Dialectic in Early Proclus and the Unity of the Soul
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. The Platonic Notion of Dialectic and Proclus’ Stance
3. The Aristotelian Perspective as a Constituent Part of Proclus’ Conception
4. The Soul as Source and Destination of Proclus’ Dialectic
5. Outcome and Perspectives
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Cf. Chlup [1], pp. 12, 40; in general the reception of the two major figures of Classical Antiquity has various aspects whereas it would be quite accurate to say that among the Neoplatonists the apparent “approval of Aristotle, however strongly expressed, never implies their systematic, universal agreement with him” (Boys-Stones [2], p. 1129 with reference to Karamanolis [3]). In a broader perspective, it would be necessary to state that not only key Platonic and Aristotelian notions but Stoic elements as well were interwoven into Neoplatonism (cf. Kenny [4], pp. 311 ff.). |
2 | |
3 | The undisputed existence of the Good follows directly from the image of the Sun (cf. ibid. VI 19, 508 a 4–509 b 5). Soon afterwards, we come across the impressive but at the same time enigmatic statement that the Good, according to its dignity and its power, does not belong to Being (in general) but lies beyond it (οὐκ οὐσίας ὄντος τοῦ ἀγαθοῦ, ἀλλ’ ἔτι ἐπέκεινα τῆς οὐσίας πρεσβείᾳ καὶ δυνάμει ὑπερέχοντος, ibid. VI 19, 509 b 8–10) with which Proclus also deals in his Commentary on the Republic. |
4 | This refers clearly to the late dialogues, where the partners express a certain concern about delivering the right and effective answers to their possible challengers (cf. for instance, Sophist, 258 e 6–259 e 7 in Plato [9], pp. 455–457; cf. Plato [10], pp. 124–125). It is noteworthy that apart from the dubious Alcibiades I Plato’s Sophist also belongs to the dialogues that were carefully studied by Proclus. |
5 | Cf. Proclus [11], I 280, 8–281, 7. |
6 | |
7 | “Proclus reads the Alcibiades as a fundamental and foundational contribution to one’s philosophical education, and sees the dialogue as both erotic and scientific” (Ambury [14], p. 26). |
8 | Cf. Terezis [15], pp. 184–186. |
9 | Cf. Aristoteles [16], p. 100, Topica, 100 b 21–23. |
10 | |
11 | Cf. In Alcibiadem I, 23.8–11 in Proclus [17], p. 10. |
12 | |
13 | Cf. Dillon-Gerson [21], pp. 318–319. |
14 | The striking statement in the Sophist, that one must avoid confusing the sophist and the philosopher, presupposes the recognition of the similarities between them (cf. Plato [9], 231 a 3–b 2). This is also the case if we likewise take the Platonic and the Aristotelian dialectic into account: the affirmation of continuity is the precondition for studying the difference, and vice versa. |
15 | |
16 | It should also be noted that Proclus as regards the process of the attainment of knowledge remains faithful to the spirit of Plato’s Socratic dialogues also by trying to maintain the unity of the three separate fields of dialectics, erotics, maieutics: καὶ γὰρ μαιευόμενος φυλάττει τὸ τῷ ἐρωτικῷ προσῆκον καὶ τῇ διαλεκτικῇ χρώμενος οὐκ ἀφίσταται τῆς ἰδιότητος τῶν ἐρωτικῶν λόγων (In Alcibiadem I, 28.2–3 in Proclus [17], p. 12; cf. In Alcibiadem I, 29.1–5, in Proclus [17], p. 13). |
17 | “(…) in Proclus’ treatises ‘Intellect’ may mean two different things, sometimes referring to the general Plotinian Intellect, sometimes to a sublevel clearly distinguished from Being” (Chlup [1], p. 17). |
18 | Proclus holds that “it is imperative not to be satisfied with appearances, but that one should try to elevate himself up to their homologous intelligibilia, which convene to one’s own intellect” (Moutsopoulos [23], p. 206 with reference to In rem publicam, I. 63, 10–15). |
19 | Cf. MacIsaac [24], p. 60. |
20 | Chlup [1], p. 144. |
21 | Ibid., p. 17. |
22 | Cf. Chlup [1], pp. 156–157, with references to the Euclid Commentary, the Parmenides Commentary, and the Elements of Theology. |
23 | This necessary possibility refers to the crucial and evidence-based idea, that “the project of apprehension and unification with the One can only be made possible through a One-like faculty of the soul”, which, as Van Tu shows, relies on a Cognitive Likeness Principle that governs the relation between the ontological supreme reality and the soul as particular entity (cf. Tu [25]; In Alcibiadem I, 184.8–18 in Proclus [17], p. 85). |
24 | Cf. MacIsaac [24], pp. 59–60. |
25 | In Alc. 227.19–228.1, in Proclus [17], p. 105. The exact wording of this passage is as follows: φυλακτέον τὰ μέτρα τῆς ψυχῆς, καὶ τοὺς περὶ τῆς τελειώσεως λόγους οὔτε ἀπὸ τῶν σωματικῶν ἐπ’ αὐτὴν ἀναθετέον οὔτε ἀπὸ τῶν θείων εἰς αὐτὴν καθελκυστέον, ἵνα δὴ τοῦ Πλάτωνος ὦμεν ἐξηγηταὶ καὶ μὴ πρὸς ἰδίας ὑπ<ολήψεις ἀπ>ευθύνωμεν τὰς τοῦ φιλοσόφου ῥήσεις. |
26 | Cf. the reconstruction of Socrates’ standpoint (In Alc. I, 27.15–16) as demonstrating the form of dialectic through its evident implementation in practical matters (τῆς διαλεκτικῆς […] τὸ εἶδος δι’ αυτῶν τῶν ἔργων ἐπιδεικνύμενον). |
27 | A negative factor for the reception of Neoplatonism was the fact that this current in general was initially seen with suspicion and even vehemently attacked by Christians inasmuch as they felt the need to make clear distinctions between currents of thought representing similar conceptions about the Highest Being (cf. for instance Störig [26], pp. 230–231). |
28 | Cf. Schopenhauer [27], p. 12. |
29 | Cf. Iliopoulos [28], pp. 287–288. |
30 | The overall orientation of Hegel’s system reminds of certain traits in Proclus’ thought, mainly as regards the main conceptual trinitarian (speculative) figure of the movement of Being from immanence to procession and then to reversion (μονή, πρόοδος and ἐπιστροφὴ according to the Neoplatonist terminology; for a rather compact account of this conception one should primarily consult the Elements of Theology; cf. for instance 31.1–32.10 in Proclus [29], pp. 34–37; Helmig-Steel [30]; Beierwaltes [31], 251–252; about Hegel’s positive reception of Proclus cf. Hegel [32], pp. 472–474; von Aster [33], p. 108; about the major line of philosophical continuity leading from Plato to Hegel cf. Halfwassen [34], p. 278; about Feuerbach’s famous dictum discerning Hegel as the German Proclus cf. Redding [35], p. 137). It can also be pointed out that Victor Cousin in 1821 dedicated his edition of Proclus’ Parmenides Commentary to Hegel and Schelling, who were also favorable to Proclus (cf. Chlup [1], p. 284). |
References
- Chlup, R. Proclus: An Introduction; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Boys-Stones, G.R. Review of Karamanolis. In Mind, New Series; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; Volume 116, pp. 1129–1132. [Google Scholar]
- Karamanolis, G.E. Plato and Aristotle in Agreement? Platonists on Aristotle from Antiochus to Porphyry; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Kenny, A. Ancient Philosophy; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Respublica (Politeia). In Platonis Opera; Burnet, J., Ed.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1900; Volume 4. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. The Republic of Plato, 2nd ed.; Bloom, A., Ed.; Bloom, A., Translator; Basic Books: New York, NY, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Mittelstraß, J. Die Dialektik und ihre wissenschaftlichen Vorübungen (Buch VI 510 b-511 e und Buch VII 521 c-539 d). In Platon. Politeia; Höffe, O., Ed.; Akademie Verlag: Berlin, Germany, 1997; pp. 229–249. [Google Scholar]
- Sayers, S. Plato’s Republic. An Introduction; Edinburgh University Press: Edinburgh, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Sophista. In Platonis Opera; Duke, E.A., Hicken, W.F., Nicoll, W.S.M., Robinson, D.B., Strachan, J.C.G., Eds.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1995; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. A Translation of Plato’s Sophist with an Introductory Commentary; Duerlinger, J., Translator; New Perspectives in Philosophical Scholarship: Text and Issues; Peter Lang: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. Procli Diadochi in Platonis Rem Publicam Commentarii; Kroll, W., Ed.; Teubner: Leipzig, Germany, 1899. [Google Scholar]
- Vasilakis, D.A. Proclus on the First Alcibiades: From Platonic Eros to Aristotelian Friendship. In Dia-Noesis. A Journal of Philosophy; University of Western Macedonia: Athens, Greece, 2019; pp. 123–134. [Google Scholar]
- Denyer, N. Introduction; Plato: Athens, Greece, 2001; pp. 1–29. [Google Scholar]
- Ambury, J. Review of: François Renaud and Harold Tarrant. The Platonic Alcibiades I: The Dialogue and Its Ancient Reception; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2015; Available online: https://ancienthistorybulletin.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/07/AHBReviews2016.07.AmburyOnRenaudTarrant.pdf (accessed on 18 February 2025).
- Terezis, C. Διαλεκτική και θεωρία στον νεοπλατωνικό Πρόκλο. Ένα σχόλιο στον πλατωνικό διάλογο Aλκιβιάδης (Dialectics and Theory in the Neoplatonist Proclus. A Commentary on the Platonic Dialogue Alcibiades); Zitros: Salonica-Athens, Greece, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Aristoteles. Topica. In Aristotelis Opera; Bekker, I., Ed.; Prussian Academy of Sciences-Georg Reimer: Berlin, Germany, 1831; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato; Westerink, L.G., Ed.; North-Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1954. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Alcibiades I. In Platonis Opera; Burnet, J., Ed.; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1901; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. Alcibiades; Denyer, N., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. Alcibiades I: A Translation and Commentary; O’ Neill, W., Translator; Martinus Nijhoff: The Hague, The Netherlands, 1965. [Google Scholar]
- Dillon, J.; Gerson, L.P. Neoplatonic Philosophy. Introductory Readings; Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, IN, USA; Cambridge, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Aristoteles. Topik. In Sophistische Widerlegungsschlüsse; Zek, H.G., Ed.; Meiner: Hamburg, Germany, 1997; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
- Moutsopoulos, E. Philosophical Suggestions; Research Center of Greek Philosophy: Athens, Greece, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- MacIsaac, G. The Noûs of the Partial Soul in Proclus’ Commentary on the First Alcibiades of Plato. In Dionysius; Dalhousie University, Department of Classics, Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences: Halifax, Canada, 2011; Volume 29, pp. 29–60. [Google Scholar]
- Tu, V. Proclus on ἕνωσις: Knowing the One by the One in the Soul. Philosophies 2024, 9, 100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Störig, H.J. Kleine Weltgeschichte der Philosophie; Fischer: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Schopenhauer, A. Die Kunst, recht zu behalten. In Achtunddreißig Kunstgriffen Dargestellt; Anaconda: Cologne, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Iliopoulos, G. Ganzes und Teile des Politischen bei Aristoteles; Tectum Verlag: Marburg, Germany, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Proclus. The Elements of Theology; Dodds, E.R., Ed.; Dodds, E.R., Translator; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Helmig. Christoph and Carlos Steel, Proclus. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2021st ed.; Edward, N., Zalta, Eds.; Stanford University: Redwood City, CA, USA, 2021; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/proclus/ (accessed on 29 December 2024).
- Beierwaltes, W. Proklos. Grundzüge seiner Metaphysik; Vittorio Klostermann: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 1965. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie II. Werke; Moldenhauer, E., Michel, K.M., Eds.; Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 1986; Volume 19. [Google Scholar]
- von Aster, E. Geschichte der Philosophie; Kröner: Stuttgart, Germany, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Halfwassen, J. Platons Metaphysik des Einen. In Platon Verstehen. Themen und Perspektiven; van Ackeren, M., Ed.; Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: Darmstadt, Germany, 2004; pp. 263–278. [Google Scholar]
- Redding, P. Continental Idealism. Leibniz to Nietzsche; Routledge: London, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Iliopoulos, G. Dialectic in Early Proclus and the Unity of the Soul. Philosophies 2025, 10, 74. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040074
Iliopoulos G. Dialectic in Early Proclus and the Unity of the Soul. Philosophies. 2025; 10(4):74. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040074
Chicago/Turabian StyleIliopoulos, Georgios. 2025. "Dialectic in Early Proclus and the Unity of the Soul" Philosophies 10, no. 4: 74. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040074
APA StyleIliopoulos, G. (2025). Dialectic in Early Proclus and the Unity of the Soul. Philosophies, 10(4), 74. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10040074