Next Article in Journal
Traces in the History of Swedish Transnational Adoption—A Diffractive Mapping through the Voices of Adoptees and Their Parents
Next Article in Special Issue
A Hypothesis of Conspiracy to Re-Enchant the World
Previous Article in Journal
Mongolian Interethnic Marriage, Ethnic Relations, and National Integration in the PRC
Previous Article in Special Issue
Multimodal Genealogy: The Capitol Hill Riot and Conspiracy Iconography
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Sociopolitical Genealogy of Populist Conspiracy Theories in the Context of Hyperpolitics

Department of History, Humanities and Society, University of Rome Tor Vergata, 00133 Rome, Italy
Genealogy 2024, 8(2), 66; https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy8020066
Submission received: 15 March 2024 / Revised: 3 May 2024 / Accepted: 13 May 2024 / Published: 23 May 2024
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Conspiracy Theories: Genealogies and Political Uses)

Abstract

:
The wide circulation of conspiracy narratives and their frequent intertwining with populist rhetoric is both an element of concern and a topic of intense scientific and philosophical debate. The depth of the link between conspiracy theories and populism represents a crucial issue whose comprehension can facilitate understanding their specific nature and the factors behind their diffusion in public communication. To this end, it is necessary to cultivate an interdisciplinary approach and great critical attention, eschewing monocausal explanations. This paper addresses the question of the essentially political nature of conspiracism, confronting the recent epistemological debate that, by putting the positivist paradigm aside, has sought to explore and understand the socio-cultural roots of conspiracy rhetoric, with its sceptical, antagonistic and hermetic traits. By integrating the reflections of epistemologists such as Cassam or Harris with the considerations of political scientists such as Taggart and with Schmitt’s radical reflections on politics, it is perhaps possible to reintegrate the different approaches to populist conspiracism into an overall social genealogical perspective, thanks also to recent demographic elaborations. Thus, we could ascribe the spread of conspiracism to the prevalence in societies of a hyperpolitical discursive regime, i.e., founded on the principle of opposition, without the possibility of compromise, between different groups and interests. At the basis of such Manichaeism, it is plausible to place in the first place the growing inequalities and related social disintegration, which hinder the circulation of trust and recognition between individuals and groups, thus ending up undermining democracy at its roots, as a political system that legitimises and thus peacefully regulates conflict.

1. Introduction

Conspiracy Theories (from now on C.T.1) have become a topic of great political and journalistic debate in recent years, and philosophers and social scientists have also begun to realise the considerable problematic nature of the concept, epistemologically, ethically and politically (Butter and Knight 2020; Räikkä and Ritola 2020). In 2016, a candidate became president of the USA who extensively used conspiracy rhetoric and references in his campaign (Harris 2023). The dissemination of C.T.-inspired speeches has long since gained space in the public sphere, probably due to a combination of factors, although there are scholars like Butter (2014) who deny a wider diffusion of C.T.
This is why the problem I intend to address in this paper is not that of the mere existence of C.T., but the reason for their greater diffusion in specific historical moments and different social contexts rather than in others—hence the origin of such a dynamic, in the conviction that only by understanding this, it is possible to understand the very meaning of C.T. and populism.
The hypothesis that I intend to propose is that neither economic nor technological nor cultural factors, considered in isolation, can integrate an overall picture of this dynamic because, at the origin, there are structural transformations that have affected contemporary society as a whole, understood as a system of relations, which we can describe through the concept of social capital and social distance. Thus, the growing social distance resulting from the weakening of social ties represents the genealogy of the dynamic that sees populist conspiracism gaining more and more space in the public sphere. Recent research reinforces the hypothesis that growing inequalities are closely related to this growing anomie, in parallel with the crisis of democratic policies and the extension of market logic in society. The current historical situation poses a significant challenge to democracy and science. In fact, both these pillars rely on a widespread sense of trust and a general willingness for mutual recognition, which is gravely jeopardised by dissatisfaction and social disintegration. I hypothesise in conclusion that this anomic conjuncture is associated with the affirmation of a rhetorical paradigm based on the recirculating delegitimisation of the various social actors, which I call hyperpolitics and which is the basis of the typical Manichaeism found in both conspiracism and populism.
In fact, inequalities are growing at an ever-improving speed, as demonstrated in the last “Oxfam Global Report—Inequality Inc” of January 2024 (OXFAM 2024), where we can read that “The wealth of the world’s five richest billionaires has more than doubled since the start of this decade, while 60% of humanity has grown poorer […] Sharply increasing billionaire wealth and rising corporate and monopoly power are deeply connected […] […]. Profits are hugely concentrated in a few corporates: globally the largest 0.001% of firms earn roughly one-third of all corporate profits […] Every US$100 of profit generated by 96 major companies between July 2022 and June 2023, US$82 was returned to shareholders in the form of stock buybacks and dividends […] Corporate and monopoly power has exploded inequality” (p. 8, 10, 23, 35 and passim).
On closer inspection, however, the propensity to denounce conspiracies which very often do not exist dates back at least as far as the modern age (Butter 2014), although the appearance of the specific expression seems to date back to the period between the 19th and 20th centuries and its subsequent evolutions (McKenzie-McHarg 2019). It was only later and only with Popper’s reflections in the ‘30s (Popper 2006) that the expression ‘conspiracy theory’ became a way of stigmatising completely irrational when not demented forms of reasoning and worldviews (Butter and Knight 2018): this path found its acme between the 50s and 60s in Hofstadter’s (1996) which represents a milestone for any discourse on the subject, regardless of the theoretical approach adopted. On the other hand, historical and literary research has shown how, for a long time, the function of the C.T. was quite different from today: while today they convey an attitude of contestation of institutional power structures, branded as falsely democratic, for centuries the stigma that the C.T. bore was pinned precisely on the subaltern or contesting classes (Butter 2014; Thalmann 2019). This is the reason why some scholars deny at root the legitimacy of the concept of C.T. itself because they believe it is not epistemologically grounded and a stigmatising intent connotes it (Dentith 2014; Pigden 2007).
However, in this work, I refer to the definition of C.T. by Cubitt (1989), for whom they are characterised by intentionalism, dualism and occultism: every C.T. maintains that adverse events are the result of the action carried out strategically and covertly by a very minority but more powerful part of society, as opposed to the majority and less aware part. This approach almost always accompanies the moral stigmatisation of this active minority, and thus the victimisation of the part considered innocent, so it consists of an ethical-political denunciation (as a scapegoating dynamic, see Hassan 2020). From the epistemological point of view, the “self-sealing” quality is the distinctive element of C.T. whereby any element that can refute a conspiracy hypothesis is, by its proponents, converted into favourable evidence (Sunstein and Vermeule 2009)2. In this sense, C.T. are anti-scientific and inherently false since they are based on premises that deny a priori their falsifiability. In short, one could consider C.T. as inspired by a Manichean and Gnostic logic, but this result, as I mentioned, does not exhaust the debate on the matter; on the contrary, it has encountered a real critical turn, starting from the end of last century (Butter and Knight 2020).
Some scholars trace the diffusion of C.T. to the psychological or sociopsychological dimension (Abalakina-Paap et al. 1999; Van Prooijen and Douglas 2018) and Sunstein and Vermeule (2009) have focused on the cognitive-cultural aspect, questioning the epistemological fallacy that distinguishes them (crippled epistemology). Still others have emphasised how C.T. are a simple, and therefore reassuring, explanation of the current global complexity (Zajenkowski et al. 2022) holding together the epistemological and socio-psychological aspects. One strand is also the one that attributes a particularly relevant role to the introduction of new technology of communication, such as the Internet and the smartphone, at the basis of the platform society and socio-cognitive phenomena such as filter bubbles, echo chambers and misinformation (Barberis 2020).
A further strand is whether or not C.T. have an essentially political nature (and thus can be considered as ideologies). Scholars interested in this question, perhaps more than others, have shifted their attention from examining the inherently false content of conspiracy narratives to the historical-political and socio-cultural context that allows them to emerge and spread, thus to the genealogical-structural dimension.
Epistemologists such as Cassam (2019, 2023), following previous reflections by Coady (2006), have attempted to distinguish C.T. from reasonable and doubtful discourses on the existence of conspiracies (called by him simply conspiracy theories), identifying at the basis of the former the logic of Power as a force always capable of manipulating the truth. This logic should better explain how any element capable of disproving such theories is converted by their followers into evidence in favour of them, precisely as an indication of the action of hidden Power. Other scholars, who have intentionally left the epistemological issue aside, have tried to explain C.T. by framing them in a discourse that problematises the relationship between truth, Power and knowledge. These researchers argue that C.T. have a pragmatic/performative character, i.e., a political rather than narrative or, in any case, merely theoretical nature (Hristov 2019). They emphasise the background of C.T.: the present historical phase characterised by uncertainty and distrust, so that the distinctive trait of the C.T. is the parresiastic one, i.e., an index of revolt against institutional Power. Moreover, scholars such as Fenster (2008) have argued that C.T. are discourses about Power.
Finally, in the field of politology, more and more often, C.T. have been related to the other central contemporary theme, that of populism (Bergmann 2018; Castanho Silva et al. 2017)—which are often intertwined with conspiracy narratives or make opportunistic use of them. Populism and C.T. share a hostility toward institutions and their procedures, to which they counter truth and justice that reside in what they call the common people or the People and in its common sense. Both phenomena display a Manichean conception of society (Taggart 2018), based on the opposition between Us and Them: the people, i.e., the majority, and the elite, i.e., the manipulative and usurping minority of sovereignty, according to the minimalist definition of populism, now widely used, proposed by Mudde (2004). Another important trait shared by populism and C.T. is that of the problematic epistemology, also linked to the stigmatising meaning of the term.
On the other hand, in parallel, the focus on the phenomenon of populism has also been expanding, and many different approaches have been proposed (Palano 2017), both to explain its origin (economic, cultural, generational, etc.) and its various manifestations (left-wing or right-wing, protest or governing, etc.).
Significantly, just as conspiracy theorists were primarily framed in the light of the rationality paradigm, so populism was classified as a form of paralogism (Taguieff 2003; Merker 2009), but attention has gradually shifted toward the socio-historical context and the function that populism and conspiracy theorists might play within that framework. For all these reasons, as previously said, the hypothesis has gained consensus that it is better to link the question of truth with that of power more than that of knowledge in order to understand the historical and social significance of C.T. So that we can hypothesise an almost genetic link between populism and C.T. and above all, indicate an essentially political nature of the latter.
It is, therefore, a question of reintegrating the issue of populist conspiracism and its worrying rise into the field of political sociology.
Concerning the political nature of C.T., I identify three central positions: Cassam (2019, 2023), Harris (2023) and Taggart (2018): in the following, I will proceed by considering these positions in order to propose the thesis that C.T. should be understood as essentially political discourses, albeit in a broad sense, based on the theoretical elaborations of Carl Schmitt. Next, I will address the question of the origin of C.T. in the context of social structures based on recent findings. Finally, I will first reflect on the concept of hyperpolitics, understood as a highly problematic socio-cultural dimension, in its dialectical connection with the technocratic depoliticisation that has inspired much rhetoric and many government policies in recent years.

2. Political Character of Conspiracism

To try to understand conspiracism and especially its ample diffusion means trying to frame it rationally, renouncing presenting it simply as foolish and/or needing to be pigeonholed in a semantic domain entirely apart. On the contrary, rationalising the intrinsic—and often proclaimed—incongruity of conspiracy discourses means integrating them into the general context, striving to trace their links with other situations, other discursive traditions and other cultural materials.
As previously said, there are grounds for wondering whether the most effective direction of research that can be invested with this task is one that emphasises the critical relationship between C.T. and power and thus questions the nature, i.e., the function, of conspiracism as essentially political.
This is certainly not a new debate, and Popper’s reading and, on closer inspection, Hofstadter’s reading were already rooted in such a dialectical framework, but what they emphasised was the relationship between irrationality and politics (Butter and Knight 2020), which was at the basis of conspiracy understood, as we know, as a ‘conspiracy theory of society’, into which could be inserted discourses that later were no longer even appropriately considered conspiracy related.
Subsequently, the topic has been forcefully taken up, and I will focus on three fundamental positions that have emerged more recently.
The first is that of Cassam (2019), for whom C.T. represent a ‘form of political propaganda’ and are essentially, not only occasionally, political discourses.
He clarified first of all that talking about C.T. does not mean, contrary to what is argued by the proponents of the ‘neutral’ approach to this topic (e.g., Dentith 2014), talking about any discourse that mentions the possibility of a conspiracy as the cause of an event: this would go against common sense and would dissolve the concept of C.T. and, if anything, focus on that of ‘conspiracy theory phobia’, or conversely, paradoxically, present almost any critical theory of society as a C.T. in the wake of Popper.
Instead, Cassam returned to the distinction posed by Coady (2006) and Keeley (2006), based on a still fundamentally epistemological approach, between C.T. and mere talk about possible conspiracies. In particular, he emphasised that while the proponents of the ‘neutralist’ approach believe that any theory must be assessed a posteriori based on the specific examination of the evidence for or against it (so that ultimately, no theory can ever be stigmatised as conspiracy-based and therefore fallacious because as Popper explains, the empiricist approach is by definition always open), Cassam instead pointed out that it is possible to classify a priori a discourse as C.T., and therefore fallacious, precisely because it is a political-ideological discourse, given that a prejudicial contrast with an official truth characterises it. This polemical character refers to an overall, aprioristic and, in this sense, ideological view of reality that sees authorities and institutions as always and, in any case, deceptive, both political and epistemic.
In this sense, Cassam’s approach, when he presents C.T. as ideologies or at any rate as an engrossing part of political-ideological projects, can be linked back to Mannheim’s tradition of sociology of culture and Foucault’s postmodern philosophy. On this basis, he contrasted an exquisitely political approach with a purely epistemological one (which would run the risk of going around in circles) and a psychological one and can take on board the potential for general critique brought about by the C.T., pointed out by the ‘neutralists’, without, however, throwing the foundations of modern epistemology up in the air, falling into a speculative, almost nihilistic irrationalism.
On the other hand, the approach that places as the primary criterion for reliability not the content of the discourse but the identity of the person producing it, that is the logic of C.T., is an inherently anti-scientific, anti-rational and anti-democratic approach (see (Vernant 1976) on the link between rationality and democracy).
I will return to the polemical-political connection, but before, it is essential to point out, along with Cassam himself, how, of late, many conspiracy discourses are not even theories but, as explained by Muirhead and Rosenblum (2019), are ‘conspiracy without the theory’ because they no longer even strive to imitate the academic argumentative form, but instead oppose science head-on using iterative and emotive communication, which essentially consists of endlessly repeated slogans in a communicative sphere completely closed to other discursive proposals. Essentially, “The new conspiracism—all accusation and no evidence—substitutes social validation for scientific validation” (Muirhead and Rosenblum 2019, p. 3). This means that conspiracism at the bottom is never a theory but presupposes a theory; it does not seek the truth but proclaims it and takes it for granted; in essence, it is nothing more than a denunciation based on an ideological rather than a critical attitude. Moreover, I stress that such discursiveness is structurally rooted in a system of social and communicative relations. Indeed, the fragmentary and disjointed discursiveness conveyed on the Internet highlights a conspiracy mindset and, even better, a socio-cultural atmosphere characterised by resentment and polemical ardour without any self-reflexive propensity. Corresponding to the stigma toward conspiracism is the stigma toward others on the part of conspiracists, and the latter can well refute any criticism based on the principle that official knowledge is compromised with power and therefore suspect by definition.
Indeed, Cassam (2023) explains that the function of C.T. is to express and promote an ideology and that they operate in an ideological space. Cassam refers to the definition of ideology of Uscinski and Parent as “a set of interrelated beliefs that provide a way for people to understand the world. Ideologies tell people what is important, who the good guys and bad guys are, what their goals are, and how those goals should be reached” (Uscinski and Parent 2014, p. 12) and argues that the ideology founding the conspiracism is the stigmatisation of “the mainstream media and other members of the so-called elite” (Cassam 2023, p. 198). In conclusion, “The ideological motivating force of new conspiracism is not opposition to democracy as such but the belief that the status quo is not truly democratic and needs to be replaced by a different form of government that genuinely expresses the will of the people” (Ibidem). On closer inspection, C.T. corresponds to a “purely negative” (Cassam 2023, p. 194) political programme that aims to delegitimise democracy as we know it, whereby “Disorientation and delegitimation are its two main products” (Ibidem).
Nevertheless, the link between delegitimisation and C.T. is genetic. What I will try to argue is that it is also genealogical, in the sense that the delegitimisation of the authorities, and thus also of science, which characterises a significant part of public discourse, is at the origin of the very intensity and diffusion of C.T. in today’s society.
In order to understand this, it is necessary to reconnect, more than Cassam does, the social dimension closely with the political-institutional one, and I will try to do just that by reasoning on the objections that Harris posed to Cassam, recovering classic suggestions from Schmitt’s political thought, which have also been taken up by other contemporary authors.
The main objection presented by Harris (2023) to Cassam was that the “contrarian nature” of C.T. “does not imply that conspiracy theories are inherently political” (p. 22). He points out the assumption that “conspiracy theories are, by definition, contrary to the claims of authorities” (p. 23) and suggests that “This approach can be elaborated in at least two ways […]. On one approach, the relevant form of authority is governmental or otherwise related to power. According to an alternative approach, the relevant form of authority is epistemic” (Ibidem), and not accidentally, “some prominent conspiracy theories have no immediate connection to any political agenda” (Harris 2023, p. 25). For Harris, the intrinsic function of C.T. is to manifest antagonism towards authority, and often more specifically epistemic authority, as a premise to “facilitate the reassertion of epistemic autonomy” (p. 22).
Some of the examples Harris gives, such as ‘flat Eartherism’ or the supposed faked death of Elvis, would indicate the lack of political substance in many C.T. discourses and that such discourses instead end up being encompassed by populists not because of an elective affinity but because they share a bitterly polemical trait. For this reason, populist politicians have a good game in deploying opportunistic tactics to enlist many conspiracists in their ranks. However, for Harris, there is quite a distance between C.T. and populism.
In essence, at the origin of the belief in C.T., according to Harris, there is not a political ideology but “those who resent what appears from their perspective as the shaping of the epistemic landscape by alien perspectives” (Harris 2023, p. 22).
In response to this criticism, Cassam, as we have seen, argues that even those C.T. that seem to lack a political component are political in the broadest sense. They all seem to float in an ideological atmosphere that, as we have already said, is characterised by a radical scepticism towards all forms of authority. Whoever believes that the NASA missions did not reach the Moon does not only doubt the governmental authorities themselves.
For an example of the Italian social landscape, we can cite the popular support, characterized by conspiracy rhetoric, for Dr. De Donno, who proposed to cure COVID-19 with alternative methods to those supported by the national health authorities (ANSA 2021). How can one explain it if not with antagonism towards the government itself, and not only towards science, given that the doctor was an accredited specialist, albeit isolated from his colleagues?
Another reason why it is challenging to distinguish between political authorities and epistemic authorities, especially in the democratic sphere—and this is only apparently paradoxical—is that the legitimacy of epistemic authorities is at least partly based on the democratic principle: who, if not the political authorities elected by the people, is in charge of the basic rules for funding and recruiting academic, scientific, and technical institutions? Furthermore, what else of the consensus found within the vast community of scholars guarantees the public of non-experts that certain scientific positions are worthy of respect?3
All this may lead to the conclusion that it is possible to understand the nature and origin of C.T. only by reasoning in political terms, and I argue that it is possible to fully understand the origin and political character of C.T. by recovering Schmitt’s (1972) reflection on the concept of the political, supported by the interpretation of a scholar like Kervegan (2016).
The controversial German philosopher based his entire work on the idea that, on the one hand, politics does not have its specific nature (Schmitt 1972, p. 109), and on the other hand, that precisely because of this, everything could be political, especially since the distinction between the legal and the socio-political level—so to say, between institutions and what lies outside them—can only be made based on a starting point that is in itself essentially political. Perhaps this is because it is primarily political to decide what is political, i.e., legitimately debatable, as it is to decide what is not and is instead technical, whose discussion is therefore not open to all, or not at all (Kervegan 2016; Preterossi 2009).
As is well known, the other trait that characterises the political for Schmitt is the agonistic one, by which politics, it must be emphasised once again, cannot claim its own substantiality but must be understood in a dynamic and, above all, relational sense (Kervegan 2016, especially p. 165).
For this reason, I argue that we can support authors such as Cassam and hypothesise that even abstruse theories, such as those on the flat Earth, have an intrinsically political value (which their proponents often claim) and deserve the utmost consideration. In C.T., there is always an element of acute polemics towards institutions; indeed, they always seem to proceed from the identification of institutions as enemies, in Schmitt’s sense of the term, and for this reason, their nature can also be considered essentially political.
We see that the debate on C.T. helps to reveal that the real problem is what is political and what is not, leading to the topic of contemporary democratic societies and their crises. So, while Cassam asserted the political nature of C.T. and Harris denied it, political scientist Taggart (2018) (who is a scholar of populism) claimed that C.T. have a ‘non-properly political’ nature and attempted to delineate this dimension and link C.T. as well as populism to it.
Basically, for Taggart—for whom “we need to re-insert a fuller sense of populism’s relationship to politics into the definition of populism” (p. 79)—populism and conspiracism not only share a Manichean attitude (the glorification of the people and the demonisation of elites), they also share an ambiguous view of politics, precisely what he calls unpolitics, whereby in populism there is “a tendency towards conspiracy theory” (p. 84).
Taggart explains that “Unpolitics is not the same as anti-politics or being apolitical“ (p. 81), since instead, unpolitics is “the repudiation of politics as the process for resolving conflict […] but staying within a democratic frame of reference” (Ibidem). Additionally “It is clearly not apolitical as populism can lead to the full engagement in politics [even though] it is the emergence of a sense of crisis that mobilises this constituency to rise up and start to become engaged actively in politics” (Ibidem).
From this root, we would derive the propensity of populists for forms of intense antagonism, such as war, as well as for the intense moral dimension of religion, both often accompanied by the inclination towards conspiracism.
In the end, following Taggart, in populist unpolitics, we would find the genealogy of conspiracism itself, which would be confirmed as a political phenomenon, but in an ‘improper’ way, perhaps not entirely ascribable to a rational explanation.
He says that “underlying populism as an ideology is a very profound and fundamental ambivalence about politics such that it implicitly celebrates or is drawn to unpolitic” (Taggart 2018, p. 85). This defines an admittedly political attitude, but ‘in the negative’, i.e., by the absence of politics (unpolitics) as opposed to actual politics, whereby “populists will often, but not always, be pulled into narratives and ways of thinking associated with activities divergent from politics, namely war, religion and conspiracy theories” (Ibidem).
We even have a definition of politics by Taggart (2018, p. 85): “Politics as practice is about settlement”, while “Populism tends to relish unsettling politics”, whereby, in essence, politics is identified with representative procedures and liberalism, and populism again becomes an irrational form of politics, so much so as to be basically indefinable, or definable only ‘in the negative’. Here, the problematic nexus of the relationship between C.T., populism, and politics emerges again.
Indeed, Taggart admits that “I am equating politics itself with either liberalism or representative democratic politics […]. Of course, other forms of politics exist” (p. 85), arguing that “The disjuncture between unpolitics and politics is that make populism often so spectacular and so perplexing to students of politics” (Ibidem). In any case, for Taggart, “it is the confrontation of this unpolitics with the functioning of representative politics that makes populism so potent and so provocative to contemporary representative democracy” (Taggart 2018, p. 79).
Taggart concludes, “The prevalence of contemporary populism then means that we need to address what it is that makes unpolitics so palatable and politics so unpalatable to so many […]. The success of populism and the celebration of unpolitics represent perhaps a particular failing of politics at a particular time” (p. 86).
Thus, Taggart recognises the political character of the context in which C.T. are spreading but does not recognise their political nature, leaving the definition of unpolitics uncertain. In fact, it is precisely on the basis of Schmitt’s lesson that we can attribute an undoubtedly political nature to populist conspiracism precisely because of its intensely agonistic and radical character. The fact that the conspiracist and populist mentality is characterised by hostility towards liberal institutions, as everyone knows, should not be attributed to supposed unpolitics but rather to their essentially political character.
As seen, Schmitt (1972) argued that the decision on institutional arrangements always precedes these arrangements, so it is logical that the highest level of politicalness coincides with the radical questioning of the institutions themselves and their legitimacy. As Taggart recognises, on the other hand, liberal politics exist, as well as other political tendencies, albeit the latter ones are by no means peaceful and are hostile to the rational logic that should inform democracy. These tendencies derive their strength from social events, and it is by systematically considering this dimension that we can understand C.T. because, as Schmitt argues, it is at the social, pre-institutional level that politics is fully expressed so that legal institutions are formed. This is to say, it is at that level that the legitimacy of the very laws that will later be written is formed. Therefore, continuing the reasoning on the political nature of C.T. will allow us to grasp its rootedness in an overall socio-historical situation.

3. Conclusions: Social-Psychological Genealogy of Conspiracism and Populism as a (Hyper)Political Phenomenon

In this section, I will attempt to propose a synthesis of what I have outlined above, putting forward a hypothesis on the genealogy of populist conspiracism.
As I anticipated, Harris rightly identifies in conspiracists a feeling of cultural alienation, which drives them to elaborate polemical discourses against science and its institutions. Hence, he considers the political trait of C.T. to be only secondary to the quest for epistemic autonomy. This is his alternative hypothesis to that proposed by Cassam. But as Lee Basham (2006, p. 67) wrote, “The background suspicion of most conspiracy theorists is that public institutions are and perhaps always have been untrustworthy”, and it would be wrong to “imagine that conspiracy theorists begin in isolation from this broader scepticism”. In essence, Harris does not question why so many people are embarrassed by contemporary science and, in fact, denies that there is a root connection between political antagonism and feelings of cultural alienation—while Taggart locates the roots of conspiracy theorists and populism in the social situation but does not clearly answer why so many are embarrassed by the workings of politics, and Cassam instead traces C.T. almost exclusively to a reactionary cultural tradition (Cassam 2023, p. 198).
On the other hand, as we have previously mentioned, the ideology underpinning C.T. is nourished by a radical scepticism toward both democratic institutions and modern thought itself, and their epistemological approach is directed against both science and liberal democracy, so once again, it is difficult to distinguish the polemic against government authorities from that against scientific authorities.
The point is that C.T. must be approached from an interdisciplinary perspective because neither the epistemic nor the political or other factors can be understood outside a systematic sociological approach. From where does this come? The hypothesis I propose to account for the extreme polarisation that characterises our age, which I believe is reflected in the Manichean tendencies of C.T. and populism, is that recent work in social statistics is very useful. As we have seen, research such as that conducted by OXFAM (2024) confirms the growing social inequalities characterising today’s society, so we could argue that polarisation, in turn, originates from inequalities and social disintegration. Actually, this dynamic and its connection to the spread of populism and conspiracism were found in a very recent demoscopic exploration (Golob et al. 2023) by a team that interrogated the statistics made available by the European Social Survey4. This research tested the link between social fragmentation and political-cultural divisions, and in particular between social stratification on the one hand and trust in democracy or inclination toward populism and conspiracism on the other, coming to find how the simultaneous lack of social, cultural, and economic resources, in individuals, proves to be a predictor of the inclination toward populism and conspiracism (see pages 31, 50 particularly). This study, hinging on the concept of social capital5 valued by authors such as Bourdieu (2001), confirmed how greater social inequalities are accompanied by a deterioration of general social capital, fuelling among citizens distrust, disorientation, and thus a sense of distance from institutions, something that threatens the survival of representative democracy. In fact, each person’s social capital consists of a network of exchanges—and the contribution that each element of the network makes to the others—whose limit “also constitutes the limit of the group beyond which there can be no legitimate exchange” (Moro 2007, p. 167, my transl.) so that it can be said that through social capital “passes not only mutual recognition but also denial and discrimination” (Moro 2007, p. 168). Thus, it is precisely from the decay of social capital that a growing social distance6 originates, understood as “the relational unavailability and closure […] of a subject toward others perceived […] as different on the basis of their traceability to social categories” (Introini and Lo Verde 2007, p. 44, my transl.). We might hypothesise here, then, that the Manichean distinction between Us/People and Them/Elites, which is the cornerstone of populist and conspiracist rhetoric (and ideology), represents the symbolic-spatial crystallisation of this process of social distancing and consequent delegitimisation and stigmatisation at the political level. In order to explain this phenomenon, or rather the dynamic whereby conspiratorial and populist discourses, in recent years, have been gaining ever larger shares of the public sphere, I propose an essentially political reading, rooted in the social, supplementing the reflections of a scholar like Cassam with references to Schmitt’s thought. In fact, for the German jurist, what characterises the political is the essentially relational nature, by virtue of which everything can become political, and in addition, the agonistic dimension, more or less intense, that invests the formation and functioning of institutions. In essence, for Schmitt, the political dimension is not to be confused with the properly legal-institutional dimension, of which it constitutes the premise: in fact, the very legitimacy of every institution, including epistemic institutions, is the fruit of a decision that is placed at the level of social reality, that is, of social relations, and which is never final. This is to say that the problem posed by conspiracies and populisms is essentially a problem of the social legitimacy of institutions, which, however, should not be deciphered with only an epistemological-cultural, economic, or politological paradigm because each of these approaches fails to grasp the radical nature of the problem at hand but grasps only one aspect of it among many.
Confirming this, research such as that of Golob et al. (2023) shows that populist conspiracism is associated with the decrease in social, cultural, and economic capital, along with increased social disintegration and distance, in a context of increasing socioeconomic inequality.
To recognise the essentially political root of populist conspiracism, in the sense that it invests the legitimacy of our institutional system at its root, is thus to recognise that the problem such phenomena pose invests the functioning and structure of our societies as a whole and no reductionist approach, be it epistemological, psychological, or political, is appropriate since we are talking about the symptom of an overall crisis of Western civilisation.
I hypothesise, in conclusion, that this anomic conjuncture should be associated with the establishment of a rhetorical paradigm based on the recirculating delegitimisation of various social actors, which I call hyperpolitics, and it is the basis of the typical Manichaeism found in both conspiracism and populism. What I propose to call hyperpolitics, developing suggestions from Esposito (2020) and Sloterdijk (2020), consists precisely of the social atmosphere characterised at once by the extension of an extreme polemical paradigm of politics to every sphere of social communication and by the extreme radicalisation of positions, such that there seems to be absolutely no room for compromise, and the rule that prevails is that of mutual complete delegitimisation and non-recognition of different social and political actors. It is this atmosphere of distrust that feeds the Manichean and aggressive rhetoric of populist conspiracism. This psychological-social atmosphere of widespread and extreme conflictuality is the direct expression of an anonymous and increasingly less integrated society and has to be conceptualised in a dynamic sense. It can correspond to that process of decivilisation that Elias (1982, 1983) speaks of, i.e., increasing disintegration leading to the re-emergence of identitarianism, prejudice, and violence—thus to the spread of an acute feeling of social distance. While civilisation progressively leads to substituting trust for violence through increasing interdependence and mutual recognition, decivilisation represents the reverse process. Tipaldo et al. (2022) have already linked pseudoscientific polemics and Elias’ decivilisation, a dynamism due to decreasing social cohesion that goes hand in hand with the decrease in generalised trust. This social atmosphere is often instrumentalised by the polarising rhetoric that inspires populistic and conspiracist movements and their criticism of liberal-democratic institutions.
Recently, Jäger (2023) has also recovered the term hyperpolitics in a series of publications: at the center of the proposed reflection, there is the transition from the post-political phase (i.e., of depoliticisation) following 1989 to the later phase of intense, chaotic, and sterile politicisation, i.e., transformation into a field of conflict of a wide variety of issues previously removed from the public sphere (with a large role played by the new media, of course), as if the tendencies identified by Schmitt were coming back into vogue, through the activism of masses formed by solitudes not united by a project but only by resentment (see also Hassan 2020; Mishra 2017). Already scholars such as Bazzicalupo (2014) and Bickerton and Accetti (2021) have argued that such a hyperpolitical dynamic should be related to the technocratic depoliticisation and the technopopulism that have been widely held views in recent decades because this vision, which started from the distinction between technical and political, has ended up subjugating political democracy to technical-economic globalization, realising a process that is exquisitely political and that recalls Crouch’s postdemocracy (see also Müller 2022). In fact, if every technical knowledge presents itself as an objective solution to problems regardless of the position of the actors in the field—and is therefore genuinely apolitical—differently, politics cannot claim a technical status (Schmitt 1972) since it arises from the interplay of different social actors and is a space to choose, so that what characterises it is only a method that legitimises or does not legitimise the diversity of positions—without prejudice to the competitive character that distinguishes it. Instead, with neoliberalism, the legitimacy of the competitive dimension has been transferred to the market level, leaving politics with a merely executive administrative role and depriving all social conflict of legitimacy. In this sense, Bazzicalupo considers depoliticization as an actual political dynamic, and Bickerton and Accetti reflect on techno-populism, understood as rhetoric that delegitimises divergent political positions by advocating the possibility and, indeed, the necessity of following impartial and overriding economic-scientific criteria. All of these authors link depoliticization to financial globalisation and scholars such as Crouch (2003) argue that this very process, dispossessing states of their ability to develop egalitarian policies, contributes to tearing apart the socio-cultural fabric and ultimately weakening democracy itself.
So, if democratic-liberal politics was precisely the kind of politics that legitimised differences and conflicts and thus prevented the triggering of a warlike dynamic, we could argue then that it is not an apolitical discourse that informs conspiracism and populism but rather an extreme political discourse, in the sense that it advocates politics as a contrast between enemies and friends: a form of Manichaeism that, as mentioned, the two phenomena share. Such a discourse, however, is not born against politics; it is a hyperpolitical discourse, in the sense that it asserts the intrinsically competitive nature of politics, in antithesis to that depoliticising discourse of neoliberalism which, by claiming to deny the dissimilarity of interests, based on a technical paradigm (i.e., respect for the global financial market), does not facilitate their conciliation but, precisely by delegitimising competition, comes to fuel conflict and hyperpolitics, beyond institutional and epistemic limits. That is the horizon that risks looming in our future, in which populist conspiracy narratives are dystopias that take the place of historical ideologies and religions.
In sum, if conspiracism is linked to the crisis of science, this can be traced back to a general socio-political problem, which coincides with hyper-politics. Indeed, both democracy and modern science are based on the principle of discoursive reason in the Habermasian way, and this, in turn, on the trust that it is possible to agree on some basic assumptions about what is true or false: I here propose that the collective malaise that arises from social disintegration affects not only governmental institutions but also epistemic institutions and science because, and that with increased estrangement there is instead less willingness for mutual recognition, at least on the part of those who perceive that they have the least to gain in the current socio-historical situation. The result is the social polarisation that nurtures both populism and the systematic scepticism (Musgrave 1995) that underlies conspiracy theories and the “politicisation of science” (Lewandowsky et al. 2013) or “epistemic populism.” In conclusion, we could argue that the spread of populist conspiracism is the expression of that “empty secret” of Simmelian ascendancy (Eco 2020), which is a tool of Power. It’s the correspondence of the lack of politics in the era of postdemocracy that induces a hyperpolitical attitude which, by claiming the myth of a redemptive democracy (Canovan 2005), delegitimises every institutional level. This attitude ends up materialising in a mythology (Jesi 1989) of Power, which, in the face of inequalities that belie the egalitarian assumptions of democracy, places precisely Power as the exclusive criterion at the expense of any value, including truth.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Marco Solinas for having invited me to submit my article to Genealogy and for his comments and suggestions.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

Notes

1
See below Cassam’s (2019) distinction between “Conspiracy Theory” and “conspiracy theory”.
2
See also Eco’s (1990) concept of classical hermetic semiosis as an antecedent of this logic.
3
See Levy (2007). For a recent pragmatic account of the relationship between science and democracy, see Barrotta (2016). For a problematic reading of the instrumental political stigmatisation of conspiracism, in addition to Thalmann (2019), already cited, see, for example, Di Cesare (2021).
4
The European Social Survey (ESS) is an academically driven cross-national survey, headquartered at City, Univer-sity of London, that has been conducted every two years across Europe since 2001. The survey measures the atti-tudes, beliefs and behaviour patterns of diverse populations in more than thirty nations using the highest methodo-logical standards.
5
For an overall account of the usefulness of the concept of social capital in a systematic approach to sociology, see also Andriani (2013). Here, I refer to social capital primarily understood as the trust that circulates in a community characterised by a dense web of reciprocal relationships (see also Putnam et al. 1993).
6
It is a conceptual tool with great hermeneutic potential that owes its first formulation to Simmel (1998), who attributes to it “a dual role: descriptive on the one hand, and epistemological on the other”, as Cesareo (2007, p. 11, my transl.) recalls. With a group of collaborators, Cesareo has committed himself to the critical revision and consequent recovery of the concept of social distance.

References

  1. Abalakina-Paap, Marina, Walter G. Stephan, Traci Craig, and W. Larry Gregory. 1999. Beliefs in Conspiracies. Political Psychology 20: 637–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Andriani, Luca. 2013. Social Capital: A Road Map of Theoretical Frameworks and Empirical Limitations. Working Paper. London: Birkbeck College, University of London. [Google Scholar]
  3. ANSA. 2021. Redazione Ansa. Covid: Morto suicida il medico De Donno, avviò la cura con il plasma iperimmune. Ansa.it. Available online: https://www.ansa.it/sito/notizie/cronaca/2021/07/27/covid-morto-suicida-il-medico-de-donno-avvio-la-cura-con-il-plasma-iperimmune_20c46e01-af05-478e-9150-408149dd75d8.html (accessed on 27 July 2021).
  4. Barberis, Mauro. 2020. La scatola delle meraviglie. Tre spiegazioni del populismo. In L’età dei Populismi. Un’analisi Politica e Sociale. Edited by Antonio Masala and Lorenzo Viviani. Firenze: Carocci. [Google Scholar]
  5. Barrotta, Pierluigi. 2016. Scienza e Democrazia: Verità, Fatti e Valori in Una Prospettiva Pragmatista. Firenze: Carocci. [Google Scholar]
  6. Basham, Lee. 2006. “Living with the Conspiracy”. In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate. Edited by David Coady. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Limited, pp. 61–76. [Google Scholar]
  7. Bazzicalupo, Laura. 2014. Come in uno specchio: Populismo e governamentalità neoliberale. Cambio 8: 25–34. [Google Scholar]
  8. Bergmann, Eirikur. 2018. Conspiracy & Populism. The Politics of Misinformation. London and New York: Palgrave. [Google Scholar]
  9. Bickerton, Christopher J., and Carlo Invernizzi Accetti. 2021. Technopopulism: The New Logic of Democratic Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2001. La Distinzione. Bologna: Società Editrice Il Mulino. [Google Scholar]
  11. Butter, Michael. 2014. Plots, Designs, and Schemes: American Conspiracy Theories from the Puritans to the Present. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
  12. Butter, Michael, and Peter Knight. 2018. The History of Conspiracy Theory Research: A Review and Commentary. In Conspiracy Theories and the People Who Believe in Them. Edited by Joseph E. Uscinski. New York: Oxford Academic. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Butter, Michael, and Peter Knight. 2020. General introduction. In Routledge Handbook of Conspiracy Theories, 1st ed. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Canovan, Margaret. 2005. The People. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
  15. Cassam, Quassim. 2019. Conspiracy Theories. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
  16. Cassam, Quassim. 2023. Conspiracy Theories. Society 60: 190–99. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  17. Castanho Silva, Bruno, Federico Vegetti, and Levente Littvay. 2017. The Elite Is Up to Something: Exploring the Relation between Populism and Belief in Conspiracy Theories. Swiss Political Science Review 23: 423–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Cesareo, Vincenzo. 2007. Rivisitare la distanza sociale. In La Distanza Sociale. Edited by Vincenzo Cesareo. Milano: Franco Angeli. [Google Scholar]
  19. Coady, David. 2006. Conspiracy Theories and Official Stories. In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate, 1st ed. Edited by David Coady. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Limited. [Google Scholar]
  20. Crouch, Colin. 2003. Postdemocrazia. Roma-Bari: Laterza. [Google Scholar]
  21. Cubitt, Geoffrey T. 1989. Conspiracy Myths and Conspiracy Theories. Journal of the Anthropological Society of Oxford 20: 12–26. [Google Scholar]
  22. Dentith, Matthew R. X. 2014. The Philosophy of Conspiracy Theories. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
  23. Di Cesare, Donatella. 2021. Il Complotto al Potere. Torino: Einaudi. [Google Scholar]
  24. Eco, Umberto. 1990. I Limiti dell’Interpretazione. Milano: Bompiani. [Google Scholar]
  25. Eco, Umberto. 2020. Il Complotto. Milano: La Nave di Teseo. [Google Scholar]
  26. Elias, Norbert. 1982. Il Processo di Civilizzazioneː La Civiltà delle Buone Maniere. Translated by G. Panzieri. Bologna: Società Editrice Il Mulino. [Google Scholar]
  27. Elias, Norbert. 1983. Il Processo di Civilizzazioneː Potere e Civiltà. Translated by G. Panzieri. Bologna: Società Editrice Il Mulino. [Google Scholar]
  28. Esposito, Roberto. 2020. Pensiero Istituente. Tre Paradigmi di Ontologia Política. Torino: Einaudi. [Google Scholar]
  29. Fenster, Mark. 2008. Conspiracy Theories: Secrecy and Power in American Culture, 2nd ed. London: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
  30. Golob, Tea, Maruša Gorišek, and Matej Makarovič. 2023. Authoritarian and Populist Challenges to Democracy Correspond to a Lack of Economic, Social, and Cultural Capitals. Societies 13: 181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  31. Harris, Keith Raymond. 2023. Conspiracy Theories, Populism, and Epistemic Autonomy. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 9: 21–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  32. Hassan, Claudia Gina. 2020. Populism, Racism and Scapegoat. In Clockwork Enemy. Xenophobia and Racism in the Era of Neo-Populism. Edited by Alfredo Alietti and Dario Padovan. Milano: Mimesis International, pp. 221–39. [Google Scholar]
  33. Hofstadter, Richard. 1996. The paranoid style in American politics. In The Paranoid Style in American Politics and Other Essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 3–40. [Google Scholar]
  34. Hristov, Todor. 2019. Impossible Knowledge: Conspiracy Theories, Power, and Truth. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  35. Introini, Fabio, and Fabio Massimo Lo Verde. 2007. Studiare la distanza sociale. Il quadro di riferimento. In La Distanza Sociale. Edited by Vincenzo Cesareo. Milano: Franco Angeli. [Google Scholar]
  36. Jäger, Anton. 2023. Everything is Hyperpolitical. A genealogy of the present. The Point Mag, February 22, 29. [Google Scholar]
  37. Jesi, Furio. 1989. Mito. Milano: Mondadori. [Google Scholar]
  38. Keeley, Brian L. 2006. Of Conspiracy Theories. In Conspiracy Theories: The Philosophical Debate. Edited by David Coady. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing Limited. [Google Scholar]
  39. Kervegan, Jean-François. 2016. Che Fare di Carl Schmitt? Roma: Laterza. Bari: Laterza. [Google Scholar]
  40. Levy, Neil. 2007. Radically Socialized Knowledge and Conspiracy Theories. Episteme 4: 181–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  41. Lewandowsky, Stephan, Gilles E. Gignac, and Klaus Oberauer. 2013. The Role of Conspiracist Ideation and Worldviews in Predicting Rejection of Science. PLoS ONE 8: e75637. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  42. McKenzie-McHarg, Andrew. 2019. Conspiracy theory: The nineteenth-century prehistory of a twentieth century concept. In Conspiracy Theories and the People Who Believe Them. Edited by Joseph E. Uscinski. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 62–81. [Google Scholar]
  43. Merker, Nicolao. 2009. Filosofie del Populismo. Roma: Laterza. Bari: Laterza. [Google Scholar]
  44. Mishra, Pankaj. 2017. Age of Anger: A History of the Present. London: Allen Lane. [Google Scholar]
  45. Moro, Giuseppe. 2007. Reti e distanza sociale. In La Distanza Sociale. Edited by Vincenzo Cesareo. Milano: Franco Angeli. [Google Scholar]
  46. Mudde, Cas. 2004. The Populist Zeitgeist. Government and Opposition 39: 541–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Muirhead, Russell, and Nancy L. Rosenblum. 2019. A Lot of People Are Saying: The New Conspiracism and the Assault on Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  48. Müller, Jan-Werner. 2022. What, If Anything, Do Populism and Conspiracy Theories Have to Do With Each Other? Social Research: An International Quarterly 89: 607–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Musgrave, Alan. 1995. Senso Comune, Scienza e Scetticismo. Firenze: Raffello Cortina. [Google Scholar]
  50. OXFAM. 2024. Oxfam Global Report—Inequality Inc. How Corporate Power Divides Our World and the Need for a New Era of Public Action. Available online: https://policy-practice.oxfam.org/resources/inequality-inc-how-corporate-power-divides-our-world-and-the-need-for-a-new-era-621583 (accessed on 4 March 2024).
  51. Palano, Damiano. 2017. Populismo. Firenze: Editrice Bibliografica. [Google Scholar]
  52. Pigden, Charles. 2007. Conspiracy Theories and the Conventional Wisdom. Episteme 4: 219–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Popper, Karl. 2006. The Conspiracy Theory of Society. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  54. Preterossi, Geminello. 2009. L’ovvia verità del ‘politico’. Diritto e ostilità in Carl Schmitt. Quaderni Fiorentini per la Storia del Pensiero Giuridico Moderno 38: 43–74. [Google Scholar]
  55. Putnam, Robert D., Robert Leonardi, and Rafaella Y. Nanetti. 1993. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  56. Räikkä, Juha, and Juho Ritola. 2020. Philosophy and conspiracy theories. In Routledge Handbook of Conspiracy Theories, 1st ed. Edited by Michael Butter and Peter Knight. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Schmitt, Carl. 1972. Il concetto di “político”. In Le Categorie del Politico. Edited by Gianfranco Miglio and Pierangelo Schiera. Bologna: Società Editrice Il Mulino. [Google Scholar]
  58. Simmel, Georg. 1998. Sociologia. Translated by Giorgio Giordano. Milano: Edizioni di Comunità. [Google Scholar]
  59. Sloterdijk, Peter. 2020. Sulla Stessa Barca. Saggio sull’Iperpolitica. Edited by Alessandro De Cesaris. Pisa: ETS. [Google Scholar]
  60. Sunstein, Cass, and Adrian Vermeule. 2009. Conspiracy Theories: Causes and Cures. Journal of Political Philosophy 17: 202–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Taggart, Paul. 2018. Populism and ‘unpolitics’. In Populism and the Crisis of Democracy. Edited by Gregor Fitzi, Juergen Mackert and Bryan Turner. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  62. Taguieff, Pierre-André. 2003. L’Illusione Populista. Translated by Alberto Bramati. Milano: Feltrinelli. [Google Scholar]
  63. Thalmann, Katharina. 2019. The Stigmatization of Conspiracy Theory since the 1950s: “A Plot to Make Us Look Foolish”. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  64. Tipaldo, Giuseppe, Sara Rocutto, Carlotta Merlo, and Fabio Bruno. 2022. Sintomi di decivilizzazione nella costruzione social dell’expertise su Facebook e altri media durante la pandemia da COVID-19: Quadro teorico e primi risultati di ricerca. Quaderni di Sociologia 89: 47–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Uscinski, Joseph E., and Joseph M. Parent. 2014. American Conspiracy Theories. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  66. Van Prooijen, Jan-Willem, and Karen M. Douglas. 2018. Belief in conspiracy theories: Basic principles of an emerging research domain. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. 48: 897–908. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  67. Vernant, Jean Pierre. 1976. Le Origini del Pensiero Greco. Roma: Editori Riuniti. [Google Scholar]
  68. Zajenkowski, Marcin, Jeremiasz Górniak, Kajetan Wojnarowski, Małgorzata Sobol, and Peter K. Jonason. 2022. I need some answers, now!: Present time perspective is associated with holding conspiracy beliefs. Personality and Individual Differences 196: 111723. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Esposito, A. Sociopolitical Genealogy of Populist Conspiracy Theories in the Context of Hyperpolitics. Genealogy 2024, 8, 66. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy8020066

AMA Style

Esposito A. Sociopolitical Genealogy of Populist Conspiracy Theories in the Context of Hyperpolitics. Genealogy. 2024; 8(2):66. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy8020066

Chicago/Turabian Style

Esposito, Alessio. 2024. "Sociopolitical Genealogy of Populist Conspiracy Theories in the Context of Hyperpolitics" Genealogy 8, no. 2: 66. https://doi.org/10.3390/genealogy8020066

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop