The Non-Arbitrary Link between Feeling and Value: A Psychosemantic Challenge for the Perceptual Theory of Emotion
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Need for an Emotional Psychosemantics
3. The Problem of Naturalness for Prinz’s Psychosemantics
3.1. Prinz’s Psychosemantics for Emotion
Thus, emotions detect values by tracking changes in the body. The bodily changes in question, of course, are not simple processes like the mere racing of the heart. Since such simple processes would fail to individuate emotion types, the idea is rather that each emotion has a unique and therefore suitably complex configuration of bodily symptoms. Each emotion has a somatic signature capable of distinguishing it from other emotions.16 It is this somatic signature that co-varies with the relevant value, enabling us to perceive it.Each emotion is both an internal body monitor and a detector of dangers, threats, losses, or other matters of concern. Emotions are gut reactions; they use our bodies to tell us how we are faring in the world. [6] (p. 70)
3.2. The Problem: Emotions as Arbitrary Beeps of Value
As this analogy makes explicit, the link between police radars and the beeping of fuzz busters is totally arbitrary. The beeps could just as well have represented anything else, even the absence of police radar, as there is no deep or inherent linkage between police radar and the sound of beeping. But is that how emotions are related to the values they represent? This seems to me severely mistaken. Emotions are not arbitrary beeps of value that could have just as well represented anything else.which people place in their cars to determine when they are driving in zones monitored by police radars. A beep emitted from a fuzz buster represents the presence of a police radar. But the beep itself is utterly lacking in structure. It cannot be analyzed into meaningful subbeeps. … [T]he beep emitted by a fuzz buster does not describe what it represents. It represents police radars because it is reliably caused by police radars, and it is set up for that purpose. Likewise, emotions can represent [values] without describing them. [6] (p. 65)
4. A Tempting Explanation Met with a Thought Experiment
4.1. The Tempting Explanation: An Appeal to Emotional Motivation18
4.2. The Thought Experiment: The Strange Case of the Emotionally Inverted Creature
5. Objections to the Thought-Experiment
5.1. Are Feelings Constitutively Linked to Emotional Motivation?
The strong dissociability thesis. The hedonic valence of an emotion cannot possibly be dissociated from its felt motivational impact. The two elements are constitutively linked.22
5.2. Am I Begging the Question against Reductive Theories of Consciousness?
5.3. Does the Naturalness Datum Hold for All Emotions?
6. The Challenge for the Perceptual Theory
6.1. Not So Fast!
6.2. The Real Challenge
6.3. Stating the Argument
- The perceptual theory is true.
- 2.
- If the perceptual theory is true, then the perceptual theory explains the naturalness datum.
- 3.
- The perceptual theory explains the naturalness datum.
- 4.
- If the perceptual theory explains the naturalness datum, then either it does so by appealing to content-relevant features, or it does so by appealing to content-irrelevant features of emotion.
- 5.
- The perceptual theory explains the naturalness datum either by appealing to content-relevant features, or by appealing to content-irrelevant features of emotion
- 6.
- The perceptual theory cannot explain the naturalness datum by appealing to content-irrelevant features.
- 7.
- The perceptual theory explains the naturalness datum by appealing to content-relevant features.
- 8.
- If the perceptual theory is true, then the perceptual theory explains the naturalness datum by appealing to content-relevant features.
- 9.
- The perceptual theory cannot explain the naturalness datum by appealing to content-relevant features.
- 10.
- The perceptual theory is false.
7. The Promise of Iconicity
8. Prinz vs. Prinz
One gets the basic sense of the objection here. This passage expresses a concern about emotions being “arbitrary symbols” with no deeper connection to their evaluative contents. At the risk of nitpicking, however, I think one thing about this passage needs straightening out. This concern about arbitrariness should be kept distinct from the observation that we “could easily represent the same content without the bodily change” (ibid). For this is entirely a modal point. As such, it poses no serious objection to Prinz [6]. It is, after all, plainly true that we “could easily represent the same content without the bodily change.” We do so whenever we believe the relevant content.Informational semantics claims that content is determined by covariation between mental states and the world. But, on that approach, there is nothing about a given mental state that determines what it refers to—mental states are no more than arbitrary symbols…. Therefore it is irrelevant that emotional components are realized by bodily states and bodily perceptions…. One could easily represent the same content without the bodily change, since the theory appeals to their information-processing characteristics and not their bodily character. [56] (p. 113)
9. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Notable defenses of the perpetual theory (or something close to it) can be found in Charland [1], de Sousa [2], Döring [3], Greenspan [4], Milona [5], Prinz [6], Roberts [7], and Tappolet [8]. See also Rossi [9], who extends the perceptual theory to include moods. Obviously, a crucial question here is what sorts of values emotions represent, and unsurprisingly, theorists diverge on this point (for discussion, see Milona [10]). I note, moreover, that in principle one could hold that emotions are perceptual states that represent, not values, but bodily states (Damasio [11]; James [12]; Lange [13]). An adjacent body of work endorses a view like the perceptual theory of emotion but not under that label, being guided chiefly by epistemological or metaethical concerns rather than an interest in emotions as such. Under this heading, I would include, but not exhaustively, Cuneo [14], Dancy [15], Johnston [16], McDowell [17,18], Oddie [19], Roberts [20], Roberts and Wood [21], Tolhurst [22], Wedgwood [23], Ch. 10, Wiggins [24], Ch. 5, and Zagzebski [25]. |
2 | See Ballard [26] for more on this line of thought. |
3 | This argument—as found, for example, in Roberts [27], Deigh [28], and D’Arms and Jacobson [29]—was one of the earliest motivations for the perceptual theory as an alternative to the judgment theory, which identifies emotions with evaluative beliefs or judgments (Foot [30], Kenny [31], Nussbaum [32], and Solomon [33]). |
4 | See, for instance, Döring [34], Milona [35], Montague [36], Ch. 9, and Pelser [37]. For challenges to this epistemic thesis, see Brady [38], Ch. 3, Brogaard and Chudnoff [39], and Vanello [40]. Note as well that emotions might be thought to provide other epistemic benefits aside from perceptual justification (for a sense of the options, see Ballard [41] and McMartin and Pickavance [42]). |
5 | But I note that Siegel [43] argues perception has its own “epistemic charge”, and can thus be assessed as rational. |
6 | Maguire [44] argues there are no reasons for affective states, only fittingness conditions. I think he has shown that a fitting emotion is not the same thing as an emotion for which there are reasons. It does not follow there are no reasons for emotions. |
7 | An influential presentation of this challenge can be found in Brady [38], Ch. 3, with significant antecedents in Helm [45] and Greenspan [4]. Some important responses to this challenge include Benbaji [46], Cowan [47], Döring [48], Grzankowski [49], Helm [50], Majeed [51], Milona and Naar [52], Vance [53], Szigeti [54], Tappolet [8], Ch. 1, and Yip [55]. |
8 | See Shargel and Prinz [56]. |
9 | But Shargel [57] raises complications for the simple picture I am suggesting here. |
10 | |
11 | The literature here is enormous, but a good place to start would be the essays in Stich and Warfield [60]. |
12 | |
13 | This point is argued forcefully in Schroeter et al. [62]. Thanks to an anonymous referee for bringing this paper to my attention. |
14 | See especially Fodor [65]. |
15 | The idea that values are causally inefficacious raises deep issues in the present context. In particular, it is often thought that for S to perceive O, O must stand a certain causal relation to S. If so, and if values are inefficacious, then we never perceive values, and emotions would not literally be perceptions of value. Further, there would arise a mystery as to how our emotions are reliably tracking values. Now, while there are responses to these difficulties (e.g., Audi [66]), notice that presently I am not adopting the view that values are inefficacious; I am simply not excluding it by terminological fiat. |
16 | |
17 | Deonna and Teroni add that “it is not intelligible to say that amusement makes the danger in the situation manifest to us” [70] (p. 86). However, we should keep this epistemic claim—that only certain emotional experiences can make certain values manifest to us—distinct from the claim that only certain emotional experiences are naturally well-suited at making those values manifest to us. |
18 | This section especially benefited from insightful feedback from Robert Cowan. |
19 | Plenty of empirical work documents the way a typical emotional experience prepares us to act in appropriate ways with respect to the emotion object. See, for example, Bradley et al. [73], Lang and Bradley [74], LeDoux [75], Pourtois et al. [76], or Susskind et al. [77]. I should note, however, that the precise shape motivation takes appears to be highly goal-dependent (Calbi et al. [78]; Mancini et al. [79]; Mirabella et al. [80]; and Moors and Fischer [81]). Thanks to an anonymous referee for bringing this work to my attention. |
20 | See Prinz [6] (p. 66). |
21 | |
22 | |
23 | See Bain [85] (p. 167). |
24 | Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this line of thought. |
25 | |
26 | Tappolet [8] (pp. 64–66). |
27 | If Kendall Walton [89] is correct, and our pity for Anna Karanina is not real pity but rather a sort of quasi-pity in a game of make-believe, then I have not here presented a case where an emotion’s hedonic valence comes apart from its motivational impact. But that does not much matter. Even if Walton is correct, I have still presented a case of a mental state with a hedonic valence just like that of a certain emotion’s but which lacks that emotion’s motivational impact. That would show that this hedonic valence does not require that motivational impact. As long as those things come apart, my emotional inversion cases will be admissible. |
28 | Corns [90] (pp. 247–248). |
29 | Relatedly, I might also mention the empirical evidence discussed by Corns and Cowan [91] that “liking” and “wanting”—enjoying a certain stimulus, and being motivated to consume or engage with it—come apart at the subpersonal level, being underwritten by independent systems. See, for instance, Barbano et al. [92], Pool et al. [93], Robinson and Berridge [94], or Robinson et al. [95]. |
30 | Some theorists, especially Adolfs and Andler [96], describe their account of emotion as functionalist but do not intend to reduce the phenomenal character of an emotion to its functional role, only to argue that the functional role of emotion is the best way to distinguish it from other mental sates. A functionalist in this sense need take no issue with my emotional inversion cases. |
31 | See, for instance, Chalmers [97] and Rey [98], who appeal to modes of presentation in addition to representational content. Put in their parlance, the question raised by the emotionally inverted creatures would be, Why is it so unnatural for disgust feelings to be the mode of presentation for the beautiful? |
32 | |
33 | Cf. Camp [102]. |
34 | Cf. Giardino and Greenberg [103]. |
35 | |
36 | |
37 | An intriguing version of this idea can be found in Nozick [112], Ch. 10. Because this proposal enlists phenomenal features of emotion to play a content-determining role, this proposal should be understood against the backdrop of the recent movement toward phenomenal intentionality (e.g., Horgan and Tienson [113], Kriegel [114], Loar [115], and Mendelovici [116]). However, since the idea I have sketched here makes no pretense to explaining all content as determined by phenomenology, my proposal is fairly modest by comparison. |
38 | I say that in a spirit of charity, but I have to admit, at times Shargel and Prinz seem to double down on the modal language. Against Griffiths and Scarantino [117], who rely on the notion of affordacnes in Gibson [118], Shargel and Prinz complain that their theory makes it “possible to represent the affordance without any bodily change” [56] (p. 116). But surely it is possible. Can we not form purely cognitive beliefs about such affordances? For my part, it is hard to see what the force of this modal objection is supposed to be. |
References
- Charland, L.C. Reconciling Cognitive and Perceptual Theories of Emotion: A Representational Proposal. Philos. Sci. 1997, 64, 555–579. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- de Sousa, R.d.d. The Rationality of Emotion; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Döring, S.A. Explaining Action by Emotion. Philos. Q. 2003, 53, 214–230. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Greenspan, P.S. Emotions and Reasons: An Enquiry into Emotional Justification; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Milona, M. Taking the Perceptual Analogy Seriously. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2016, 19, 897–915. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prinz, J.J. Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of the Emotions; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Roberts, R. Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Tappolet, C. Emotions, Value, and Agency; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Rossi, M. A Perceptual Theory of Moods. Synthese 2019, 198, 7119–7147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M. What ‘Values’ Are Emotions about? In A Tribute to Ronald de Sousa; Deonna, J., Tappolet, C., Teroni, F., Eds.; 2022; Available online: https://www.unige.ch/cisa/related-sites/ronald-de-sousa/assets/pdf/Milona_Paper.pdf (accessed on 24 October 2023).
- Damasio, A.R. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain; G. P. Putnam’s Sons: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- James, W. What Is an Emotion? Mind 1884, 9, 188–205. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lange, C. Om Sindsbevaegelser: Et Psyko-Fysiologisk Studie; Jacob Lunds: Copenhagen, Denmark, 1885. [Google Scholar]
- Cuneo, T. Signs of Value: Reid on the Evidential Role of Feelings in Moral Judgement. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2006, 14, 69–91. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dancy, J. Intuition and Emotion. Ethics 2014, 124, 787–812. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Johnston, M. The Authority of Affect. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2001, 63, 181–214. [Google Scholar]
- McDowell, J. Virtue and Reason. Monist 1979, 62, 331–350. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McDowell, J. Values and Secondary Qualities. In Morality and Objectivity; Honderich, T., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Oddie, G. Value, Reality, and Desire; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Roberts, R.C. Emotions in the Moral Life; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Roberts, R.C.; Wood, W.J. Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Tolhurst, W.E. On the Epistemic Value of Moral Experience. South. J. Philos. 1991, 29, 67–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wedgwood, R. The Nature of Normativity; Oxford University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Wiggins, D. Needs, Values, Truth: Essays in the Philosophy of Value; Oxford University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Zagzebski, L. Emotion and Moral Judgment. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2003, 66, 104–124. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ballard, B.S. Content and the Fittingness of Emotion. Philos. Q. 2021, 71, 845–863. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roberts, R.C. What an Emotion Is: A Sketch. Philos. Rev. 1988, 97, 183–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Deigh, J. Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions. Ethics 1994, 104, 824–854. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- D’Arms, J.; Jacobson, D. VIII. The Significance of Recalcitrant Emotion (or, Anti-Quasijudgmentalism). R. Inst. Philos. Suppl. 2003, 52, 127–145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Foot, P. Moral Beliefs. Proc. Aristot. Soc. 1959, 59, 83–104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kenny, A. Action, Emotion and Will; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaum, M.C. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Solomon, R.C. The Passions; Anchor Books: New York, NY, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Döring, S. The Logic of Emotional Experience: Noninferentiality and the Problem of Conflict without Contradiction. Emot. Rev. 2009, 1, 240–247. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M. On the Epistemological Significance of Value Perception. In Evaluative Perception; Bergvqist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; pp. 200–218. [Google Scholar]
- Montague, M. The Given: Experience and Its Content; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Pelser, A.C. Emotion, Evaluative Perception, and Epistemic Justification. In Emotion and Value; Cain, T., Roeser, S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014; pp. 107–123. [Google Scholar]
- Brady, M.S. Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Brogaard, B.; Chudnoff, E. Against Emotional Dogmatism. Philos. Issues 2016, 26, 59–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vanello, D. Affect, Perceptual Experience, and Disclosure. Philos. Stud. 2018, 175, 2125–2144. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ballard, B.S. The Epistemic Significance of Emotional Experience. Emot. Rev. 2021, 13, 113–124. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McMartin, J.; Pickavance, T. Affective Reason. Episteme 2022, 1–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Siegel, S. The Rationality of Perception; Oxford University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Maguire, B. There Are No Reasons for Affective Attitudes. Mind 2018, 127, 779–805. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Helm, B.W. Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Benbaji, H. How Is Recalcitrant Emotion Possible? Australas. J. Philos. 2013, 91, 577–599. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cowan, R. Epistemic Sentimentalism and Epistemic Reason-Responsiveness. In Evaluative Perception; Bergqvist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Döring, S.A. What’s Wrong with Recalcitrant Emotions? From Irrationality to Challenge of Agential Identity. Dialectica 2015, 69, 381–402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grzankowski, A. Navigating Recalcitrant Emotions. J. Philos. 2020, 117, 501–519. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Helm, B.W. Emotions and Recalcitrance: Reevaluating the Perceptual Model. Dialectica 2015, 69, 417–433. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Majeed, R. What Not to Make of Recalcitrant Emotions. Erkenntnis 2022, 87, 747–765. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Milona, M.; Naar, H. Sentimental Perceptualism and the Challenge from Cognitive Bases. Philos. Stud. 2020, 177, 3071–3096. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vance, J. Emotion and the New Epistemic Challenge from Cognitive Penetrability. Philos. Stud. 2014, 169, 257–283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Szigeti, A. Emotions as Indeterminate Justifiers. Synthese 2021, 199, 11995–12017. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yip, B. Emotion as High-Level Perception. Synthese 2021, 199, 7181–7201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shargel, D.; Prinz, J. An Enactivist Theory of Emotional Content. In The Ontology of Emotions; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2017; pp. 110–129. [Google Scholar]
- Shargel, D. Appraisals, Emotions, and Inherited Intentional Objects. Emot. Rev. 2017, 9, 46–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Prinz, J. The Emotional Construction of Morals; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Vanello, D. Affect, Motivational States, and Evaluative Concepts. Synthese 2019, 197, 4617–4636. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stich, S.P.; Warfield, T.A. Mental Representation: A Reader; Wiley-Blackwell: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Scarantino, A. The Motivational Theory of Emotion. In Moral Psychology and Human Agency: Philosophical Essays on the Science of Ethics; D’Arms, J., Jacobson, D., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014; pp. 156–185. [Google Scholar]
- Schroeter, L.; Schroeter, F.; Jones, K. Do Emotions Represent Values?: Do Emotions Represent Values? Dialectica 2015, 69, 357–380. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dretske, F.I. Knowledge and the Flow of Information; MIT Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Dretske, F.I. Naturalizing the Mind; MIT Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Fodor, J.A. A Theory of Content and Other Essays; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, R. Moral Perception; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Levenson, R.W. Autonomic Specificity and Emotion. In Handbook of Affective Sciences; Davidson, R.J., Scherer, K.R., Goldsmith, H.H., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003; pp. 212–224. [Google Scholar]
- McGinley, J.J.; Friedman, B.H. Autonomic Specificity in Emotion: The Induction Method Matters. Int. J. Psychophysiol. 2017, 118, 48–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Stephens, C.L.; Christie, I.C.; Friedman, B.H. Autonomic Specificity of Basic Emotions: Evidence from Pattern Classification and Cluster Analysis. Biol. Psychol. 2010, 84, 463–473. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Deonna, J.; Teroni, F. The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Slaby, J. Affective intentionality and the feeling body. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2008, 7, 429–444. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Frijda, N.H. The Emotions; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Bradley, M.M.; Codispoti, M.; Cuthbert, B.N.; Lang, P.J. Emotion and Motivation I: Defensive and Appetitive Reactions in Picture Processing. Emotion 2001, 1, 276. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lang, P.J.; Bradley, M.M. Emotion and the Motivational Brain. Biol. Psychol. 2010, 84, 437–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- LeDoux, J. Rethinking the Emotional Brain. Neuron 2012, 73, 653–676. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pourtois, G.; Schettino, A.; Vuilleumier, P. Brain Mechanisms for Emotional Influences on Perception and Attention: What Is Magic and What Is Not. Biol. Psychol. 2013, 92, 492–512. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Susskind, J.M.; Lee, D.H.; Cusi, A.; Feiman, R.; Grabski, W.; Anderson, A.K. Expressing Fear Enhances Sensory Acquisition. Nat. Neurosci. 2008, 11, 843–850. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Calbi, M.; Montalti, M.; Pederzani, C.; Arcuri, E.; Umiltà, M.A.; Gallese, V.; Mirabella, G. Emotional Body Postures Affect Inhibitory Control Only When Task-Relevant. Front. Psychol. 2022, 13, 6857. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Mancini, C.; Falciati, L.; Maioli, C.; Mirabella, G. Happy Facial Expressions Impair Inhibitory Control with Respect to Fearful Facial Expressions but Only When Task-Relevant. Emotion 2022, 22, 142. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Mirabella, G.; Grassi, M.; Mezzarobba, S.; Bernardis, P. Angry and Happy Expressions Affect Forward Gait Initiation Only When Task Relevant. Emotion 2023, 23, 387. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Moors, A.; Fischer, M. Demystifying the Role of Emotion in Behaviour: Toward a Goal-Directed Account. Cogn. Emot. 2019, 33, 94–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Shoemaker, S. The inverted spectrum. J. Philos. 1982, 79, 357–381. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chalmers, D.J. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory; Oxford Paperbacks: Oxford, UK, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Kauppinen, A. A Humean Theory of Moral Intuition. Can. J. Philos. 2013, 43, 360–381. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bain, D. The Imperative View of Pain. J. Conscious. Stud. 2011, 18, 164–185. [Google Scholar]
- LeDoux, J.E. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- LeDoux, J.E. Feelings: What Are They & How Does the Brain Make Them? Daedalus 2015, 144, 96–111. [Google Scholar]
- LeDoux, J.E.; Hofmann, S.G. The Subjective Experience of Emotion: A Fearful View. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci. 2018, 19, 67–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walton, K.L. Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Corns, J. Unpleasantness, Motivational Oomph, and Painfulness. Mind Lang. 2014, 29, 238–254. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Corns, J.; Cowan, R. Moral Motivation and the Affective Appeal. Philos. Stud. 2021, 178, 71–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barbano, M.F.; Le Saux, M.; Cador, M. Involvement of Dopamine and Opioids in the Motivation to Eat: Influence of Palatability, Homeostatic State, and Behavioral Paradigms. Psychopharmacology 2009, 203, 475–487. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pool, E.; Sennwald, V.; Delplanque, S.; Brosch, T.; Sander, D. Measuring Wanting and Liking from Animals to Humans: A Systematic Review. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 2016, 63, 124–142. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Robinson, T.E.; Berridge, K.C. The Neural Basis of Drug Craving: An Incentive-Sensitization Theory of Addiction. Brain Res. Rev. 1993, 18, 247–291. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Robinson, M.J.F.; Fischer, A.M.; Ahuja, A.; Lesser, E.N.; Maniates, H. Roles of ‘Wanting’ and ‘Liking’ in Motivating Behavior: Gambling, Food, and Drug Addictions. In Behavioral Neuroscience of Motivation; Eleanor, H.S., Balsam, P.D., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2015; Volume 27, pp. 105–136. [Google Scholar]
- Adolphs, R.; Andler, D. Investigating Emotions as Functional States Distinct From Feelings. Emot. Rev. 2018, 10, 191–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Chalmers, D. The Representational Character of Experience. In The Future for Philosophy; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Rey, G. A Narrow Representationalist Account of Qualitative Experience. Philos. Perspect. 1998, 12, 435–457. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Block, N. Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology. Midwest Stud. Philos. 1986, 10, 615–678. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Block, N. Conceptual Role Semantics. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Routledge: London, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Harman, G. Conceptual role semantics. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 1982, 23, 242–256. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Camp, E. Thinking with Maps. Philos. Perspect. 2007, 21, 145–182. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Giardino, V.; Greenberg, G. Introduction: Varieties of Iconicity. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2015, 6, 1–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodman, N. Languages of Art; Bobbs-Merrill: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Quine, W.V. Natural Kinds. In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays; Kim, J., Sosa, E., Eds.; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1969; pp. 114–138. [Google Scholar]
- Abell, C. Canny Resemblance. Philos. Rev. 2009, 118, 183–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hopkins, R. Picture, Image and Experience: A Philosophical Inquiry; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Kulvicki, J.V. On Images: Their Structure and Content; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Beck, J. Analogue Magnitude Representations: A Philosophical Introduction. Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 2015, 66, 829–855. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kosslyn, S.M.; Thompson, W.L.; Ganis, G. The Case for Mental Imagery; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Shea, N. Representation in Cognitive Science; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Nozick, R. Examined Life: Philosophical Meditations; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Horgan, T.; Tienson, J. The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality. In Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings; David, J.C., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 520–533. [Google Scholar]
- Kriegel, U. Phenomenal Intentionality; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Loar, B. Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis of Mental Content. In Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge; Hahn, M., Ramberg, B., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2003; pp. 229–258. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelovici, A.A. The Phenomenal Basis of Intentionality; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Griffiths, P.E.; Scarantino, A. Emotions in the Wild: The Situated Perspective on Emotion. In The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition; Robbins, P., Aydede, M., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Gibson, J.J. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception: Classic Edition; Psychology Press: London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Ballard, B.S. The Non-Arbitrary Link between Feeling and Value: A Psychosemantic Challenge for the Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Philosophies 2024, 9, 38. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9020038
Ballard BS. The Non-Arbitrary Link between Feeling and Value: A Psychosemantic Challenge for the Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Philosophies. 2024; 9(2):38. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9020038
Chicago/Turabian StyleBallard, Brian Scott. 2024. "The Non-Arbitrary Link between Feeling and Value: A Psychosemantic Challenge for the Perceptual Theory of Emotion" Philosophies 9, no. 2: 38. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9020038
APA StyleBallard, B. S. (2024). The Non-Arbitrary Link between Feeling and Value: A Psychosemantic Challenge for the Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Philosophies, 9(2), 38. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9020038