How Can a Taxonomy of Stances Help Clarify Classical Debates on Scientific Change?
Abstract
:1. Preamble
2. Why Do We Need a Taxonomy of Stances?
Of the contributors to the discussions on our symposium… who in their talks or discussion remarks referred… to ‘acceptance’ and its rules, none gave much indication that he regarded the notion of acceptance as being in need of clarification. I regard this as remarkable and rather disappointing, since it was so clear to me… that the term ‘accept’ (as well as, of course, ‘reject’) is highly ambiguous both in our ordinary speech and in our informal scientific discourse… Without this preliminary clarification, any discussion of the rationality, justifiability, or ‘logicality’ of acceptance is doomed to futility.[1] (pp. 150–151)
Acceptance may connote provisional use of certain hypotheses (without commitment to truth content), or acceptance of certain parts of the theory as true while rejecting other propositions as false, … or acceptance of the theory as true without regarding it as a program for further research.[2] (p. 165)
To commit oneself to working on a theory is one sort of cognitive stance; to take the theory for granted in testing other theories is another; … and to use the theory to put men on the moon, yet something else.[4] (p. 216)
Ultimately, it was Newton’s work that commanded the greatest scientific authority throughout most of Europe by around the middle of the century. But even though in the field of celestial mechanics and, to a lesser degree, terrestrial mechanics Newton largely reigned supreme, in other areas of science—notably those based on experiment—his shadow fell more lightly. In France the experimental sciences proceeded without any firm commitment to Newtonian concepts. The equivocal attitude of Leonhard Euler (1707–1783) toward Newton’s theory of light—ranging from an overtly anti-Newtonian rejection of the particle theory of light to a subsequent debt to elements of Newtonian mechanics in formulating his wave theory of light—is another instance of the partial and provisional character of the Newtonian hegemony of the second half of the eighteenth century.[7] (our italics)
3. A Prospective Taxonomy
Proposals for hypotheses inundate us in an overwhelming flood, while the process of verification to which each one must be subjected before it can count as at all an item, even of likely knowledge, is so very costly in time, energy, and money.
4. Application of the Taxonomy to Two Classical Debates
4.1. Lakatos and Feyerabend on Theory Rejection
- The modification increases the empirical content of the theory; i.e., it introduces excess empirical content.
- At least some of this excess empirical content is corroborated in experiments and/or observations.
- The modification is consistent with the positive heuristic of the programme.
Paul: Are you saying that if a research programme is judged better than a rival one, scientists ought to work on the allegedly superior one?
Imre: … I am giving you criteria for progress and stagnation within a programme, and the rules for the ‘elimination’ of entire programmes. Should a programme explain in a more progressive way more than a rival programme accounts for… then… the rival one may be ‘rejected’ or simply ‘shelved’. You cannot at this point fail to understand what the pragmatic meaning of ‘rejecting’ a programme is: very simply, it means the decision to cease working on it.
Paul: OK, but it is easy to see that standards of your kind have practical force only if combined with some time limit after which to keep working on a degenerating programme would be ‘irrational’. If you accept the idea of the time limit, then unfortunately, arguments very similar to the ones you used against naïve falsificationism backfire against your own standards. Consider that if it is unwise to reject faulty theories the moment they are born because they might grow and improve, then it is also unwise to reject research programmes on a downward trend because they might recover…
Imre: Don’t get me wrong here. My methodology… has no intention of handing out advice to the scientist on how to arrive at good theories or on which of two rival theories he should work on…
Paul: And yet, at the beginning, the bold project of “the logic of scientific discovery” was aimed at describing those rules which govern the acceptance and rejection of scientific theories… What then is the point of laying down the rules which may be either followed or ignored?… Your standards are only verbal ornaments.
Imre: There is freedom (‘anarchy’, if you like) in choosing which programme to work on, but the products must be judged. You are conflating methodological appraisal of a research programme with heuristic advice on what to do.[36] (pp. 3–4)
4.2. Feyerabend and Kuhn on Paradigm-Monism
At any time the practitioners of a given specialty may recognize numerous classics, some of them—like the works of Ptolemy and Copernicus or Newton and Descartes—quite incompatible one with the other. But that same group, if it has a paradigm at all, can have only one. Unlike the community of artists—which can draw simultaneous inspiration from the works of, say, Rembrandt and Cézanne and which therefore studies both—the community of astronomers had no alternative to choosing between the competing models of scientific activity supplied by Copernicus and Ptolemy.[42] (p. 352)
The idea that here we had a period governed by an all embracing paradigm which absorbed the physicist’s attention to the exclusion of everything else is seen to be a gross over-simplification.[45] (p. 253)
- Concerning acceptance: is it possible to accept two or more competing theories at the same time?
- Concerning use: is it possible to use two or more competing theories in the same application?
- Concerning pursuit: is it possible to pursue two or more competing theories at the same time?
The success of the paradigm… is at the start largely a promise of success discoverable in selected and still incomplete examples. Normal science consists in the actualization of that promise…[41] (pp. 23–24)
A myth can very well stand on its own feet. It can give explanations, it can reply to criticism, it can give a satisfactory account even of events which prima facie seem to refute it. It can do this because it is absolutely true…[52] (p. 64)
5. A Few Lessons
6. Concluding Remarks
Author Contributions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Bar-Hillel, Y. The Acceptance Syndrome. In The Problem of Inductive Logic; Lakatos, I., Ed.; North Holland Publishing Company: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1968; pp. 150–161. [Google Scholar]
- Westman, R.S. The Melanchthon Circle, Rheticus, and the Wittenberg Interpretation of the Copernican Theory. Isis 1975, 66, 165–193. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Laudan, L. Progress and Its Problems. Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Wykstra, S.J. Toward a Historical Meta-Method for Assessing Normative Methodologies: Rationability, Serendipity, and the Robinson Crusoe Fallacy. In Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the PSA 1; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1980; pp. 211–222. [Google Scholar]
- Whitt, L.A. Theory Pursuit: Between Discovery and Acceptance. In Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the PSA 1; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1990; pp. 467–483. [Google Scholar]
- Kao, M. Evaluating the Quantum Postulate in the Context of Pursuit. Ph.D. Thesis, The University of Western Ontario, London, ON, Canada, 2016. Available online: http://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3675 (accessed on 4 November 2017).
- Gascoigne, J. Ideas of Nature: Natural Philosophy. In The Cambridge History of Science. Volume 4: Eighteenth-Century Science; Porter, R., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003; pp. 285–304. [Google Scholar]
- Cardini, F.; Huang, W.X. Moxibustion for Correction of Breech Presentation: A Randomized Controlled Trial. J. Am. Med. Assoc. 1998, 280, 1580–1584. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grant, E. Eccentrics and Epicycles in Medieval Cosmology. In Mathematics and its Application to Science and Natural Philosophy in the Middle Ages; Grant, E., Murdoch, J.E., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1987; pp. 189–216. [Google Scholar]
- Grant, E. The Medieval Cosmos: Its Structure and Operation. J. Hist. Astron. 1997, 28, 147–167. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lindberg, D. The Beginnings of Western Science; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, C.S. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volumes V and VI: Pragmatism and Pragmaticism and Scientific Metaphysics; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1935. [Google Scholar]
- Hanson, N.R. Patterns of Discovery; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Achinstein, P. How to Defend a Theory without Testing It: Niels Bohr and the “Logic of Pursuit”. Midwest Stud. Philos. 1993, 13, 90–120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brown, J.R. Who Rules in Science? Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Bunge, M. Treatise on Basic Philosophy. Volume 6. Epistemology and Methodology II: Understanding the World; D. Reidel Publishing Company: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. Philosophical Papers, Volume II; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Poincaré, H. Science and Hypothesis; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1952. [Google Scholar]
- Poincaré, H. Mathematics and Science: Last Essays; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Chakravartty, A. A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Van Fraassen, B. The Scientific Image; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Cartwright, N. The Dappled World. A Study of the Boundaries of Science; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Horwich, P. On the Nature and Norms of Theoretical Commitment. Philos. Sci. 1991, 58, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barseghyan, H. The Laws of Scientific Change; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Duhem, P. The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1906. [Google Scholar]
- Popper, K.R. Conjectures and Refutations; Routledge: London, UK, 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes (1970). In Philosophical Papers, Volume I; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1978; pp. 8–101. [Google Scholar]
- Patton, P.; Overgaard, N.; Barseghyan, H. Reformulating the Second Law. Scientonomy 2017, 1, 29–39. Available online: http://www.scientojournal.com/index.php/scientonomy/article/view/27158 (accessed on 4 November 2017).
- Feyerabend, P. Consolations for the Specialist. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge; Lakatos, I., Musgrave, A., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1970; pp. 197–230. [Google Scholar]
- Lakatos, I. History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions (1971). In Philosophical Papers, Volume I; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1978; pp. 102–138. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. In Defense of Classical Physics (1970). In Philosophical Papers, Volume 4; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2015; pp. 239–267. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. Minn. Stud. Philos. Sci. 1970, 4, 17–129. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. On the Critique of Scientific Reason. In Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos; Cohen, R., Feyerabend, P., Wartofsky, M., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1976; pp. 109–143. [Google Scholar]
- Musgrave, A. Method or Madness? In Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos; Cohen, R., Feyerabend, P., Wartofsky, M., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1976; pp. 457–491. [Google Scholar]
- Motterlini, M. Has Lakatos Really Gone a Long Way Towards Epistemological Anarchism? Epistemologia 1995, 18, 215–232. [Google Scholar]
- Motterlini, M. (Ed.) For and Against Method, Including Lakatos’s Lectures on Scientific Method, and the Lakatos-Feyerabend Correspondence; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism (1962). In Philosophical Papers, Volume 1; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1981; pp. 44–97. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. The Concept of Intelligibility in Modern Physics (1948). In Philosophical Papers, Volume 4; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2015; pp. 3–8. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Against Method; New Left Books: New York, NY, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Masterman, M. The Nature of a Paradigm. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge; Lakatos, I., Musgrave, A., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1970; pp. 59–91. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, T. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd ed.; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, T. The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research. In Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Technical Invention, from Antiquity to the Present: Symposium on the History of Science, University of Oxford, 9–15 July 1961; Crombie, A.C., Ed.; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 1963; pp. 347–369. [Google Scholar]
- Watkins, J.W.N. Against ‘Normal Science’. In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge; Lakatos, I., Musgrave, A., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1970; pp. 25–37. [Google Scholar]
- Preston, J. Feyerabend: Philosophy, Science and Society; Polity: Cambridge, UK, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Review of “Scientific Change” Edited by A. C. Crombie. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 1964, 15, 244–254. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Feyerabend, P. Reply to Criticism: Comments on Smart, Sellars and Putnam (1965). In Philosophical Papers, Volume 1; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1981; pp. 104–131. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. About Conservative Traits in the Sciences, and Especially in Quantum Theory, and Their Elimination (1963). In Philosophical Papers, Volume 3; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999; pp. 188–200. [Google Scholar]
- Shaw, J. Was Feyerabend an Anarchist? The Structure(s) of ‘Anything Goes’. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 2017, 64, 11–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bschir, K. Feyerabend and Popper on Theory Proliferation and Anomaly Import: On the Compatibility of Theoretical Pluralism and Critical Rationalism. J. Int. Soc. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2015, 5, 24–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kuhn, T. Objectivity, Value Judgement, and Theory Choice (1973). In The Essential Tension; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1977; pp. 320–339. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Problems of Empiricism: I. In Beyond the Edge of Certainty; Colodny, R.G., Ed.; Prentice Hall: Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA, 1965; pp. 145–260. [Google Scholar]
- Feyerabend, P. Knowledge Without Foundations (1961). In Philosophical Papers, Volume 3; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999; pp. 50–78. [Google Scholar]
- Kuhn, T. The Essential Tension: Tradition and Innovation in Scientific Research (1959). In The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1977; pp. 225–239. [Google Scholar]
- Chang, H. Is Water H2O? Evidence, Realism and Pluralism; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
1 | Albeit very interesting, the task of differentiating between subtypes of use is beyond the scope of this paper. |
2 | While it is certainly true that some individual scientists accept one version of string theory or another, no version of string theory is currently accepted by the physics community at large. From the communal perspective, string theories are merely pursued, not accepted. |
3 | |
4 | In fact, after Perrin’s experiment, Poincaré triumphantly announces the reality of atoms and, thereby, proclaims that the atomic hypothesis should be accepted [19]. |
5 | |
6 | See [28]. |
7 | See [24] (pp. 129–132, 217–225) and references therein. |
8 | Lakatos shifts the unit of appraisal from theories to research programmes or series of theories. Feyerabend’s definition of theory is explicitly broad enough to include the notion of research programmes [29] (p. 203, fn. 2). |
9 | Lakatos credits Popper with this insight [17] (p. 221). |
10 | Note that the terminology of this fragment is still that of Lakatos. We are not yet applying our taxonomy. |
11 | |
12 | |
13 | |
14 | |
15 | See also [48]. |
16 | See [49] for a discussion of this. |
17 | |
18 | It is important to keep in mind that here we are not discussing the normative question of whether it is advisable or permissible to pursue more than one paradigm at a time. Kuhn would famously object against the practice of pursuing multiple paradigms, by calling it wasteful and not conducive to progress [53] (pp. 229–231); [41] (p. 162). On this normative issue, he and Feyerabend held opposing views. |
19 | For a detailed discussion, see [24] (pp. 152–164). |
Yes | No | |
---|---|---|
Is a theory taken as the best available description of its domain? | Accepted | Unaccepted |
Is a theory considered useful in practical applications? | Used | Unused |
Is a theory considered worthy of further development, elaboration? | Pursued | Neglected |
© 2017 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Barseghyan, H.; Shaw, J. How Can a Taxonomy of Stances Help Clarify Classical Debates on Scientific Change? Philosophies 2017, 2, 24. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies2040024
Barseghyan H, Shaw J. How Can a Taxonomy of Stances Help Clarify Classical Debates on Scientific Change? Philosophies. 2017; 2(4):24. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies2040024
Chicago/Turabian StyleBarseghyan, Hakob, and Jamie Shaw. 2017. "How Can a Taxonomy of Stances Help Clarify Classical Debates on Scientific Change?" Philosophies 2, no. 4: 24. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies2040024
APA StyleBarseghyan, H., & Shaw, J. (2017). How Can a Taxonomy of Stances Help Clarify Classical Debates on Scientific Change? Philosophies, 2(4), 24. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies2040024