Ecological Virtuous Selves: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Virtue Ethic?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Variations of Agency Regarding Virtue
- (a)
- Human agency affecting human(s). As anticipated above, this corresponds to the more traditional VE but is present also in EVE. To better understand it, consider the example of the human eye as presented by Aristotle. Such conception of virtue is typically weakly anthropocentric and is displayed in character traits such as compassion, attentiveness, attention, care, justice, etc., toward humans. According to Naess, embracing this type of moral orientation (i.e., “protecting Nature is protecting ourselves”) could constitute a motivation for pragmatic ecological ethics.
- (b)
- Non-human agency affecting human(s). In this case, the agent is a non-human being that is capable of exercising a virtue that has an effect on humans. It is interesting to point out that such a virtue would be described as an a-moral virtue when considering the non-human agent but potentially also as a moral virtue when considered from the point of view of the beneficiary (i.e., human(s)). For example, Aristotle described this version of virtuous behavior through the case of the brave horse, and it can be easily expanded to other instrumental relationships between animals and humans (e.g., animal labor/working force, food production, care labor). More broadly, this variation can be found in a lot of so-called “ecological services”, or “nature’s contribution to people” [16], or examples of symbiotic processes that benefit humans (for instance, see Margulis [17], Haraway [18]): breathing, digesting, pollination, filtration, providing food and shelter, and so forth. Accordingly, one might say that non-human agents that affect humans characterize every non-human precondition for human subsistence and flourishing. Often, these ecological capacities are turned toward human ends or made more efficient and productive through technical and technological means (e.g., devices, systems, processes). It goes without saying that many of such relationships are ambivalent and, like the Greek pharmakon, can designate either a poison or a medicine/cure (e.g., auto-immune diseases).
- (c)
- Human agency affecting non-human(s) (i.e., beings and entities). This option corresponds to EVE’s distinctive contribution through the notion of “ecological virtues”. Often, the effect(s) of such virtue(s) run the risk of being anthropomorphic in the sense that they may favor a human-centered conception of the “good/bad ends”, excluding more pluralistic conceptions (i.e., from the point of view of the non-human(s) affected). This approach comprises virtues similar to (a) but that affect non-human(s). A further risk of prioritizing non-human ends that has been highlighted several times in environmental ethics literature is that it could favor misanthropic, too radical, or eco-fascist conducts (e.g., some forms of radical environmentalism or Foreman’s rewilding proposal). Although the potential sacrifices by humans and even of humans could cohere with the recognition of the intrinsic value of non-human beings and entities, this remains extremely controversial. Later, we suggest that human selves as ecological selves can act virtuously in favor of ecological ends, the ecological worth of which could be studied scientifically.
- (d)
- Non-human agency affecting non-human(s) (i.e., beings and entities). In line with our thesis, it is possible to consider non-human beings as agents of a-moral functional ecological virtues that affect non-human beings, entities, or even ecosystems. Here, the distinctive and perhaps original element resides in the fact that the notion of self is broadened to include non-humans as potential agents (like in [b]), and the notion of virtue is decentralized as ecological virtue (like in [c]). In other words, non-human beings can act as ecological selves and are therefore considered agents capable of virtuous actions and behaviors that affect non-humans4. Similarly to [c], non-human beings can act virtuously by exercising a-moral functional ecological virtues and, similarly to [c], can affect positively different ecological dimensions and ends. As mentioned in [c], the “goodness” of these effects is a-moral and could be studied scientifically.
3. Broadening the Notion of Agency as Ecological Self
3.1. Three Traditional Conceptions of “Ecological Self” in Environmental Philosophy
“what I felt was naturally, a painful compassion and empathy. But the empathy was not basic, it was the process of identification, that ‘I see myself in the flea’. If I was alienated from the flea, not seeing intuitively anything even resembling myself, the death struggle would have left me indifferent. So there must be identification in order for there to be compassion […]” [21] (p. 36).
“[…] the ecological self is constituted by its internal socio-environmental relations. Untie the knot that is oneself in the socio-biospherical net or field of internal relations, and there’s nothing left of the self” [23] (p. 241).
“The ecological self can be viewed as a type of relational self, one which includes the goal of the flourishing of earth others and the earth community among its own primary ends, and hence respects or cares for these others for their own sake” [1].
3.2. Our Position on the Ecological Self
“The paradigm instance of the self-realizing system—or ‘self’—is the organism. But the geometrodynamic universe as a whole also qualifies for selfhood. A self-realizing being is one which, by its very activity, defines and embodies a value (viz., its value-for-itself.) Since self-realization is a function of ecological interconnectedness, the property of intrinsic value is likewise a function of such connectedness.” [20] (p. 101).
“Meaningfulness is to be found in our spiritual capacity to keep the ecocosm on course, by teaching our hearts to practise affirmation, and by awakening our faculty of active, outreaching, world-directed love. Though a tendency to ‘tread lightly’ on the earth, and to take practical steps to safeguard the particular manifestations of Nature, will inevitably flow from such an attitude, the crucial contribution will be the attitude itself, a contribution of the heart and spirit.” [20] (p. 113).
4. Towards Functional Ecological Virtues
4.1. Step by Step: What Do We Mean by (Functional) Ecological Virtue?
4.2. Functional Ecological Virtues and Moral Ecological Virtues
4.3. Possible Objections
- (1)
- The application of “virtue language” to describe the behaviors and attitudes of non-human beings is counterintuitive and potentially wrong. Other-than-human beings or more-than-human beings have been classically identified as non-moral agents or, at most, as moral patients. Indeed, the status of moral agency in modern western cultures is attributed to human only, insofar as humans can allegedly conduct their own behavior according to autonomous norms and practical reasoning [42], while virtues designate acquired excellences and not endowments. Thus, although one might agree with recognizing ecological selves in non-human behaviors, it still remains unclear how it would be possible to speak about virtues for them; whether they are considered as ecological selves or not, they would still fall under the category of moral patients, potentially protected or cared for by the expression of environmental virtues (exercised by human agents) but not as potential virtuous agents. However, as we have stressed, we are not talking about moral ecological virtues for non-humans. We rather suggest an extension of the space and meaning of ecological virtues on the basis of ontological considerations about the self. Functional ecological virtues are not virtues in any traditional moral sense; they are a-moral virtues that express mastering skills of ecological selves that can affect either humans, non-humans, or both (see Section 2 above).
- (2)
- A second objection might be put as a question: why use (and possibly distort) the concept of virtue instead of drawing upon another concept to describe such excellences or mastering skills? As we mentioned above, excellence and mastering skills are already historically part of the concept of virtue. These different concepts are not mutually exclusive but embedded in a mutual understanding in the history of ideas. The intellectual challenge of this paper was to question provocatively a well-accepted assumption of environmental virtue ethics (e.g., that the language of virtues is limited to human beings) and see what this could bring about. Using a usually (anthropocentric) moral term in an a-moral way is a strategy to expand and deconstruct dualistic inherited and rarely questioned structures or engrained theoretical assumptions. Moreover, if it were possible to consider a-moral excellences in terms of virtues, this may have a reinforcing positive impact on human moral ecological virtues, in the way explained in (i), (ii), and (iii) (see previous Section 4.2 on pp. 10–11).
- (3)
- One might say that a virtue, by definition, assumes the intentionality of the (human) moral agent as a prerequisite. This is, for example, the objection proposed by Holmes. He contested the extension of virtues to non-human beings, arguing that virtues are “achievements not endowments”, “acquired excellences” not “genetics endowments” [43] (p. 69). Holmes preferred to speak about “values as intrinsic achievements in wild nature” (ibid.) rather than using the concept of animal virtue. We can note that he did not consider plants, bacteria, or other living beings. Holmes feared that environmental virtue ethic approaches may not suffice to value nature in itself apart from human interests. Although he mentioned the meaning of virtue used by Thoreau “in the archaic sense of an “excellence”, survival skills in the migratory fish (with no reference to praiseworthy character achievement thus analogous to perfect pitch12 in humans)”, he contested it and asserted that value-based ethics respecting the intrinsic value of nature are preferable rather than virtue-based-ethics. We can reply to the objection that Holmes remains dualistic and anthropocentric in a classical naturalistic (as understood by Descola) way. The ethological dualism between will/instinct that underpins the dualistic opposition of acquired excellences/endowments is widely contested. More and more ethologists/psychologists/cognitivists tend to pay attention to individual variations and developed abilities in animal behaviors [44,45,46,47]. We argue that human beings, animals, plants, and other living beings can be characterized by “developed excellences” and that we should also pay attention to individual variations rather than only consider species-typical behavior. Moreover, Holmes seemed to adopt agent-based virtue ethics as a strawman, saying that concerns for human ends are not enough to cope with ecological issues. However, as Christine Swanton suggested,
“The environmental virtues can be understood as being virtues not just because they are dispositions to promote human-centered ends, but also the ends of the flourishing and integrity of ecosystems, species, and natural objects (sentient and non-sentient) for their own sakes. Furthermore, [the principle of pluralistic virtue] allows for the environmental virtues to have a complex profile, consisting not just of promotion of good or value, but also of respect, love for, and appreciation of natural objects.” [13] (p. 94).
5. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | “Non-human” is intended here as a synonym of “other-than-human” in the sense of a useful logical distinction but not in the sense of maintaining or defending a dualistic stance. |
2 | In this text, we do not distinguish between “environmental virtue(s)” and “ecological virtue(s)”. In the reminder, we use only the term “ecological virtue(s)” assuming the other as a synonym. However, in the paper entitled Virtue Ethics and Ecological Self: From Environmental to Ecological Virtues in this collection, Gérald Hess proposed a distinction precisely between these two. Cfr. [2]. |
3 | See this note of Roger Crisp in his translation of Nichomachean Ethics: “Aretḗ = virtue. Alternative translation: ‘excellence’. Covers non-moral as well as moral characteristics, as in, e.g., ‘This book has many virtues.’ Aristotle usually has in mind either moral excellences of character or intellectual excellences when using the term. It is related to the notion of ‘characteristic activity’ (ergon): the virtue of something consists in its capacity to perform well its characteristic activity (the virtue of an eye, for example, is to see well). Analogously, a vice (kakia) may be seen as a defect or flaw” [14] (p. 205). |
4 | If “non-humans” is considered a synonym of “nature”, then option [d] could be understood within [d]. |
5 | “I therefore tentatively introduce, perhaps for the first time ever, a concept of ecological self” [21] (p. 35). |
6 | Maybe the most important debate about the ecological self is the deep ecology–ecofeminism discussion of the 1980s–1990s, when ecofeminists criticized some aspects of the ecological self proposed by deep ecologists [24]. The main critique dealt with/focused on the fact that an “expanded self” or an “indistinguishable self”, and even the identification proposed by Naess, maintains and reproduces some patriarchal distortions. |
7 | Analogism refers here to Descola’s work [3] which gives it an ontological (and not only logical) meaning. Descola described the modern western ontology, called naturalism, as a reversed formula of animism: “articulating a discontinuity of interiorities and a continuity of physicalities” [3] (p. 172). Another ontology is analogism, which was dominant in western ontology until the Renaissance and which is common in some asian traditional cultures, among others. It is characterized as “a mode of identification that divides up the whole collection of existing beings into a multiplicity of essences, forms, and substances separated by small distinctions and sometimes arranged on a graduated scale so that it becomes possible to recompose the system of initial contrasts into a dense network of analogies that link together the intrinsic properties of the entities that are distinguished in it” [3] (p. 201). In this sense, ecological virtues could be considered as such an analogical “form” that can be shared and recognized amongst different beings and potentially arranged in another scale than the naturalistic dualistic hierarchy that only conceives human supremacy over other natural beings. |
8 | By ‘transformative’ we mean mainly two things: (1) that we transform the mainstream conception of environmental virtue, and (2) that this new conception of ecological virtue presupposes a transformation of our main naturalistic (in Descola’s sense) ontological structures and corresponding dualistic experiences of the self. |
9 | When Shaw exemplified these land virtues, with “respect (ecological sensitivity), prudence and practical judgment”, he tended to consider only human actions, allowing us to understand that land virtues are only characterized within the biotic community and human citizens and not all the other ones! |
10 | Our proposition could even be applied to a broader scale, such as Lovelock’s Gaïa self-regulating her living conditions to provide a habitat for biodiversity. |
11 | For instance, at a functional level, some Ruppell’s griffon vultures (Gyps rueppelli) that can fly up to more than 10,000 meters above African lands demonstrate incredible skills in evolving in the aerial fluid element and can undoubtedly be seen a master by paraglider’s pilots. Another more politically involved example are ‘weeds’ and the rhizomatic vegetal resistance and proliferation model, which are taken by alternative minority ecological collectives (like in the french ZAD of Notre-Dame-des-Landes) as explicit counter-hegemonic inspiring beings and dynamics for eco-social emancipatory movements (see for instance [38] entitled “Eloge des mauvaises herbes”, In praise of weeds). |
12 | Can functional ecological virtues be considered endowed skills analogous to “perfect pitch” and thus not praiseworthy acquired excellences that seem to define virtues? This example may not be the best choice. First of all, we can observe that nobody will ever develop a so-called “perfect pitch”, which is a very contextual and culturally situated skill, outside of a specific musical, familial, and social background. Thus, “perfect pitch” seems a weak paradigm of endowments as opposed to acquired excellence. It is rather the actualization in certain individuals of potentialities by a specific context (of learning, practicing, and playing some music). |
13 | We also note that intentionality may not be a requisite in classical virtue ethics, at least in the exercising of virtue, because virtues tend to be considered as internalized disposition or hexis in aristotelian terms. Moreover, some virtue ethics (e.g., daoist, zen buddhist, etc.) can consider non-deliberative virtues, like wuwei or ziran, or spontaneity as a key virtue. |
References
- Plumwood, V. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature; Routledge: London, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Hess, G. Virtue Ethics and Ecological Self: From Environmental to Ecological Virtues. Philosophies. 2024, 9. [Google Scholar]
- Descola, P. Beyond Nature and Culture; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Descola, P. Les Formes du Visible: Une Anthropologie de la Figuration; Éditions du Seuil: Paris, France, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- McShane, K. Anthropocentrism vs. nonanthropocentrism: Why should we care? Environ. Values 2007, 16, 169–185. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Callicott, J.B. The Topos of Mu and the Predicative Self. Dialogue Universalism 2023, 33, 9–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacIntyre, A. The Nature of the Virtues. In Virtue Ethics; Crisp, R., Slote, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- McCarty, R. Are there “Contra-Moral Virtues?”. Metaphilosophy 1994, 25, 362–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Koller, P. Law, Morality, and Virtue. In Working Virtue: Virtue Ethics and Contemporary Moral Problems; Walker, R.L., Ivanhoe, P.J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Slote, M.A. From Morality to Virtue; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Slote, M.A. Morals from Motives; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Huang, Y. Respecting Different Ways of Life: A Daoist Ethics of Virtue in the “Zhuangzi. J. Asian Stud. 2010, 69, 1049–1069. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swanton, C. Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Crisp, R. (Ed.) Aristotle: Nicomachean ethics. In Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Fontoynont, V. Vocabulaire Grec Commenté et Sur Textes. A. du Texte, 2nd ed.; Editions Auguste Picard: Paris, France, 1933; Available online: https://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k1189078c (accessed on 29 September 2023).
- Díaz, S.; Pascual, U.; Stenseke, M.; Martín-López, B.; Watson, R.T.; Molnár, Z.; Hill, R.; Chan, K.M.; Baste, I.A.; Brauman, K.A.; et al. Assessing nature’s contributions to people. Science 2018, 359, 270–272. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Margulis, L. Kingdoms and Domains: An Illustrated Guide to the Phyla of Life on Earth, 4th ed.; Elsevier Academic Press: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, D. Staying with the Trouble: Anthropocene, Capitalocene, Chthulucene. In Anthropocene or Capitalocene?: Nature, History, and the Crisis of Capitalism; Moore, J.W., Ed.; PM Press: Oakland, CA, USA, 2016; pp. 34–76. [Google Scholar]
- Callicott, J.B.; Frodeman, R. Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy; Macmillan Reference: Detroit, MI, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mathews, F. The Ecological Self; Routledge: London, UK, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Naess, A. Self-Realization: An Ecological Approach to Being in the World. Trumpeter 1987, 4. Available online: https://trumpeter.athabascau.ca/index.php/trumpet/article/view/623 (accessed on 10 March 2023).
- Naess, A. Ecosophy and Gestalt Ontology. Trumpeter 1989, 6. Available online: https://trumpeter.athabascau.ca/index.php/trumpet/article/view/756 (accessed on 9 September 2022).
- Callicott, J.B. Notes on “Self-Realization: An Ecological Approach to Being in the World”. Worldviews 2017, 21, 235–250. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Diehm, C. Arne Naess, Val Plumwood, and Deep Ecology Subjectivity: A contribution to the “Deep Ecology-Ecofeminism Debate”. Ethics Environ. 2002, 7, 24–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plumwood, V. Environmental Culture: The Ecological Crisis of Reason; Routledge: London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Mathews, F. Towards a Deeper Philosophy of Biomimicry. Organ. Environ. 2011, 24, 364–387. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mathews, F. Reinhabiting Reality towards a Recovery of Culture. In SUNY Series in Environmental Philosophy and Ethics; University of New South Wales Press: Sydney, NSW, Australia, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Varela, F.J. Organism, Cognitive Science and the Emergence of Selfless Selves. Rev. Eur. Des Sci. Soc. 1991, 29, 173–198. [Google Scholar]
- Furstenburg, D.; van Hoven, W. Condensed tannin as anti-defoliate agent against browsing by giraffe (Giraffa camelopardalis) in the Kruger National Park. Comp. Biochem. Physiol. Part A Physiol. 1994, 107, 425–431. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shaw, B. A Virtue Ethics Approach to Aldo Leopold’s Land Ethic. Environmental Ethics 1997, 19, 53–67. Available online: https://www.pdcnet.org/pdc/bvdb.nsf/purchase?openform&fp=enviroethics&id=enviroethics_1997_0019_0001_0053_0067 (accessed on 2 October 2023).
- Rohwer, Y. Evolution Is Not Good. In Environmental Ethics; Philosophy Documentation Center: Charlottesville, VA, USA, 2023. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marder, M. Plant-Thinking: A Philosophy of Vegetal Life; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Chamovitz, D. What a Plant Knows: A Field Guide to the Senses, Updated and Expanded ed.; Scientific American/Farrar, Straus and Giroux: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Peeters, W.; Diependaele, L.; Sterckx, S. Moral Disengagement and the Motivational Gap in Climate Change. Ethic. Theory Moral Pract. 2019, 22, 425–447. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van Zyl, L. Virtue Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction. In Routledge Contemporary Introductions to Philosophy, 1st ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jacobsen, S.-E.; Mujica, A.; Jensen, C.R. The Resistance of Quinoa (Chenopodium quinoaWilld.) to Adverse Abiotic Factors. Food Rev. Int. 2023, 19, 99–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Guzy, J.; Falk, B.G.; Smith, B.J.; Willson, J.D.; Reed, R.N.; Aumen, N.G.; Avery, M.L.; Bartoszek, I.A.; Campbell, E.; Cherkiss, M.S.; et al. Burmese pythons in Florida: A synthesis of biology, impacts, and management tools. NeoBiota 2023, 80, 1–119. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lindgaard, J. (Ed.) Éloge des Mauvaises Herbes: Ce que Nous Devons à la ZAD; Les Liens qui Libèrent: Paris, France, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Merchant, C. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution; Harper & Row: San Francisco, CA, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Merchant, C. Radical ecology: The search for a livable world. In Revolutionary Thought/Radical Movements; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Merchant, C. Autonomous Nature: Problems of Prediction and Control from Ancient Times to the Scientific Revolution; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hess, G. Éthiques de la Nature; PUF: Paris, France, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Holmes, R.I. Environmental Virtue Ethics: Half the Truth but Dangerous as a Whole. In Environmental Virtue Ethics; Sandler, R., Cafaro, P., Eds.; Rowman & Littlefield: Lanham, MD, USA, 2005; pp. 61–78. [Google Scholar]
- Blumberg, M.S. Development evolving: The origins and meanings of instinct. Wiley Interdiscip. Rev. Cogn. Sci. 2017, 8, 10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Longa, V.M.; Lorenzo, G. Study of Instinct. In Encyclopedia of Evolutionary Psychological Science; Shackelford., T.K., Weekes-Shackelford, V.A., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2019; pp. 1–4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Morizot, B. Les Diplomates: Cohabiter Avec les Loups sur une Autre Carte du Vivant; Éditions Wildproject: Marseille, France, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Colling, S. Animal Resistance in the Global Capitalist Era; Michigan State University Press: East Lansing, MI, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Delorme, D.; Calidori, N.; Frigo, G. Ecological Virtuous Selves: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Virtue Ethic? Philosophies 2024, 9, 11. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010011
Delorme D, Calidori N, Frigo G. Ecological Virtuous Selves: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Virtue Ethic? Philosophies. 2024; 9(1):11. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010011
Chicago/Turabian StyleDelorme, Damien, Noemi Calidori, and Giovanni Frigo. 2024. "Ecological Virtuous Selves: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Virtue Ethic?" Philosophies 9, no. 1: 11. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010011
APA StyleDelorme, D., Calidori, N., & Frigo, G. (2024). Ecological Virtuous Selves: Towards a Non-Anthropocentric Environmental Virtue Ethic? Philosophies, 9(1), 11. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010011