassroots movements, contacting elected officials, and attending public forums [244]. Through these means, federalism promotes more effective political expression and accountability, thus clearly contributing to democracy [245,246,247].
On the other hand, federalism can also pose challenges to democracy. First, federal arrangements may entrench the power base of local elites, enabling them to obstruct social and political reforms. For example, the persistence of racial segregation policies in U.S. history for many years was partly due to opposition from state governments, especially in Mississippi, Alabama, and Arkansas [248,249]. Federal structures can also be exploited as a testing ground for conservative legislation to block democracy—through practices like gerrymandering, strict voter ID laws, reducing early voting, and mass purges of voter rolls [250].
Moreover, the rise of radical federalism poses a new challenge to existing federalism. It attempts to reinterpret constitutional provisions to greatly weaken federal authority and national legal framework. While appropriate decentralization can promote local autonomy, radical decentralization without central coordination can be abused to exacerbate regional inequalities, and thus endanger democracy itself [251,252].
Under authoritarian federalism, federalism may become a tool for the central government to maintain its rule, rather than a carrier of democracy. In the absence of an independent judiciary, media freedom, and a robust civil society, federal structures can be exploited by authoritarian regimes [116,252]. For example, in Russia, the authorities have gradually centralized power under the guise of nominal decentralization through measures such as restricting gubernatorial elections and strengthening fiscal vertical dependency [253]. In countries like Nigeria and Ethiopia, local governments sometimes serve as arenas for ethnic mobilization or resource capture, rather than as guarantors of citizen autonomy [253,254,255].
However, research also shows that even within non-democratic systems, federalism may create institutional frictions and open spaces. Research indicates that fiscal decentralization sometimes provides opportunities for local policy innovation or experimental reforms, even if these opportunities do not immediately lead to democratic transitions [138,256]. Precisely for this reason, non-democratic/authoritarian federalism may both reinforce centralization and become the institutional soil for future democratization.

4. Federalism in Policies

In addition to the discussion of federalism as a political institution and a normative ideal, federalism also interacts with different policy areas, giving rise to research areas such as fiscal federalism, environmental federalism, welfare federalism and health care federalism. This section briefly introduces these specific policy areas of federalism, their practices, and the challenges they face.

4.1. Fiscal Federalism

Fiscal federalism studies the division of financial responsibilities between federal and local governments [257,258,259]. It typically involves stabilization functions (unemployment, inflation), distribution functions (income redistribution), and allocation functions (provision of goods/services). Functions that are universal or cross-regional are generally considered more suitable for the central government; for functions with regional characteristics, sub-national governments are more appropriate [260].
Regarding the distribution of tax revenue, taxes on highly mobile entities (such as value-added tax) are best managed by the central government to avoid a “race to the bottom” and tax spillovers [261,262]. Taxes on less mobile entities are more suitable for state and local governments [260,263,264]. In terms of expenditure responsibilities, defense spending is basically the responsibility of the central government. Local governments usually take charge of more local resident services, but often have to rely on central government fiscal transfers due to fiscal capacity constraints [265,266].
However, the imbalance between revenue and expenditure often becomes a problem in fiscal federalism, leading to inefficiency and irresponsibility [267,268]. Although most countries have established a system of fiscal transfers from the central to the local, whether the distribution of transfers is fair often sparks debate. Moreover, continuous transfers may also weaken the fiscal discipline of local governments in a federal system [269,270].
In addition to fiscal transfers from the central government, direct fiscal decentralization to local governments is another option. Some scholars argue that a certain degree of fiscal decentralization can improve the efficiency of local government public spending [271]. But other scholars point out that, under conditions of political polarization and poor institutional design, excessive decentralization may lead to unsustainable policies [272]. Moreover, the imbalance in economic development among regions also poses challenges to fiscal decentralization, such as those faced by EU member states [273].

4.2. Environmental Federalism

Environmental policy is also an area where central and subnational governments divide power and cooperate within a federal system. Usually, the federal government sets standards, while states are in charge of implementation and make adjustments according to local conditions [274,275].
For example, in the United States, under the Clean Air Act, states devise their own plans to meet National Ambient Air Quality Standards. Similarly, under the Clean Water Act, states take on the responsibility of issuing and enforcing permits [276]. In addition, the National Environmental Policy Act (NEPA) provides an institutional framework for federal-state cooperation. On the other hand, independent exploration by state governments can sometimes, in turn, promote federal legislation. For example, California’s Global Warming Solutions Act (AB 32) has served as a legislative template at the federal level [277].
On the contrary, the Canadian example reflects tensions between the federal and provincial governments on environmental issues. The Canadian government proposed a “carbon pricing” policy to cut carbon emissions, but traditional oil-producing provinces like Alberta opposed it [278]. On the one hand, environmental governance has cross-regional characteristics, and individual states can not thoroughly solve the problem of “negative externalities” [279]. For instance, if one state/province allows high-polluting enterprises, the pollutants may spread to neighboring states. On the other hand, local governments have information on specific industries and can make more reasonable responses [127]. This creates tension between federal-level decision-making and local realities.
In federal-like structures such as the European Union, due to the lack of central-level authority, dealing with environmental issues has to rely more on softer, consultative approaches. Policy incentives and cooperative networks, rather than enforcement, are used more to align the policies of member states [280,281].

4.3. Health Care and Welfare Federalism

Federalism also affects health care and social welfare policies. Usually, federal and state governments adopt a cooperative model to jointly share the responsibilities for social welfare and medical services [282,283]. Similarly to environmental policies, the federal government usually provides a broad framework but encourages state to adapt to local unique conditions [284].
Take the United States as an example. The federal government leads major legislative actions such as medical insurance and assistance, but their implementation is highly dependent on state governments. Some states expand the coverage of Medicaid while others resist. This leads to significant differences in medical services among states [285,286]. In addition, states also play a leading role in physician licensing, drug regulation, and crisis response.
In Canada, although social insurance and pension plans (the Canada Pension Plan, CPP) originated from federal design, provinces are gaining increasing autonomy [284]. For example, Quebec has successfully devolved the responsibility for social programs from the federal level [283]. Quebec also established its own pension system, the Quebec Pension Plan (QPP) [287,288]. These measures not only strengthen the legitimacy of provincial governments in Quebec society but also enhance Quebec’s position on social welfare policies relative to the other nine provinces [289].
However, the impact of social welfare policies under federalism is two-way. On the one hand, states are closer to local preferences and can try appropriate policy approaches. Successful innovations may then be extended to the federal level [290,291]. On the other hand, federalism may lead to unequal treatment of citizens, especially when there are significant differences in the fiscal capabilities of various states [248,292].
For example, due to its weaker economic base, Western Canada faces greater pressure in social welfare compared to other provinces. However, federal-level transfer payments are not sufficient to bridge this gap [293]. In the United States, southern states receive lower public health investments than the national average, exacerbating the vulnerability of relatively poor groups [285,294]. During the COVID-19 period, to some extent, the coordination dilemma in federal countries was also highlighted in the process of medical procurement and material distribution [295].

5. Conclusions

This study comprehensively presents a panoramic view of federalism research. It not only offers a theoretical and empirical overview but also aims to show scholars a set of operational research agendas. It is hoped that readers will use this as a starting point to combine theoretical frameworks with cross-regional and cross-methodological research, thereby filling the geographical and thematic gaps in future studies. In this study, we showed the early forms of federalism, such as the city-state alliances in classical Greece and the confederation of the Iroquois tribes. Next, we introduced the pioneer of early modern federal thought, Johannes Althusius, mentioning his symbiosis and association federal theory, which laid the normative foundation for federalism to resist centralization. We examined the early American constitutional debates between federalist and anti-federalist and how the United States achieved a successful federal design to prevent tyranny of the majority. However, it was this institution-oriented approach that, to some extent, overshadowed Althusius’s normative vision.
We then looked at the various manifestations of federalism: the differences in origin between coming-together federalism and holding-together federalism, the institutional evolution between dual federalism and cooperative federalism, the distinction between decentralization and non-centralization, the innovations of asymmetrical and non-territorial federalism, and the differences between presidential federalism and parliamentary federalism. All of these indicate that federalism has strong plasticity and can be adapted to different backgrounds. Nevertheless, federalism is not without challenges. We also mentioned the operation of federalism in non-democratic and authoritarian systems: it can maintain autonomy through the decentralization of power, but it can also become a tool for authoritarian authorities to manipulate politics.
This study strives to map the entire picture of federalism research, although it has far from exhausted all dimensions in this field. We have to admit that given the limitations of space and the availability of materials, this paper does have a preference for the selection of materials and cases mainly from North America and Europe (especially Belgium, Spain, Switzerland, etc.). Federal or quasi-federal practices in Africa, Latin America, and Asia (such as the federal fiscal mechanisms in Brazil and Mexico, the ethnic federal governance in Nigeria and Ethiopia) have not been deeply discussed in this paper. In future research, it is obvious that there needs to be greater geographical diversity rather than just focusing on Western cases. Follow-up studies can expand the framework shown in this paper through regional thematic studies.
To make the encyclopedic review more academically progressive, based on the research topics already reviewed, this paper proposes several testable propositions for future researchers to consider: (i) Whether non-territorial autonomy (NTA) reduces the risk of secessionist conflicts: In countries with a significant distribution of ethnic differences, has units adopting a non-territorial autonomy system reduced the incidence of ethnic violence? (ii) The coordination ability of federalism in transnational (environmental, health) affairs also deserves more attention. This can be studied using quantitative regression analysis. The measurement indicator can be the existence of coordination mechanisms. (iii) In terms of federalism and democratic resilience, I propose a hypothesis that the protective effect of federalism on democracy depends on the existence of judicial independence and media freedom. To test this hypothesis, interaction-term regression analysis can be used.
Overall, whether as an institution or as a normative theory, the breadth and depth of federalism increasingly demonstrate that this topic is worthy of in-depth study. In an increasingly pluralistic, and even fragmented, world, federalism will continue to provide us with insights on how to balance unity and diversity.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Acknowledgments

I would like to express my sincere gratitude to Devrim Sezer in Izmir University of Economics, who guided me toward the research of federalism and provided invaluable inspiration. I would like to thank the academic editor for the guidance provided during the manuscript processing. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their comments, which have greatly improved this manuscript.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

References

  1. Elazar, D.J. Federalism and Consociational Regimes. Publius J. Fed. 1985, 15, 17–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Elazar, D.J. Exploring Federalism, 1st ed.; University of Alabama Press: Tuscaloosa, AL, USA, 1987; ISBN 978-0-8173-0575-8. [Google Scholar]
  3. Hüglin, T.O. Yet the Age of Anarchism? Publius J. Fed. 1985, 15, 101–112. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Zuckert, M.P. Federalism and the Founding: Toward a Reinterpretation of the Constitutional Convention. Rev. Polit. 1986, 48, 166–210. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Karmis, D.; MacLure, J. Two Escape Routes from the Paradigm of Monistic Authenticity: Post-Imperialist and Federal Perspectives on Plural and Complex Identities. Ethn. Racial Stud. 2001, 24, 361–385. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Requejo, F. National Pluralism and Federalism. Four Potential Scenarios for Spanish Plurinational Democracy. Perspect. Eur. Politics Soc. 2001, 2, 305–327. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Chryssochoou, D.N. Federalism and Democracy Reconsidered. Reg. Fed. Stud. 1998, 8, 1–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Filippov, M.; Shvetsova, O. Federalism, Democracy, and Democratization. In Federal Dynamics: Continuity, Change, and the Varieties of Federalism; Benz, A., Broschek, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; pp. 167–185. ISBN 978-0-19-965299-0. [Google Scholar]
  9. Guzina, D. Federalism and Regional Autonomy. In Oxford Research Encyclopedia of International Studies; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010; ISBN 978-0-19-084662-6. [Google Scholar]
  10. Moreno, L.; Arriba, A.; Serrano, A. Multiple Identities in Decentralized Spain: The Case of Catalonia. Reg. Fed. Stud. 1998, 8, 65–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Covell, M. Regionalization and Economic Crisis in Belgium: The Variable Origins of Centrifugal and Centripetal Forces. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 1986, 19, 261–281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Benz, A.; Sonnicksen, J. (Eds.) Federal Democracies at Work: Varieties of Complex Government, 1st ed.; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada; Buffalo, NY, USA; London, UK, 2021; ISBN 978-1-4875-0900-2. [Google Scholar]
  13. Sayers, A.M.; Banfield, A.C. The Evolution of Federalism and Executive Power in Canada and Australia. In Federal Dynamics: Continuity, Change, and the Varieties of Federalism; Benz, A., Broschek, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; pp. 185–205. ISBN 978-0-19-965299-0. [Google Scholar]
  14. Requejo, F.; Sanjaume-Calvet, M. Defensive Federalism: Protecting Territorial Minorities from the “Tyranny of the Majority”, 1st ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2022; ISBN 978-1-003-29606-5. [Google Scholar]
  15. Karmis, D.; Gagnon, A.-G. Federalism, Federation and Collective Identities in Canada and Belgium: Different Routes, Similar Fragmentation. In Multinational Democracies; Gagnon, A.-G., Tully, J., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 137–175. ISBN 978-0-511-52157-7. [Google Scholar]
  16. Kymlicka, W. Federalism, Nationalism, and Multiculturalism. In Theories of Federalism: A Reader; Karmis, D., Norman, W., Eds.; Palgrave Macmillan US: New York, NY, USA, 2005; pp. 269–292. ISBN 978-0-312-29581-3. [Google Scholar]
  17. Béland, D.; Lecours, A. Does Nationalism Trigger Welfare-State Disintegration? Social Policy and Territorial Mobilization in Belgium and Canada. Environ. Plann. C. 2010, 28, 420–434. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Hale, G.E. Canadian Federalism and the Challenge of North American Integration. Can. Public Adm. 2004, 47, 497–524. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Loughlin, J. Federalism, Regionalism and Local Government: Comparative Perspectives on Transforming the Nation-State. Eur. Polit. Sci. 2008, 7, 472–482. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Da Silva, M. Federalism: Contemporary Political Philosophy Issues. Philos. Compass 2022, 17, e12820. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Fenna, A.; Schnabel, J. What Is Federalism? Some Definitional Clarification. Publius J. Fed. 2024, 54, 179–200. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. McCulloch, A. Consociational Executives: Power-Sharing Governments between Inclusion and Functionality. In Defensive Federalism: Protecting Territorial Minorities from the “Tyranny of the Majority”; Requejo, F., Sanjaume-Calvet, M., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2022; pp. 22–45. ISBN 978-1-003-29606-5. [Google Scholar]
  23. Bertel, M. The Fabulous Designs of Federal States. In The Value of Comparative Federalism: The Legacy of Ronald L. Watts; Steytler, N.C., Arora, B., Saxena, R., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2021; pp. 86–101. ISBN 978-0-367-77560-5. [Google Scholar]
  24. Jewkes, M. Diversity, Federalism and the Nineteenth-Century Liberals. Crit. Rev. Int. Soc. Polit. Philos. 2016, 19, 184–205. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. Baronowski, D.W. Roman Treaties with Communities of Citizens. Class. Q. 1988, 38, 172–178. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Spruyt, H. Chapter 6—The Fragmentation of the German Empire and the Rise of the Hanseatic League. In The Sovereign State and Its Competitors; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1994; pp. 109–129. ISBN 978-0-691-21305-7. [Google Scholar]
  27. Steinman, E. Indigenous Nationhood Claims and Contemporary Federalism in Canada and the United States. Policy Soc. 2005, 24, 98–123. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Scott, K.A. Macrolevel Consent: A Defense of Federalism. Publius J. Fed. 2012, 42, 592–612. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Wheare, K.C. Federal Government, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1946. [Google Scholar]
  30. Riker, W.H. Federalism: Origins, Operation, Significance, 1st ed.; Little, Brown and Company: New York, NY, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
  31. Elazar, D.J. (Ed.) Federal Systems of the World: A Handbook of Federal, Confederal, and Autonomy Arrangements, 2nd ed.; Longman Current Affairs; Longman: Harlow, UK, 1994; ISBN 978-0-582-23678-3. [Google Scholar]
  32. Choudhry, S. Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation? Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008; ISBN 978-0-19-953541-5. [Google Scholar]
  33. Ryan, E. Federalism as Legal Pluralism. In The Oxford Handbook of Global Legal Pluralism; Berman, P.S., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020; pp. 491–527. ISBN 978-0-19-751674-4. [Google Scholar]
  34. Berman, P.S. Federalism and International Law through the Lens of Legal Pluralism. Mo. Law Rev. 2008, 73, 1149–1184. [Google Scholar]
  35. Berman, P.S. Global Legal Pluralism: A Jurisprudence of Law Beyond Borders, 1st ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012; ISBN 978-1-139-02861-5. [Google Scholar]
  36. Resnik, J. Law’s Migration: American Exceptionalism, Silent Dialogues, and Federalism’s Multiple Ports of Entry. Yale Law J. 2006, 115, 1564–1670. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  37. Gerken, H.K. Federalism All the Way Down. Harv. Law Rev. 2010, 124, 4–74. [Google Scholar]
  38. Walker, N. The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism. Mod. Law Rev. 2002, 65, 317–359. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  39. Maduro, M.P. Contrapunctual Law: Europe’s Constitutional Pluralism in Action. In Sovereignty in Transition: Essays in European Law; Walker, N., Ed.; Hart: Oxford, UK, 2006; pp. 501–537. ISBN 978-1-84113-564-9. [Google Scholar]
  40. Avbelj, M.; Komárek, J. Constitutional Pluralism in the European Union and Beyond; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2012; ISBN 978-1-84731-891-6. [Google Scholar]
  41. Teubner, G. Constitutional Fragments: Societal Constitutionalism and Globalization. In Oxford Constitutional Theory; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012; ISBN 978-0-19-964467-4. [Google Scholar]
  42. Krisch, N. Beyond Constitutionalism: The Pluralist Structure of Postnational Law. In Oxford Constitutional Theory; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010; ISBN 978-0-19-922831-7. [Google Scholar]
  43. Føllesdal, A. Survey Article: Subsidiarity. J. Polit. Philos. 1998, 6, 190–218. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Ossewaarde, M.R.R. Three Rival Versions of Political Enquiry: Althusius and the Concept of Sphere Sovereignty. Monist 2007, 90, 106–125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  45. Von Gierke, O.F. Johannes Althusius and the Development of Natural Law Theory, 1st ed.; Karl-Marx Verlag: Potsdam, Germany, 2025; ISBN 978-3-9825536-4-1. [Google Scholar]
  46. Baker, J.W. The Covenantal Basis for the Development of Swiss Political Federalism: 1291–1848. Publius J. Fed. 1993, 23, 19–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Hüglin, T.O. Early Modern Concepts for a Late Modern World: Althusius on Community and Federalism, 1st ed.; Wilfrid Laurier University Press: Waterloo, ON, Canada, 1999; ISBN 978-0-88920-322-8. [Google Scholar]
  48. Ruokanen, J. Alignment of the Individual and Common Good in the Political Theory of Johannes Althusius. In Common Good and Self-Interest in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy; Haara, H., Toivanen, J., Eds.; The New Synthese Historical Library; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2024; Volume 78, pp. 171–197. ISBN 978-3-031-55303-5. [Google Scholar]
  49. Kong, L. Johannes Althusius: The First Federalist in Early Modern Times. Histories 2025, 5, 35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  50. de Benoist, A. The First Federalist: Johannes Althusius. Telos 2000, 2000, 25–58. [Google Scholar]
  51. Althusius, J. Politica: An Abridged Translation of Politics Methodicely Set Forth and Illustrated with Sacred and Profane Examples, 1st ed.; Liberty Fund: Carmel, IN, USA, 1995; ISBN 978-0-86597-115-8. [Google Scholar]
  52. Overeem, P. Johannes Althusius on Public Administration. Adm. Theory Prax. 2014, 36, 31–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Skillen, J.W. The Political Theory of Johannes Althusius. Philos. Reformata 1974, 39, 170–190. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  54. Witte, J. The Universal Rule of Natural Law and Written Constitutions in the Thought of Johannes Althusius. In Morality and Responsibility of Rulers: European and Chinese Origins of a Rule of Law as Justice for World Order; Carty, A., Nijman, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; pp. 167–186. ISBN 978-0-19-967005-5. [Google Scholar]
  55. Elazar, D.J. The Multi-Faceted Covenant: The Biblical Approach to the Problem of Organizations, Constitutions, and Liberty as Reflected in the Thought of Johannes Althusius. Const. Political Econ. 1991, 2, 187–208. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  56. Malan, K.J. Johannes Althusius’ Grand Federalism, the Role of the Ephors and Post-Statist Constitutionalism. Potchefstroom Electron. Law J. 2017, 20, 1–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Heidemann, D.; Stoppenbrink, K. (Eds.) Join, or Die—Philosophical Foundations of Federalism, 1st ed.; De Gruyter: Boston, MA, USA, 2016; ISBN 978-3-11-042658-8. [Google Scholar]
  58. Nicolaïdis, K. European Demoicracy and Its Crisis. JCMS J. Common Mark. Stud. 2013, 51, 351–369. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  59. Scharpf, F.W. Legitimacy in the Multilevel European Polity. Eur. Polit. Sci. Rev. 2009, 1, 173–204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  60. Follesdal, A.; Hix, S. Why There Is a Democratic Deficit in the EU: A Response to Majone and Moravcsik. JCMS J. Common Mark. Stud. 2006, 44, 533–562. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Hüglin, T.O. Federalism at the Crossroads: Old Meanings, New Significance. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 2003, 36, 275–294. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  62. Moots, G.A. Politics Reformed: The Anglo-American Legacy of Covenant Theology; University of Missouri Press: Columbia, MO, USA, 2022; ISBN 978-0-8262-2263-3. [Google Scholar]
  63. Pettit, P. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. In Oxford Political Theory; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003; ISBN 978-0-19-829642-3. [Google Scholar]
  64. Viroli, M. Republicanism, 1st American ed.; Hill and Wang: New York, NY, USA, 2002; ISBN 978-0-8090-8077-9. [Google Scholar]
  65. von Gierke, O.F. Johannes Althusius und die Entwicklung der Naturrechtlichen Staatstheorien. In Nachdruck der Ausgabe von 1880; Hansebooks GmbH: Norderstedt, Germany, 2016; ISBN 978-3-7411-8726-1. [Google Scholar]
  66. von Gierke, O.F. The Development of Political Theory. Freyd, B., Ed.; 2018 Reprint; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-0-203-70535-3. [Google Scholar]
  67. Woldring, H.E.S. The Constitutional State in the Political Philosophy of Johannes Althusius. Eur. J. Law Econ. 1998, 5, 123–132. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  68. Nitschke, P. Volkssouveränität Missverstanden: Die Althusius-Rezeption Bei Otto von Gierke in Der Relektüre. In Der Staat Als Genossenschaft: Zum Rechtshistorischen und Politischen Werk Otto von Gierkes; Schröder, P., Ed.; Staatsverständnisse; Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft mbH & Co. KG: Baden-Baden, Germany, 2021; ISBN 978-3-8487-6128-9. [Google Scholar]
  69. Hüglin, T.O. Sozietaler Föderalismus: Die Politische Theorie des Johannes Althusius; European University Institute—Series C; Reprint 2013; De Gruyter: Tubingen, Germany, 2013; ISBN 978-3-11-012830-7. [Google Scholar]
  70. Jouin, C. Althusius et l’Europe. De Quoi Althusius Est-Il Le Nom? Noesis 2020, 35–36, 163–182. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  71. Hobbes, T. Leviathan. In Oxford World’s Classics; Gaskin, J.C.A., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1998; ISBN 978-0-19-283498-0. [Google Scholar]
  72. Locke, J. Two Treatises of Government: And a Letter Concerning Toleration. In Rethinking the Western Tradition; Shapiro, I., Ed.; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA; London, UK, 2003; ISBN 978-0-300-10017-4. [Google Scholar]
  73. Rousseau, J.-J. The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings. In Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought, 1st ed.; Gourevitch, V., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1997; ISBN 978-0-521-41382-4. [Google Scholar]
  74. Skinner, Q. Liberty Before Liberalism; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1998; ISBN 978-1-139-17127-4. [Google Scholar]
  75. Zuckert, M. On the Separation of Powers: Liberal and Progressive Constitutionalism. Soc. Philos. Policy 2012, 29, 335–364. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  76. Putterman, E. Rousseau on Agenda-Setting and Majority Rule. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 2003, 97, 459–469. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  77. Hamilton, A.; Madison, J.; Jay, J. The Federalist Papers. In Oxford World’s Classics; Goldman, L., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2008; ISBN 978-0-19-280592-8. [Google Scholar]
  78. Wood, G.S. Ideology and the Origins of Liberal America. In Thomas Paine; Kuklick, B., Ed.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2018; pp. 271–283. ISBN 978-1-351-14462-9. [Google Scholar]
  79. Pocock, J.G.A. The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition, 2nd ed.; Princeton Paperbacks; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2003; ISBN 978-0-691-11472-9. [Google Scholar]
  80. Wood, G.S. The Creation of the American Republic, 1776–1787; The Norton Library: New York, NY, USA, 1972; ISBN 978-0-393-00644-5. [Google Scholar]
  81. Bermeo, N. A New Look at Federalism: The Import of Institutions. J. Democr. 2002, 13, 96–110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  82. Kong, L. The Sacred Federation of Tibet and the Mongol Empire. Histories 2024, 4, 557–574. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  83. Moots, G.A. The Covenant Tradition of Federalism: The Pioneering Studies of Daniel J. Elazar. In The Ashgate Research Companion to Federalism; Ward, A., Ward, L., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2009; pp. 391–412. ISBN 978-0-367-60302-1. [Google Scholar]
  84. Mollov, B. Daniel J. Elazar: Federalism, Brit, and Implications for Israeli Society. Jew. Political Stud. Rev. 2007, 19, 135–145. [Google Scholar]
  85. Hüglin, T.O. Federalism and Political Theory: A Case of Mutual Neglect. In A Research Agenda for Federalism Studies; Kincaid, J., Ed.; Elgar Research Agendas; Edward Elgar Publishing Limited: Cheltenham, UK, 2019; pp. 15–26. ISBN 978-1-78811-296-3. [Google Scholar]
  86. Erk, J. Federalism and Non-Territorial Representation. Forum Fed. 2003, 1–24. Available online: https://forumfedorg.b-cdn.net/libdocs/SriLanka02/946-SLMG0306-Erk.pdf (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  87. Diamond, M. The American Idea of Equality: The View from the Founding. Rev. Polit. 1976, 38, 313–331. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  88. McLaughlin, A.C. The Background of American Federalism. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 1918, 12, 215–240. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  89. Eblen, J.E. Origins of the United States Colonial System: The Ordinance of 1787. Wis. Mag. Hist. 1968, 51, 294–314. [Google Scholar]
  90. Mittal, S.; Rakove, J.N.; Weingast, B.R. The Constitutional Choices of 1787 and Their Consequences. In Founding Choices: American Economic Policy in the 1790s; Irwin, D.A., Sylla, R.E., Eds.; A National Bureau of Economic Research Conference Report; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2010; pp. 25–56. ISBN 978-0-226-38474-0. [Google Scholar]
  91. Wolfe, C. On Understanding the Constitutional Convention of 1787. J. Polit. 1977, 39, 97–118. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  92. Yarbrough, J. Rethinking “the Federalist’s View of Federalism.” . Publius J. Fed. 1985, 15, 31–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  93. Sinopoli, R.C. Liberalism and Political Allegiance in Anti-Federalist Political Thought. Publius J. Fed. 1992, 22, 123–139. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  94. Elazar, D.J. Confederation and Federal Liberty. Publius J. Fed. 1982, 12, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  95. Nowlin, J.W. The Rehnquist Court and the “New Federalism”. In The Ashgate Research Companion to Federalism; Ward, A., Ward, L., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2009; pp. 551–565. ISBN 978-0-367-60302-1. [Google Scholar]
  96. Black, F.R. The American Revolution as “Yardstick” in the Debates on the Constitution, 1787–1788. Proc. Am. Philos. Soc. 1973, 117, 162–185. [Google Scholar]
  97. Derthick, M. American Federalism: Madison’s Middle Ground in the 1980s. Public Adm. Rev. 1987, 47, 66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  98. Borowiak, C.T. Accountability Debates: The Federalists, the Anti-Federalists, and Democratic Deficits. J. Polit. 2007, 69, 998–1014. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  99. Hampsher-Monk, I. Democracy and Federation in the Federalist Papers. In Federal Democracies; Burgess, M., Gagnon, A., Eds.; Routledge Series in Federal Studies; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2010; pp. 29–45. ISBN 978-1-138-96964-3. [Google Scholar]
  100. Peterson, P. The Meaning of Republicanism in the Federalist. Publius J. Fed. 1979, 9, 43–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  101. Wood, G.S. Democracy and the Constitution. In How Democratic Is the Constitution? Goldwin, R.A., Schambra, W.A., Eds.; American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research: Washington, DC, USA, 1980; pp. 1–17. ISBN 978-0-8447-3400-2. [Google Scholar]
  102. Wood, G.S. “Motives at Philadelphia”: A Comment on Slonim. Law Hist. Rev. 1998, 16, 553–562. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  103. Zuckert, M.P. Completing the Constitution: The Fourteenth Amendment and Constitutional Rights. Publius J. Fed. 1992, 22, 69–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  104. Arendt, H. On Revolution, 1st Penguin Classics ed.; Penguin Publishing Group: New York, NY, USA, 2006; ISBN 978-0-14-303990-7. [Google Scholar]
  105. Duncan, C.M. Men of a Different Faith: The Anti-Federalist Ideal in Early American Political Thought. Polity 1994, 26, 387–415. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  106. Wolin, S.S. What Revolutionary Action Means Today. In Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community; Mouffe, C., Ed.; Verso: London, UK, 1992; pp. 240–253. ISBN 978-0-8609-1556-0. [Google Scholar]
  107. Morey, W.C. The Sources of American Federalism. Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. Soc. Sci. 1895, 6, 1–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  108. Kramnick, I. The “Great National Discussion”: The Discourse of Politics in 1787. William Mary Q. Mag. Early Am. Hist. 1988, 45, 3–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  109. Popp-Madsen, B.A. Anti-Federalism and the Question of Constituent Power in the American Constitutional Debate. Ideas Hist. J. Nord. Soc. Hist. Ideas 2014, 8, 25–46. [Google Scholar]
  110. Stepan, A. Federalism and Democracy: Beyond the U.S. Model. J. Democr. 1999, 10, 19–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  111. Stepan, A. Comparative Theory and Political Practice: Do We Need a ‘State-Nation’ Model as Well as a ‘Nation-State’ Model? Gov. Oppos. 2008, 43, 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  112. Anderson, L. Federalism and Secessionism: Institutional Influences on Nationalist Politics in Québec. Natl. Ethn. Politics 2007, 13, 187–211. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  113. Hüglin, T.O. Treaty Federalism as a Model of Policy Making: Comparing Canada and the European Union: Treaty Federalism as a Model of Policy Making. Can. Public Adm. 2013, 56, 185–202. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  114. Mueller, S. Agreeing to Disagree: Federal Veto Powers in Switzerland. In Defensive Federalism: Protecting Territorial Minorities from the “Tyranny of the Majority”; Requejo, F., Sanjaume-Calvet, M., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2022; pp. 131–152. ISBN 978-1-003-29606-5. [Google Scholar]
  115. Benz, A.; Broschek, J. (Eds.) Federal Dynamics: Continuity, Change, and the Varieties of Federalism, 1st ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; ISBN 978-0-19-965299-0. [Google Scholar]
  116. Watts, R.L. Comparing Federal Systems. In Queen’s Policy Studies, 3rd ed.; McGill-Queen’s University Press: Montréal, QC, Canada, 2008; ISBN 978-1-55339-188-3. [Google Scholar]
  117. Tillin, L. United in Diversity? Asymmetry in Indian Federalism. Publius J. Fed. 2007, 37, 45–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  118. Colino, C. Constitutional Change without Constitutional Reform: Spanish Federalism and the Revision of Catalonia’s Statute of Autonomy. Publius J. Fed. 2008, 39, 262–288. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  119. Conversi, D. The Spanish Federalist Tradition and the 1978 Constitution. Telos 1998, 1998, 125–144. [Google Scholar]
  120. Deschouwer, K. The Politics of Belgium: Governing a Divided Society. In Comparative Government and Politics, 1st ed.; Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke, Hampshire, UK, 2009; ISBN 978-0-230-21815-4. [Google Scholar]
  121. Swenden, W.; Jans, M.T. ‘Will It Stay or Will It Go?’ Federalism and the Sustainability of Belgium. West Eur. Polit. 2006, 29, 877–894. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  122. Bednar, J. The Robust Federation: Principles of Design. In Political Economy of Institutions and Decisions, 1st ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009; ISBN 978-0-511-81944-5. [Google Scholar]
  123. Kincaid, J. From Cooperative to Coercive Federalism. Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. Soc. Sci. 1990, 509, 139–152. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  124. Ehrlich, C.E. Federalism, Regionalism, Nationalism: A Century of Catalan Political Thought and Its Implications for Scotland in Europe. Space Polity 1997, 1, 205–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  125. Marchildon, G. Postmodern Federalism and Sub-State Nationalism. In The Ashgate Research Companion to Federalism; Ward, A., Ward, L., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2009; pp. 441–455. ISBN 978-0-367-60302-1. [Google Scholar]
  126. Moreno, L. The Federalization of Spain, 1st ed.; Routledge Series in Federal Studies; Taylor and Francis: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2013; ISBN 978-0-7146-5138-5. [Google Scholar]
  127. Happaerts, S.; Schunz, S.; Bruyninckx, H. Federalism and Intergovernmental Relations: The Multi-Level Politics of Climate Change Policy in Belgium. J. Contemp. Eur. Stud. 2012, 20, 441–458. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  128. Kincaid, J. The Eclipse of Dual Federalism by One-Way Cooperative Federalism. Ariz. State Law J. 2017, 49, 1061–1089. [Google Scholar]
  129. Vandamme, T. From Federated Federalism to Converging Federalism? The Case of EU Subsidiarity Scrutiny in Spain and Belgium. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2012, 22, 515–531. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  130. León, S. How Do Citizens Attribute Responsibility in Multilevel States? Learning, Biases and Asymmetric Federalism. Evidence from Spain. Elect. Stud. 2012, 31, 120–130. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  131. Watts, R.L. Federal Idea and Its Contemporary Relevance, 1st ed.; Institute of Intergovernmental Relations, Queen’s University: Kingston, ON, Canada, 2006. [Google Scholar]
  132. Grodzins, M. The Federal System. In Goals for Americans: The Report of the President’s Commission on National Goals; Prentice-Hall: Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA, 1960; pp. 265–282. [Google Scholar]
  133. Watts, R.L. The American Constitution in Comparative Perspective: A Comparison of Federalism in the United States and Canada. J. Am. Hist. 1987, 74, 769–792. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  134. Wallis, J.J. The Political Economy of New Deal Fiscal Federalism. Econ. Inq. 1991, 29, 510–524. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  135. Tulane University Law School. The Evolution of Cooperative Federalism. Available online: https://online.law.tulane.edu/blog/the-evolution-of-cooperative-federalism (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  136. Elazar, D.J. Community Self-Government and the Crisis of American Politics. Ethics 1971, 81, 91–106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  137. Elazar, D.J. Cursed by Bigness or toward a Post-Technocratic Federalism. Publius J. Fed. 1973, 3, 239–298. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  138. Elazar, D.J. Contrasting Unitary and Federal Systems. Int. Polit. Sci. Rev. 1997, 18, 237–251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  139. Requejo, F. Federalism in Plurinational Societies: Rethinking the Ties between Catalonia, Spain, and the European Union. In Theories of Federalism: A Reader; Karmis, D., Norman, W., Eds.; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2005; pp. 311–320. ISBN 978-0-312-29581-3. [Google Scholar]
  140. Watts, R.L. Daniel J. Elazar: Comparative Federalism and Post-Statism. Publius J. Fed. 2000, 30, 155–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  141. Elazar, D.J. Federalism vs. Decentralization: The Drift from Authenticity. Publius J. Fed. 1976, 6, 9–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  142. Requejo, F. Decentralisation and Federal and Regional Asymmetries in Comparative Politics. In Federalism Beyond Federations: Asymmetry and Processes of Resymmetrization in Europe; Requejo Coll, F., Nagel, K.-J., Eds.; Federalism Studies; Routledge: London, UK, 2011; pp. 19–30. ISBN 978-1-138-26089-4. [Google Scholar]
  143. Conversi, D. The Smooth Transition: Spain’s 1978 Constitution and the Nationalities Question. Natl. Identities 2002, 4, 223–244. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  144. Lopez, C.E.D. The State of the Autonomic Process in Spain. Publius. J. Fed. 1981, 11, 193–218. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  145. Moreno, F. Ethnoterritorial Concurrence in Multinational Societies: The Spanish Communidades Autonomas. In Multinational Democracies; Gagnon, A.-G., James, T., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 201–221. ISBN 978-0-511-52157-7. [Google Scholar]
  146. Moreno, L. Federal Democracy in Plural Spain. In Federal Democracies; Burgess, M., Gagnon, A., Eds.; Routledge Series in Federal Studies; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2010; pp. 174–191. ISBN 978-1-138-96964-3. [Google Scholar]
  147. Basta, K. The State between Minority and Majority Nationalism: Decentralization, Symbolic Recognition, and Secessionist Crises in Spain and Canada. Publius J. Fed. 2018, 48, 51–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  148. Agranoff, R. Federal Evolution in Spain. Int. Polit. Sci. Rev. 1996, 17, 385–401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  149. Moreno, L.; Obydenkova, A. Federalization in Russia and Spain: The Puzzle of Reversible and Irreversible Outcomes. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2013, 23, 151–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  150. Simeon, R.; Conway, D.-P. Federalism and the Management of Conflict in Multinational Societies. In Multinational Democracies; Gagnon, A.-G., Tully, J., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 338–365. ISBN 978-0-521-80473-8. [Google Scholar]
  151. Caminal, M. Democracy, Federalism and Plurinational States. In Political Liberalism and Plurinational Democracies; Requejo, F., Caminal, M., Eds.; Nationalism and Ethnicity/Routledge Studies in Nationalism and Ethnicity; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2011; pp. 226–251. ISBN 978-1-138-88214-0. [Google Scholar]
  152. Leslie, P. Canada: The Supreme Court Sets Rules for the Secession of Quebec. Publius J. Fed. 1999, 29, 135–151. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  153. Krislov, S. American Federalism as American Exceptionalism. Publius J. Fed. 2001, 31, 9–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  154. Kong, L. Proudhon’s Critique of Nationalism in His Federalism Vision. Philosophies 2025, 10, 97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  155. Proudhon, P.-J. The Principle of Federation and the Need to Reconstitute the Party of Revolution. Full 31 Chapters Version, 1st ed.; Open Democracy & Stettbach Press: London, UK, 2025; ISBN 978-1-7393257-7-0. [Google Scholar]
  156. Proudhon, P.-J.; Kong, L. A Collection of Scattered Articles and Letters of Proudhon, 1st ed.; Karl-Marx Verlag: Potsdam, Germany, 2024; ISBN 978-3-9825536-2-7. [Google Scholar]
  157. McGarry, J.; O’Leary, B. Federation as a Method of Ethnic Conflict Regulation. Forum Fed. 2004, 1–30. Available online: https://www.forumfed.org/document/federation-as-a-method-of-ethnic-conflict-regulation/ (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  158. Lash, K.T. Federalism, Individual Rights and Judicial Engagement. Georg. Mason Law Rev. 2012, 19, 873–886. [Google Scholar]
  159. Norman, W.J. Negotiating Nationalism: Nation-Building, Federalism, and Secession in the Multinational State; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2006; ISBN 978-0-19-829335-4. [Google Scholar]
  160. Burgess, M.; Gagnon, A. (Eds.) Federal Democracies, 1st ed.; Routledge Series in Federal Studies; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2010; ISBN 978-1-138-96964-3. [Google Scholar]
  161. Requejo, F. Political Liberalism in Multinational States: The Legitimacy of Plural and Asymmetrical Federalism. In Multinational Democracies; Gagnon, A.-G., Tully, J., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 110–132. ISBN 978-0-511-52157-7. [Google Scholar]
  162. Requejo, F. Federalism and National Groups. Int. Soc. Sci. J. 2001, 53, 41–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  163. Karmis, D.; Norman, W. (Eds.) Theories of Federalism: A Reader, 1st ed.; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2005; ISBN 978-0-312-29581-3. [Google Scholar]
  164. Caluwaerts, D.; Reuchamps, M. Combining Federalism with Consociationalism: Is Belgian Consociational Federalism Digging Its Own Grave? Ethnopolitics 2015, 14, 277–295. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  165. Gagnon, A.-G. Multinational Federalism: Challenges, Shortcomings and Promises. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2021, 31, 99–114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  166. Trent, J.E. Canadian Federalism Under Pressure. In Globalization, Governance and Identity; Presses de l’Université de Montréal: Montréal, QC, Canada, 2000; pp. 233–265. ISBN 978-2-7606-1782-7. [Google Scholar]
  167. Jacobs, D.; Swyngedouw, M. Territorial and Non-Territorial Federalism in Belgium: Reform of the Brussels Capital Region, 2001. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2003, 13, 127–139. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  168. Bonthius, A. The Patriot War of 1837–1838: Locofocoism with a Gun? Labour/Le Trav. 2003, 52, 9–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  169. Laforest, G. The Meaning of Canadian Federalism in Québec: Critical Reflections. Rev. d’Estud. Auton. Fed. 2010, 11, 10–55. [Google Scholar]
  170. Paksy, M. Toward a Better Understanding of Peripheral Nation-Building Strategies: A Critical Comparison of the Austro-Hungarian Ausgleich and the Canadian British North America Act (1867). Int. J. Semiot. Law Rev. Int. Sémiot. Jurid. 2020, 33, 823–853. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  171. Rocher, F. Transformations in Contemporary Quebec Nationalism, 1960–2020: A Shift in the Sources of Collective Animosities. Nations Natl. 2023, 29, 280–294. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  172. Field, M.A. The Differing Federalisms of Canada and the United States. Law Contemp. Probl. 1992, 55, 107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  173. Montpetit, É.; Foucault, M. Canadian Federalism and Change in Policy Attention: A Comparison with the United Kingdom. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 2012, 45, 635–656. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  174. Palley, H.A. Canadian Federalism and the Canadian Health Care Program: A Comparison of Ontario and Quebec. Int. J. Health Serv. 1987, 17, 595–616. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  175. Frateur, J.; Bursens, P.; Meier, P. Exploring the Relationship between Federal Reform and the Representation of the People: The Case of the Belgian House of Representatives. Publius J. Fed. 2023, 53, 618–641. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  176. Swenden, W. Belgian Federalism: Basic Institutional Features and Potential as a Model for the European Union; Royal Institute of International Affairs: London, UK, 2003; pp. 1–21. [Google Scholar]
  177. Hooghe, L. Belgium: From Regionalism to Federalism. Reg. Polit. Policy 1993, 3, 44–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  178. Popelier, P.; Cantillon, B. Bipolar Federalism and the Social Welfare State: A Case for Shared Competences. Publius J. Fed. 2013, 43, 626–647. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  179. Beaufays, J. Belgium: A Dualist Political System? Publius J. Fed. 1988, 18, 63–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  180. Farrell, M.; Van Langenhove, L. Towards Cultural Autonomy in Belgium. In National-Cultural Autonomy and its Contemporary Critics; Nimni, E., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; pp. 189–201. ISBN 978-1-134-53413-5. [Google Scholar]
  181. Celis, K.; Meier, P. Convergence and Divergence: The Federalization of Belgian Equality Policies. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2011, 21, 55–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  182. Watts, R.L. Federalism, Federal Political Systems, and Federations. Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 1998, 1, 117–137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  183. Papillon, M. Adapting Federalism: Indigenous Multilevel Governance in Canada and the United States. Publius J. Fed. 2012, 42, 289–312. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  184. Reuchamps, M. Belgium: The Short Story of a Long History of (In)Stability? Available online: https://50shadesoffederalism.com/case-studies/belgium-short-story-long-history-instability/ (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  185. Gagnon, A.-G. The Moral Foundations of Asymmetrical Federalism: A Normative Exploration of the Case of Quebec and Canada. In Multinational Democracies; Gagnon, A.-G., James, T., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 319–337. ISBN 978-0-511-52157-7. [Google Scholar]
  186. Swenden, W. Asymmetric Federalism and Coalition-Making in Belgium. Publius J. Fed. 2002, 32, 67–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  187. Tarlton, C.D. Symmetry and Asymmetry as Elements of Federalism: A Theoretical Speculation. J. Polit. 1965, 27, 861–874. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  188. Lluch, J. Autonomism and Federalism. Publius J. Fed. 2012, 42, 134–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  189. Boatright, R.G. The Place of Québec in Canadian Interest Group Federalism. Am. Rev. Can. Stud. 2011, 41, 2–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  190. Caron, J.-F.; Laforest, G. Canada and Multinational Federalism: From the Spirit of 1982 to Stephen Harper’s Open Federalism. Natl. Ethn. Politics 2009, 15, 27–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  191. Redhead, M. Charles Taylor’s Deeply Diverse Response to Canadian Fragmentation: A Project Often Commented on but Seldom Explored. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 2003, 36, 61–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  192. Smiley, D. The Canadian Federation and the Challenge of Quebec Independence. Publius J. Fed. 1978, 8, 199–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  193. Choudhry, S. Citizenship and Federations: Some Preliminary Reflections. In The Federal Vision; Nicolaidis, K., Howse, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2001; pp. 377–402. ISBN 978-0-19-924500-0. [Google Scholar]
  194. Kostov, C. Canada-Quebec Immigration Agreements (1971–1991) and Their Impact on Federalism. Am. Rev. Can. Stud. 2008, 38, 91–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  195. Balthazar, L. Quebec and the Ideal of Federalism. Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. Soc. Sci. 1995, 538, 40–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  196. Simeon, R. Recent Trends in Federalism and Intergovernmental Relations in Canada: Lessons for the UK? Round Table 2000, 89, 231–243. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  197. Agranoff, R. Inter-governmental Politics and Policy: Building Federal Arrangements in Spain. Reg. Politics Policy 1993, 3, 1–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  198. Ciepley, D. Dispersed Constituency Democracy: Deterritorializing Representation to Reduce Ethnic Conflict. Polit. Soc. 2013, 41, 135–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  199. Kössler, K. Federalism and Non-Territorial Autonomy: Revisiting Two Interrelated Concepts. In Federalism and the Law of Diversity; Brill Nijhoff: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2025; pp. 27–51. ISBN 978-90-04-70776-4. [Google Scholar]
  200. Jedwab, J. Going Forward: The Evolution of Quebec’s English-Speaking Community; Office of the Commissioner of Official Languages: Ottawa, ON, Canada, 2004; ISBN 978-0-662-68534-0. [Google Scholar]
  201. McRoberts, K. Misconceiving Canada: The Struggle for National Unity; Oxford University Press: Toronto, ON, Canada; New York, NY, USA, 1997; ISBN 978-0-19-541233-8. [Google Scholar]
  202. Bourne, A. Europeanization and Secession: The Cases of Catalonia and Scotland. J. Ethnopolitics Minor. Issues Eur. 2014, 13, 94–120. [Google Scholar]
  203. Burgess, M. Territorial and Non-Territorial Identities: Multinational Federalism in Multinational Federation. In Proceedings of the Multinational Federalism in Perspective: A Viable Model? Montreal, QC, Canada, 25–27 September 2009; Université du Quebec à Montreal (UQAM): Montreal, QC, Canada, 2009; pp. 1–31. [Google Scholar]
  204. McGarry, J.; Moore, M. Karl Renner, Power Sharing and Non-Territorial Autonomy. In National-Cultural Autonomy and Its Contemporary Critics; Nimni, E., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; pp. 64–81. ISBN 978-1-134-53413-5. [Google Scholar]
  205. Nimni, E. The Conceptual Challenge of Non-Territorial Autonomy. In The Challenge of Non-Territorial Autonomy: Theory and Practice; Nimni, E., Osipov, A., Smith, D.J., Eds.; Nationalisms Across the Globe; Peter Lang AG, Internationaler Verlag der Wissenschaften: Bern, Switzerland, 2013; pp. 1–24. ISBN 978-3-0353-0511-1. [Google Scholar]
  206. Nimni, E.; Osipov, A.; Smith, D.J. (Eds.) The Challenge of Non-Territorial Autonomy: Theory and Practice, 1st ed.; Nationalisms across the Globe; Peter Lang AG, Internationaler Verlag der Wissenschaften: Bern, Switzerland, 2013; ISBN 978-3-0353-0511-1. [Google Scholar]
  207. Nimni, E.; Pavlović, A. Non-Territorial Autonomy as an Enrichment of Representative Democracy. Filoz. Druš./Philos. Soc. 2020, 31, 277–285. Available online: https://journal.ifdt.bg.ac.rs/index.php/fid/article/view/893/728 (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  208. Osipov, A. Mapping Non-Territorial Autonomy Arrangements. Ethnopolitics 2022, 21, 561–580. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  209. Alessi, N.; Trettel, M. Embracing Diversity: How Law and Federalism Shape Inclusive Societies. Eurac Res. 2025. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  210. Shikova, N. The Normative Base for Non-Territorial Autonomy—A Comparative Legal Overview. In Non-Territorial Autonomy as an Instrument for Effective Participation of Minorities; Vizi, B., Dobos, B., Shikova, N., Eds.; Centre for Social Sciences & University American College Skopje: Skopje, North Macedonia, 2021; pp. 25–38. ISBN 978-608-4607-53-3. [Google Scholar]
  211. Nimni, E. Minorities and the Limits of Liberal Democracy. In Minority Accommodation Through Territorial and Non-Territorial Autonomy; Malloy, T.H., Palermo, F., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015; pp. 57–82. ISBN 978-0-19-874666-9. [Google Scholar]
  212. Bauer, O. The Question of Nationalities and Social Democracy, 1st ed.; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2000; ISBN 978-0-8166-3265-7. [Google Scholar]
  213. Renner, K. State and Nation. In National Cultural Autonomy and its Contemporary Critics; Nimni, E., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; pp. 13–40. [Google Scholar]
  214. Keating, M. So Many Nations, So Few States: Accommodating Minority Nationalism in the Global Era. In Multinational Democracies; Gagnon, A.-G., James, T., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 39–64. ISBN 978-0-511-52157-7. [Google Scholar]
  215. Nimni, E. (Ed.) National-Cultural Autonomy and Its Contemporary Critics, 1st ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; ISBN 978-1-134-53413-5. [Google Scholar]
  216. de Villiers, B. Community Government for Minority Groups–Revisiting the Ideas of Bauer and Renner towards Developing a Model of Self-Government by Minority Groups under Public Law. Z. Ausl. Öffentl. Recht Völkerr. 2016, 76, 909–949. [Google Scholar]
  217. Papadopoulos, D.; Tsianos, V.S. After Citizenship: Autonomy of Migration, Organisational Ontology and Mobile Commons. Citizsh. Stud. 2013, 17, 178–196. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  218. Prina, F. Nonterritorial Autonomy and Minority (Dis)Empowerment: Past, Present, and Future. Natl. Pap. 2020, 48, 425–434. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  219. Bauböck, R. Territorial or Cultural Autonomy for National Minorities? In The Politics of Belonging: Nationalism, Liberalism, and Pluralism; Dieckhoff, A., Ed.; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2004; pp. 221–258. ISBN 978-0-7391-0825-3. [Google Scholar]
  220. Bauböck, R. Political Autonomy or Cultural Minority Rights? A Conceptual Critique of Renner’s Model. In National-Cultural Autonomy and Its Contemporary Critics; Nimni, E., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; pp. 97–111. ISBN 978-1-134-53413-5. [Google Scholar]
  221. Levey, G.B. National Cultural Autonomy and Liberal Nationalism. In National-Cultural Autonomy and Its Contemporary Critics; Nimni, E., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; pp. 128–140. ISBN 978-1-134-53413-5. [Google Scholar]
  222. Weller, M. Settling Self-Determination Conflicts: Recent Developments. Eur. J. Int. Law 2009, 20, 111–165. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  223. McGarry, J.; O’Leary, B. Consociational Theory, Northern Ireland’s Conflict, and Its Agreement 2. What Critics of Consociation Can Learn from Northern Ireland. Gov. Oppos. 2006, 41, 249–277. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  224. Lijphart, A. Consociation and Federation: Conceptual and Empirical Links. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 1979, 12, 499–516. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  225. Duchacek, I.D. Consociational Cradle of Federalism. Publius J. Fed. 1985, 15, 35–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  226. Swenden, W. What—If Anything—Can the European Union Learn from Belgian Federalism and Vice Versa? Reg. Fed. Stud. 2005, 15, 187–204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  227. Hulsey, J. Electoral Accountability in Bosnia and Herzegovina under the Dayton Framework Agreement. Int. Peacekeep. 2015, 22, 511–525. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  228. Younis, N. Set up to Fail: Consociational Political Structures in Post-War Iraq, 2003–2010. Contemp. Arab Aff. 2011, 4, 1–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  229. Bogaards, M. Formal and Informal Consociational Institutions: A Comparison of the National Pact and the Taif Agreement in Lebanon. Natl. Ethn. Polit. 2019, 25, 27–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  230. Jarstad, A.K. Power Sharing: Former Enemies in Joint Government. In From War to Democracy; Jarstad, A.K., Sisk, T.D., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. 105–133. ISBN 978-0-521-71327-6. [Google Scholar]
  231. Wolff, S. Post-Conflict State Building: The Debate on Institutional Choice. Third World Q. 2011, 32, 1777–1802. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  232. Kemp, R.L. (Ed.) How American Governments Work: A Handbook of City, County, Regional, State, and Federal Operations; McFarland: Jefferson, NC, USA, 2002; ISBN 978-0-7864-1299-0. [Google Scholar]
  233. Aroney, N. The Formation and Amendment of Federal Constitutions in a Westminster-Derived Context. Int. J. Const. Law 2018, 16, 17–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  234. Gamkhar, S.; Vickers, J. Comparing Federations: Lessons from Comparing Canada and the United States. Publius J. Fed. 2010, 40, 351–356. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  235. Radin, B.A.; Boase, J.P. Federalism, Political Structure, and Public Policy in the United States and Canada. J. Comp. Policy Anal. 2000, 2, 65–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  236. Turgeon, L.; Wallner, J. Adaptability and Change in Federations: Centralization, Political Parties, and Taxation Authority in Australia and Canada. In The Global Promise of Federalism; Skogstad, G., Cameron, D., Papillon, M., Banting, K., Eds.; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada, 2013; ISBN 978-1-4426-1919-7. [Google Scholar]
  237. Malloy, J. High Discipline, Low Cohesion? The Uncertain Patterns of Canadian Parliamentary Party Groups. J. Legis. Stud. 2003, 9, 116–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  238. Choudhry, S. Can Federalism Save India’s Constitutional Democracy? Jus Cogens 2022, 4, 69–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  239. Filippov, M.; Švecova, O.V.; Ordeshook, P.C. Designing Federalism: A Theory of Self-Sustainable Federal Institutions; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004; ISBN 978-0-511-61087-5. [Google Scholar]
  240. Adeney, K. Federalism and Ethnic Conflict Regulation in India and Pakistan; Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke, UK, 2007; ISBN 978-1-4039-7186-9. [Google Scholar]
  241. Abbey, R.; Taylor, C. Communitarianism, Taylor-Made: An Interview with Charles Taylor. Aust. Quart. 1996, 68, 1–10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  242. Diamond, L. Why Decentralize Power in A Democracy? Available online: https://diamond-democracy.stanford.edu/speaking/speeches/why-decentralize-power-democracy (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  243. Gushchina, K.; Kaiser, A. Multilevel Governance and Women’s Legislative Representation. Eur. J. Polit. Res. 2021, 60, 934–953. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  244. Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations. Citizen Participation in the American Federal System; Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations: Washington, DC, USA, 1979; pp. 1–35. [Google Scholar]
  245. Mooney, C.Z. State Politics and Policy Quarterly and the Study of State Politics: The Editor’s Introduction. State Polit. Policy Q. 2001, 1, 1–4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  246. Oliver, J.E. City Size and Civic Involvement in Metropolitan America. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 2000, 94, 361–373. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  247. Pehr, A. Does Federalism Foster Happiness? Reviewing Political Decentralization and Citizens’ Happiness. Available online: https://50shadesoffederalism.com/theory/does-federalism-foster-happiness-reviewing-political-decentralization-and-citizens-happiness/ (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  248. Amy, D.J. The Democratic Drawbacks of Federalism. Available online: https://secondratedemocracy.com/the-drawbacks-of-federalism/ (accessed on 20 July 2025).
  249. Napolio, N.G.; Peterson, J.C. Their Boot in Our Face No Longer? Administrative Sectionalism and Resistance to Federal Authority in the U.S. South. State Polit. Policy Q. 2019, 19, 101–122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  250. Grumbach, J.M. Laboratories of Democratic Backsliding. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 2023, 117, 967–984. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  251. Benz, A.; Sonnicksen, J. Patterns of Federal Democracy: Tensions, Friction, or Balance between Two Government Dimensions. Eur. Polit. Sci. Rev. 2017, 9, 3–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  252. Kaufman, R.R.; Kelemen, R.D.; Kolcak, B. Federalism and Democratic Backsliding in Comparative Perspective. Perspect. Polit. 2025, 23, 15–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  253. Busygina, I.; Filippov, M. Non-Democratic Federalism and Decentralization in Post-Soviet States, 1st ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2023; ISBN 978-1-003-26750-8. [Google Scholar]
  254. Adeney, K.; Boni, F. Federalism and Regime Change: De/Centralization in Pakistan—1956–2020. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2023, 33, 725–753. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  255. Dardanelli, P.; Kincaid, J.; Adeney, K.; Moscovich, L.; Olmeda, J.C.; Schlegel, R.; Suberu, R.; Boni, F.; Lacroix Eussler, S. Authoritarianism, Democracy and de/Centralization in Federations: What Connections? Reg. Fed. Stud. 2023, 33, 577–606. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  256. Sorens, J. The Institutions of Fiscal Federalism. Publius J. Fed. 2011, 41, 207–231. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  257. Bournakis, I. The Politics of Fiscal Federalism: Neoliberalism versus Social Democracy in Multilevel Governance: By Adam Harmes, McGill-Queen’s University Press, Montreal, 2019. 328 Pp., US$32.95 (Pbk), ISBN 9780773556751. https://www.mqup.ca/politics-of-fiscal-federalism--the-products-9780773556751.php. Reg. Stud. 2020, 54, 733–735. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  258. Salazar-Morales, D.A.; Hallerberg, M. The Role of Fiscal Coordination and Partisanship in the Spanish Fiscal Federalist System. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2022, 32, 617–639. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  259. Xu, C. The Fundamental Institutions of China’s Reforms and Development. J. Econ. Lit. 2011, 49, 1076–1151. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  260. Lago-Peñas, S.; Fernández-Leiceaga, X.; Vaquero-García, A. Spanish Fiscal Decentralization: A Successful (but Still Unfinished) Process. Environ. Plan. C Politics Space 2017, 35, 1509–1525. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  261. Bird, R.M.; Smart, M. Intergovernmental Fiscal Transfers: International Lessons for Developing Countries. World Dev. 2002, 30, 899–912. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  262. Keen, M.J.; Kotsogiannis, C. Does Federalism Lead to Excessively High Taxes? Am. Econ. Rev. 2002, 92, 363–370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  263. Eyraud, L.; Lusinyan, L. Vertical Fiscal Imbalances and Fiscal Performance in Advanced Economies. J. Monet. Econ. 2013, 60, 571–587. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  264. Weingast, B.R. Second Generation Fiscal Federalism: The Implications of Fiscal Incentives. J. Urban Econ. 2009, 65, 279–293. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  265. Baskaran, T. Soft Budget Constraints and Strategic Interactions in Subnational Borrowing: Evidence from the German States, 1975–2005. J. Urban Econ. 2012, 71, 114–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  266. Rodden, J. Reviving Leviathan: Fiscal Federalism and the Growth of Government. Int. Organ. 2003, 57, 695–729. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  267. Argimón, I.; Cos, P.H.D. Fiscal Rules and Federalism as Determinants of Budget Performance: An Empirical Investigation for the Spanish Case. Public Financ. Rev. 2012, 40, 30–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  268. Valdesalici, A. Measuring Fiscal Responsibility: From “Law in Books” to “Law in Action.” In The Value of Comparative Federalism: The Legacy of Ronald L. Watts; Steytler, N.C., Arora, B., Saxena, R., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2021; pp. 123–144. ISBN 978-0-367-77560-5. [Google Scholar]
  269. Dahlby, B.; Warren, N. Fiscal Incentive Effects of the Australian Equalisation System. Econ. Rec. 2003, 79, 434–445. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  270. Rodden, J. Hamilton’s Paradox: The Promise and Peril of Fiscal Federalism; Cambridge Studies in Comparative Politics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2006; ISBN 978-0-511-61607-5. [Google Scholar]
  271. Asatryan, Z.; Feld, L.P. Revisiting the Link between Growth and Federalism: A Bayesian Model Averaging Approach. J. Comp. Econ. 2015, 43, 772–781. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  272. Stegarescu, D. Public Sector Decentralisation: Measurement Concepts and Recent International Trends*. Fisc. Stud. 2005, 26, 301–333. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  273. Heinemann, F.; Osterloh, S.; Kalb, A. Sovereign Risk Premia: The Link between Fiscal Rules and Stability Culture. J. Int. Money Financ. 2014, 41, 110–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  274. Klyza, C.M.; Sousa, D.J. American Environmental Policy: Beyond Gridlock. In American and Comparative Environmental Policy; Updated and Expanded Edition; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2013; ISBN 978-0-262-52504-6. [Google Scholar]
  275. Rabe, B.G. Greenhouse Governance: Addressing Climate Change in America, 1st ed.; Brookings Institution Press: Washington, DC, USA, 2010; ISBN 978-0-8157-0331-0. [Google Scholar]
  276. Green, A.J. Public Participation, Federalism and Environmental Law. Buffalo Environ. Law J. 1999, 6, 169–213. [Google Scholar]
  277. Carlson, A.E. Iterative Federalism and Climate Change. Northwestern Univ. Law Rev. 2009, 103, 1097–1161. [Google Scholar]
  278. Meadowcroft, J. Canadian Federalism and the Political Economy of Energy and the Environment. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 2021, 54, 977–979. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  279. Oates, W.E. A Reconsideration of Environmental Federalism. In Recent Advances in Environmental Economics; List, J.A., De Zeeuw, A., Eds.; Edward Elgar Publishing: Cheltenham, UK, 2002; ISBN 978-1-84376-730-5. [Google Scholar]
  280. Börzel, T.A.; Risse, T. Governance without a State: Can It Work?: Governance without a State. Regul. Gov. 2010, 4, 113–134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  281. Jordan, A.J. (Ed.) Environmental Policy in Europe: The Europeanization of National Environmental Policy; Routledge Research in Environmental Politics; Transferred to Digital Print; Routledge: London, UK, 2005; ISBN 978-0-415-33941-4. [Google Scholar]
  282. Greer, S.L.; Jacobson, P.D. Health Care Reform and Federalism. J. Health Polit. Policy Law 2010, 35, 203–226. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  283. Béland, D.; Lecours, A. Federalism, Nationalism and Social Policy Decentralization in Canada and Belgium. Reg. Fed. Stud. 2007, 17, 405–419. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  284. Banting, K. Canada: Nation-Building in a Federal Welfare State. In Federalism and the Welfare State; Obinger, H., Leibfried, S., Castles, F.G., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2005; pp. 89–137. ISBN 978-0-521-84738-4. [Google Scholar]
  285. Grogan, C.M.; Park, S. (Ethan). The Racial Divide in State Medicaid Expansions. J. Health Polit. Policy Law 2017, 42, 539–572. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  286. Oberlander, J. Long Time Coming: Why Health Reform Finally Passed. Health Aff. 2010, 29, 1112–1116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  287. Béland, D.; Weaver, R.K. Federalism and the Politics of the Canada and Quebec Pension Plans. J. Int. Comp. Soc. Policy 2019, 35, 25–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  288. Lecours, A. Dynamic de/Centralization in Canada, 1867–2010. Publius J. Fed. 2019, 49, 57–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  289. Van den Berg, A.; Raïq, H.; Proulx, C.; Plante, C.; Faustmann, S. Combating Poverty: Quebec’s Pursuit of a Distinctive Welfare State. In Studies in Comparative Political Economy and Public Policy; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada; Buffalo, NY, USA; London, UK, 2017; ISBN 978-1-4875-0156-3. [Google Scholar]
  290. Blank, R.H.; Burau, V.D.; Kuhlmann, E. Comparative Health Policy, 5th ed.; Macmillan Education, Palgrave: London, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-1-137-54495-7. [Google Scholar]
  291. Obinger, H.; Castles, F.G.; Leibfried, S. Federalism and the Welfare State: New World and European Experiences, 1st ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2005; ISBN 978-0-521-84738-4. [Google Scholar]
  292. Béland, D.; Lecours, A.; Paquet, M.; Tombe, T. A Critical Juncture in Fiscal Federalism? Canada’s Response to COVID-19. Can. J. Polit. Sci. 2020, 53, 239–243. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  293. Swagel, P.; Kaufman, M.D.; Swagel, P.; Dunaway, S. Regional Convergence and the Role of Federal Transfers in Canada; IMF Working Papers; International Monetary Fund: Washington, DC, USA, 2003; ISBN 978-1-4518-5204-2. [Google Scholar]
  294. Sparer, M.S. Federalism and the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010: The Founding Fathers Would Not Be Surprised. J. Health Polit. Policy Law 2011, 36, 461–468. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  295. Greer, S.L.; King, E.J.; Da Fonseca, E.M.; Peralta-Santos, A. The Comparative Politics of COVID-19: The Need to Understand Government Responses. Glob. Public Health 2020, 15, 1413–1416. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Table 1. Key Terms and Brief Definitions (For Quick Reference).
Table 1. Key Terms and Brief Definitions (For Quick Reference).
TermBrief DefinitionNotes/Examples
Unitary SystemA system where the central government holds ultimate authority. The powers of regional or local governments are delegated by the central government and can be revoked.China, France, Japan
FederalismA constitutional multi-level government system. Within the same national framework, two or more levels of government are constitutionally recognized and possess their own powers (self-rule + shared rule).Defining federalism itself is a perennial subject of federalism studies, so it is almost impossible to give a short definition that satisfies all. Here, we temporarily adopt Elazar’s [2] widely accepted definition of federalism
ConfederationA loose alliance of sovereign states, with weak central power and high sovereignty retained by member states.Early or quasi confederations: Achaean League, Hanseatic League, Iroquois Confederacy. Modern: The United States under the Articles of Confederation
Coming-Together Federal ModelThe constituent units jointly create a federal system, not by decentralization from a single center.The establishment of Canada, the United States, and Switzerland
Holding-Together Federal ModelThe center proactively grants powers to subnational units to maintain the integrity of a diverse society.The 1978 Spanish Constitution
Dual FederalismClear and relatively independent division of responsibilities between levels of government.The United States in its Founding
Cooperative FederalismOverlapping functions and frequent collaboration between levels of government.The United States since the New Deal
Decentralization The process of devolving power from the center to lower-level governments.The 1978 Spanish Constitution
Non-centralizationA federal system jointly created by the constituent units; a terms also used to describe the current federal state being centerless.Switzerland
Monist FederalismEmphasizes the federal entity as a single national sovereign community.The United States
Multinational FederalismFederalism designed to accommodate different ethnic or linguistic groups.Belgium, India
Asymmetrical FederalismDifferent units have different arrangements in terms of autonomy.Quebec in Canada, Catalonia in Spain
Non-Territorial Autonomy (NTA)Group autonomy arrangements not based on territory. Belgian language communities
ConsociationalismElite negotiation and power-sharing governance model to stabilize divided societies.Belgium, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Lebanon
Presidential FederalismThe executive head (president) is elected independently of the legislature. Federal power is institutionally separated among different branches at the center.United States, Brazil, Mexico
Parliamentary FederalismExecutive power derives from a parliamentary majority. Inter-level coordination is mainly achieved through mechanisms between parties and cabinets.Canada, Australia, India
Democratic FederalismFederalism and democracy complement each other, expanding citizen participation and accountability through local autonomy.Australia, Canada, Germany, Switzerland, and the United States
Authoritarian Federalism/Facade FederalismNominal adoption of a federal constitution, but in reality highly centralized. “Federal” is more of a decorative arrangement.Nigeria under military rule
Fiscal FederalismStudies the allocation and effects of fiscal functions (taxation, transfer payments, expenditure responsibilities) among multi-level governments.Related to regional inequality and transfer payment mechanisms
Environmental FederalismStudies the responsibilities and outcomes of environmental governance among multi-level governments.The U.S. Clean Air Act grants states the right to set standards
Health & Welfare FederalismAnalyzes how health and social welfare issues are implemented between the federal and local levels.Canadian health care system; U.S. Medicaid state differences
Table 2. A Comparative Overview of Typical Monist Federalism (United States) and Multinational Federalism (Canada, Belgium).
Table 2. A Comparative Overview of Typical Monist Federalism (United States) and Multinational Federalism (Canada, Belgium).
FeatureUnited States
(Mono-National/Monist Federalism)
Canada (Bi-/Multinational Federalism)Belgium (Multinational
Federalism)
Formation TypeComing-Together FederalismComing-Together FederalismHolding-Together Federalism
IdentitySingle nation/unified citizen body (Mononational Demos) [157]Recognition of multiple nations/identities (Multiple Demoi/Identities) [166]Recognition of multiple nations/identities (Multiple Demoi/Identities) [175]
Power-AllocationEnumerated federal powers, residual powers to states; judicial interpretation tends to expand federal powersEnumerated federal powers + residual powers, enumerated provincial powers; judicial interpretation tends to expand provincial powersResidual powers to federation; extensive powers devolved through successive rounds of reform [176]
Diversity StrategyTerritorial neutrality, emphasis on individual rights; adaptation via shift from “dual” to “cooperative” modelasymmetrical federalism (Quebec’s special status); non-territorial autonomy; shared rule and self-ruleasymmetrical federalism; consociationalism; non-territorial autonomy; gradual federalization
Concept of CitizenshipIndividual rights primacy, emphasis on a single national citizenshipBalance of individual and group rights; recognition of dual loyalties [166]Balance of individual and group rights; coexistence of community identities alongside national identity [175]
Main ChallengesGovernmental gridlock, regional inequality, special-interest influence, risks of democratic erosionQuebec separatism, inter-regional imbalances, intensified nationalismEthno-linguistic conflict, cabinet-formation difficulties, challenges to national unity [184]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Kong, L. Federalism: A Comprehensive Review of Its Evolution, Typologies, and Contemporary Issues. Encyclopedia 2025, 5, 156. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5040156

AMA Style

Kong L. Federalism: A Comprehensive Review of Its Evolution, Typologies, and Contemporary Issues. Encyclopedia. 2025; 5(4):156. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5040156

Chicago/Turabian Style

Kong, Lingkai. 2025. "Federalism: A Comprehensive Review of Its Evolution, Typologies, and Contemporary Issues" Encyclopedia 5, no. 4: 156. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5040156

APA Style

Kong, L. (2025). Federalism: A Comprehensive Review of Its Evolution, Typologies, and Contemporary Issues. Encyclopedia, 5(4), 156. https://doi.org/10.3390/encyclopedia5040156

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop