Mutual Flourishing: A Dialogical Approach to Environmental Virtue Ethics
Abstract
:1.
For a large number, although not all, of individual living things and biological collectives, we should recognize and promote their flourishing as an end itself. Such care for the natural world is constitutive of a flourishing human life. The best human life is one that includes an awareness of and practical concern with the goods of entities in the nonhuman world.[2] (p. 24; see also pp. 78, 153 and p. 155)
Individuality is cherished and nurtured, because, in order for the whole to flourish, each of us has to be strong in who we are and carry our gifts with conviction, so they can be shared with others’.[1] (p. 134)
A Grammatical Aproach to the Subject: Toward a Narrative Environmental Virtue Ethics
2.
2.1. A Recognising Attitude of Nature Based on Love as a Form of Adequate Recognition
2.2. The Relational Space of a Mutual Flourishing Environmental Virtue Ethics
2.3. Ascription: Conceiving Nature’s Autonomy or Capacity for Agency
3.
3.1. The Relational Space as a Moral Space: Toward an Ecological Identity
3.2. The Relational Space as an Ontological and Ethical Place: Toward a Mutual Flourishing Environmental Virtue Ethics
3.3. Being(s) Together: An Illustration
[Stefano:] And these encounters were…let’s say a way of deepening knowledge that in this close contact with a wild animal created the desire to learn to get to know a very fascinating animal better. […] In fact, he’s a character. The fox, when you meet him, you understand he has a lot to tell you. What I like doing is getting to know an individual. In this case the fox, not as a species, but as this specific subject, this individual. And so learn its habits, its behaviour, its character, I mean…the animal’s personality. Jokingly with my wife, we often say they’re my ‘anima friends’, but we really do become friends. So, in this context, ethics are something natural. I work on the principle that I respect my friends. If a fox is unbelievably beautiful and has a particular attitude, I call it Beauty. If on the contrary, the fox is dominant in its territory with maybe a scar on its nose, I remember, we nicknamed hi the Boss. […] So, these are little nicknames, which in fact enable us, on the one hand, to break down a bit the barrier between me and the other species. For example, I didn’t see a fox, but I saw the Boss who was doing this or that. And so the story begins there.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The expression ‘substantial account of nature’ means, according to B. Bannon’s interpretation, that natural entities have mind-like properties (intentionality, agency, etc.); that is, that they have ‘teleological purposiveness’. Bannon counters this with a relational account in which it is not intentionality but processes and relations that best explain the basis of non-dualistic environmental ethics. |
2 | In this approach, place, therefore, supplants nature: ‘beings all participate in the creation of a place to the extent that they contribute to it through their openness to affection and their affection of other bodies’ [5] (p. 50). |
3 | Taking Jacob von Uexküll’s example, Virginie Maris [11] illustrates her purpose thus: ‘Whereas the world-for-the-bear, stretching for hundreds of kilometres, is made up of rivers, fish, paths, plants and caves, the world-for-the-tick is made up of branches, hair, skin and blood. It is as complete a world for the tick as the world-for-the-bear is for the bear.’ (pp. 204–205). |
4 | Today, in the epoch of the Anthropocene, this encounter takes the form of the uncanny: ‘It is surely no coincidence that the word uncanny has begun to be used, with ever greater frequency, in relation to climate change […] No other word comes close to expressing the strangeness of what is unfolding around us […] the uncanny and improbable events that are beating at our doors seem to have stirred a sense of recognition, an awareness that humans were never alone, that we have always been surrounded by beings of all sorts who share elements of that which we had thought to be most distinctively our own: the capacities of will, thought, and consciousness’ [12] (p. 35). |
5 | Indeed, ‘there always needs to be two-way recognition for even one-way recognition to take place’ [19] (p. 319). |
6 | As Arto Laitinen notes, recognition is not only a matter of attitudes: ‘It can be a matter of acting, emoting, expressing the attitudes or emotions, a matter of statuses, relations, etc.’ [19] (p. 335). |
7 | This is because love, in Maturana’s sense, is unidirectional, that is, is other-directed and does not require mutual loving: ‘the loved one arises as a legitimate other through the behaviour of the lover without necessarily being an active participant in a loving or any other relation with the lover’ [21] (p. 55). |
8 | Thus, virtues, I argue, can be cultivated only when a relational space exists that then makes the cultivation of virtues possible. |
9 | At this point, the following question inevitably arises: moral subjectivity entails responsibility. If nature’s subjectivity involves recognising its capacity for intentionality and agency, then what about nature’s responsibility (e.g., when a snake bites me, or a rock hits me on the head…)? Is not responsibility an important feature of subjectivity? This is a very important question that deserves a thorough examination. However, I will give the following tentative answers: often responsibility is indeed ascribed (on this see the following section) to an animal, as when we attribute to the wolf the responsibility for killing the sheep (and, in most cases, it is hunted to death as a result). More importantly, I think that from a place-based ethics perspective, the question of responsibility is closely linked to the question of limits. First, knowing ‘our’ limits: the snake bites me, but did I step into the snake’s place? The rock hits me on the head, but was I in ‘my’ place when I climbed the mountain? Sometimes animals step into ‘our’ place. This last point is reminiscent of V. Plumwood’s example: in this case, ‘[f]or example, the ethical perplexities and strategies for dealing with a strange highly venomous snake who has just moved onto your veranda may not be all that different from those involved in dealing with a difficult human stranger who has done the same’ [3] (p. 170). Ultimately, as V. Plumwood argues, this is a question of interspecies distributive justice: sharing the earth with other species [3] (p. 117). Of course, sometimes tragedy happens at the crossing of boundaries, at the interface of places. I am very grateful to one attentive reviewer of this essay for raising this important question. |
10 | I use the term ‘environmental identity’ in a narrower sense than what we might call, following Arne Naess, ‘an ecological self’, that is, a metaphysical reality in which I participate on the basis of a subjective experience of identification with nature. In short, it is the extension and the transformation of the ego into a broader understanding of the self in which ecological dependencies and interdependencies are constitutive of identity (‘my’ self-realisation is then the self-realisation of an ecological self). This rather (eco)phenomenological perspective, although at the heart of our subject matter here, goes beyond the scope of the place-based approach that I have chosen to develop here. It is for this reason that I will now turn to C. Taylor’s understanding of modern identity. |
11 | Available online: https://www.meg.ch/en/expositions/beings-together (accessed on 20 November 2023). |
12 | Available online: https://www.stefanounterthiner.com/ (accessed on 20 November 2023). |
References
- Kimmerer, R.W. Braiding Sweetgrass, 1st ed.; Milkweed Editions: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- O’Neill, J. Ecology, Policy and Politics, Human Well-Being and the Natural World; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Plumwood, V. Environmental Culture: The Ecological Crisis of Reason; Environmental Philosophies Series; Routledge: London, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Plumwood, V. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature; Digital Printing; Routledge: London, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Bannon, B. Developing Val Plumwood’s Dialogical Ethical Ontology and Its Consequences for a Place-Based Ethic. Ethics Environ. 2009, 14, 39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bannon, B.E. From Intrinsic Value to Compassion: A Place-Based Ethic. Environ. Ethics 2013, 35, 259–278. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilliand, C. Experiencing Values in the Flow of Events: A Phenomenological Approach to Relational Values. Environ. Values 2021, 30, 715–736. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Descombes, V. Le Complément de Sujet: Enquête Sur Le Fait d’agir de Soi-Même; Tel 421; Gallimard: Paris, France, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Castoriadis, C. L’état Du Sujet Aujourd’hui. In Le Monde Morcelé, Les Carrefours Du Labyrinthe III; Éditions du Seuil: Paris, France, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Maturana, H.; Varela, F. De Maquinas y Seres Vivos, Autopoiesis: La Organizacion de lo Vivo; Editorial Universitaria: Santiago de Chile, Chile, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Maris, V. La Part Sauvage Du Monde: Penser La Nature Dans l’Anthropocène; Anthropocène Seuil; Éditions du Seuil: Paris, France, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Ghosh, A. The Nutmeg’s Curse: Parables for a Planet in Crisis; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Chakrabarty, D. The Climate of History: Four Theses. Crit. Inq. 2009, 35, 197–222. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chakrabarty, D. The Anthropocene and the Convergence of Histories. In The Anthropocene and the Global Environmental Crisis, Rethinking Modernity in a New Epoch; Hamilton, C., Bonneuil, C., Gemenne, F., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Sandler, R. Environmental Virtue Ethics. In Environmental Ethics, The Big Questions; Keller, D.R., Ed.; Wiley-Blackwell: Malden, MA, USA; Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Treanor, B. Narrative Environmental Virtue Ethics: Phronesis without a Phronimos. Environ. Ethics 2008, 30, 361–379. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rosa, H. Resonance: A Sociology of Pur Relationship to the World; James Wagner, J., Translator; Polity Press: Cambridge, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Honneth, A.; Butler, J.; Geuss, R.; Lear, J.; Jay, M. Reification: A New Look at an Old Idea; The Berkeley Tanner Lectures; Oxford University Press: Oxford, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Laitinen, A. On the Scope of “Recognition”: The Role of Adequate Regard and Mutuality. In The Philosophy of Recognition: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives; Schmidt am Busch, H.-C., Zurn, C.F., Eds.; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Arcos, E. Autonomy as the self-realisation of an environmental identity. Environ. Values 2023, 09632719231214311. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maturana Romesín, H.; Verden-Zöller, G. The Origin of Humanness in the Biology of Love; Imprint Academic: Upton Pyne, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle; Ross, W.D.; Brown, L. The Nicomachean Ethics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Ricœur, P. The Course of Recognition; Institute for Human Sciences Vienna Lecture Series; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Clayton, S. Environmental Identity: A Conceptual and an Operational Definition. In Identity and the Natural Environment, The Psychological Significance of Nature; Clayton, S., Opotow, S., Eds.; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA; London, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, C. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Casey, E.S. Between Geography and Philosophy: What Does It Mean to Be in the Place-World? Ann. Assoc. Am. Geogr. 2001, 91, 683–693. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Arcos, E. Mutual Flourishing: A Dialogical Approach to Environmental Virtue Ethics. Philosophies 2024, 9, 6. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010006
Arcos E. Mutual Flourishing: A Dialogical Approach to Environmental Virtue Ethics. Philosophies. 2024; 9(1):6. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010006
Chicago/Turabian StyleArcos, Esteban. 2024. "Mutual Flourishing: A Dialogical Approach to Environmental Virtue Ethics" Philosophies 9, no. 1: 6. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010006
APA StyleArcos, E. (2024). Mutual Flourishing: A Dialogical Approach to Environmental Virtue Ethics. Philosophies, 9(1), 6. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9010006