1. Introduction
In his early and deep contributions to the insurance economics literature,
Borch (
1960,
1962) made the assumption that the decision-maker’s utility function depends only upon his/her final wealth. This assumption was adopted for decades in the analysis of insurance choice, and a recent survey of this literature by
Schlesinger (
2013) confirms this observation.
An exception to Borch’s assumptions resulted from the distinction made by
Segal and Spivak (
1990) between second-order and first-order risk aversion (respectively, SORA and FORA). While under SORA (as for Borch) the utility function of final wealth is always differentiable, it exhibits (at least) one point of non-differentiability under FORA, and this assumption has important consequences for the insured’s optimal behavior. For instance, under FORA,
Mossin’s (
1968) famous claim about the non-optimality of full insurance under a positive premium loading may no longer hold.
More recently,
Guo et al. (
2016) have proposed a model of choice in which the decision-maker’s risk-averse utility function depends upon two arguments: his/her final wealth and the level of losses or gains relative to a reference level.
1 Guo et al. (
2016) consider only the implications of their model for the stochastic dominance literature and do not discuss the implications for insurance demand.
It is precisely the purpose of the present paper to analyze the implications of
Guo et al.’s (
2016) model for the analysis of insurance decisions. It is worth observing that Guo’s model provides new perspectives about optimal behavior with respect to insurance choices. Additionally, since Guo’s model presents some similarities (but also differences) with the FORA case developed by
Segal and Spivak (
1990), we also extend a result derived by
Segal and Spivak (
1990) for binary risks to any distribution of losses.
In the context of proportional insurance, this extension creates a link between features of the insurance contract and the Omega performance measure, a concept often used in the quantitative finance literature (see, e.g.,
Keating and Shadwick 2002). Based on the Omega measure, we obtain a necessary and sufficient condition for the optimality of full coverage and illustrate its similarities with some recent works on stochastic orderings (
Müller et al. 2016) and optimal portfolio choices (
Bernard and Ghossoub 2010).
A necessary and sufficient condition for the optimality of full coverage is also derived in the context of deductible insurance, in which the extension of Segal and Spivak’s result to a general loss distribution is shown to be possible under Guo’s model.
Based on a comparative analysis of insurance decisions under FORA and SORA, we prove that FORA always stimulates the demand for insurance coverage relative to SORA, leading to either a higher co-insurance rate or a lower level of deductible. These findings can help explain some empirical “anomalies” in risky choices that have been documented for some agents in real insurance markets, namely that people tend to over-insure against modest risks (
Schmidt 2016) and that many customers purchase low deductibles despite costs exceeding expected losses (
Sydnor 2010).
Our analysis differs from
Schmidt (
2016) substantially. Whereas
Schmidt (
2016) uses a single-argument value function specified as a power function of gains and losses, our results are derived for a two-argument utility model and for a general specification of the gain/loss function (not necessarily power-based). Different than
Schmidt (
2016), we work with general loss distributions (rather than with binary risks) and we allow a positively loaded insurance premium. Our approach is therefore instrumental to analyze the impact of FORA on the decision to take up full coverage when insurance contracts are priced above their actuarially fair value, as usually happens in real-world circumstances.
In Guo’s model, preferences are consistent with a set of stochastic dominance rules for ordering risks in the presence of an exogenous target. Based on these rules, we prove an extension of Arrow’s theorem of the deductible (
Arrow 1974) showing that, under FORA, risk-averse decision-makers maintain a preference for concentrating insurance coverage in the states with the largest losses. Hence, a straight deductible policy is proved to be the optimal choice relative to other forms of insurance contracts.
Guo et al. (
2016) were not the first to propose the reference-dependent utility model. Its origins date back to
Köszegi and Rabin (
2006,
2007), whose work stimulated an impressive stream of theoretical research aimed at investigating how FORA is embedded in alternative models of non-expected utility (see
Masatlioglu and Raymond (
2016), for a complete taxonomy). Our framework is, on the one hand, more specific than that of Masatlioglu and Raymond and permits the derivation of some relevant results under milder conditions. On the other hand, our setting is a bit different from that of the aforementioned authors since we consider an exogenous reference point instead of an endogenous one.
Other important precursors of
Guo et al. (
2016) are the papers of
Cox and Sadiraj (
2006,
2008),
Schmidt et al. (
2008), and
Sugden (
2003), who all pointed out an “income-and-wealth” characterization of utility. In particular, a promising direction for future research is the “Third-generation prospect theory” introduced by
Schmidt et al. (
2008) combining reference dependence, decision weights, and an uncertain reference point. Based on these considerations, we believe that it may be useful to explore the implications of allowing a two-argument utility function for insurance demand, and we show here that the model of
Guo et al. (
2016) provides a tractable framework for this analysis.
Our paper is organized as follows. In
Section 2, we describe the model and its specificities for the measurement of local risk aversion. Proportional insurance is covered in
Section 3, while in
Section 4 we turn to deductible insurance. Alternative forms of insurance contracts are compared in
Section 5.
Section 6 includes a discussion of our findings in connection with some recent literature and a few conclusions.
2. Model and Notation
A decision-maker (DM) with initial wealth
is exposed to a random loss
L defined on
where
is the potential maximum loss. We denote by
the cumulative distribution function of
L and by
its expected value. Initial wealth is assumed fixed and known to the DM.
2The DM may purchase an insurance contract that compensates the occurrence of a loss by an indemnity , with . The premium charged for the contract is assumed proportional to the expected indemnity, , where is the loading factor. The final wealth of an insured agent is thus given by .
Under FORA, the DM’s utility function is concave with (at least) one point of non-differentiability. Such a situation may arise because of utility loss aversion
3 as recently argued by
Guo et al. (
2016). Their model combines a classical outcome-based utility function, which reflects intrinsic taste for end-period wealth, with a Kahneman–Tversky value function, which describes the sensation of gain or loss induced by deviations from a reference wealth level. Formally, the DM’s reference-dependent utility is specified by
where
r is a fixed (exogenous) reference point,
u is a concave utility function of wealth, and
is a piecewise linear value function:
Here,
is a positive parameter that represents the relative weight of gain–loss utility, while
is the magnitude of loss aversion. In the limit case of
, the reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (
1) is only composed of a Kahneman–Tversky value function (see
Guo et al. (
2016), for a formal proof). For computational purposes, the utility function expressed by Equation (
1) may be rewritten as follows:
For reference-dependent utility models, the choice of the target or reference wealth
r plays a central role. In a paper dealing with portfolio choice under cumulative prospect theory,
Bernard and Ghossoub (
2010) argue that the target corresponds to “the amount the individual would have received at the end of the period had he invested all of his initial wealth in the risk-free asset.” In a sense in the portfolio problem, the target corresponds to the choice of a zero risk situation. The equivalent target in an insurance problem is a situation, where the DM is fully insured, so one interesting way to define the reference wealth
r is given by
This reference point was also considered in an insurance setting by
Schmidt (
2016), who refers to Equation (
4) as the “safe alternative”.
Indeed, the definition of the reference point is critical and may be a subjective choice. Alternative approaches were suggested, for instance, by
Köszegi and Rabin (
2006,
2007) (who considered as a reference point for practical purposes the expected value of a lottery), by
Gul (
1991) (who used the certainty equivalent), and by
Schmidt et al. (
2008) (who argued in favor of an uncertain reference point). A variety of possible characterizations for the reference point were empirically tested by
Baillon et al. (
2016), who found that approximately
of subjects involved in an experimental study chose a fixed reference point consisting of either the status quo (given by the participation fee paid to subjects enrolled in the study), or a security level (given by the maximum of the minimal outcome of the prospects in a choice). As is common practice in empirical studies, the experiment of
Baillon et al. (
2016) involved choices among speculative gambles, i.e., lotteries in which the risk could result in either a loss or a gain to the agent.
As pointed out by
Sydnor (
2010), insurance decisions are different from speculative gambles because their consequences are determined entirely in the loss domain. It is therefore questionable whether the status quo (corresponding to initial wealth without taking up insurance) could be an appropriate reference point for a two-argument utility model. Conversely, a safe alternative is available if subjects take up full insurance (
Schmidt 2016), and some empirical evidence reported in
Baillon et al. (
2016) is also consistent with a security-based rule according to which subjects adopt the maximum outcome they can reach for sure as the reference point (see
Baillon et al. (
2016), footnote 4 and online appendix).
In the following sections, we analyze optimal insurance demand using Equation (
4) as the reference point. A comparative statics analysis is included in
Section 3 to illustrate the impact of changes in
r.
First-Order Risk Aversion, Loss Aversion, and Local Risk Attitude
The reference-dependent utility
v specified in Equation (
1) is always concave
4 owing to the concavity of
u and the piecewise linearity of the value function
. However, in contrast with recent literature on downside loss aversion within the EU framework (see, e.g.,
Eeckhoudt et al. (
2016);
Jarrow and Zhao (
2006); references therein), neither loss aversion nor the gain–loss component introduced via Equation (
2) affect the degree of local risk aversion of
u away from the reference point. It is straightforward to verify that, for all
, the Arrow–Pratt coefficient of absolute risk aversion (ARA) for
v is given by
We now examine local risk attitudes at the reference point considering a real number
t and a zero-mean risk
with cumulative distribution function
valued in
. Denote by
the risk premium that a DM with utility function expressed by Equation (
3) associates to the outcome
. This risk premium is defined by
where
.
In accordance with
Davies and Satchell (
2007), we examine the characteristics of
for sufficiently small risks by taking a first-order Taylor approximation around the reference point on the left-hand side (LHS) of the above equation:
and a second-order approximation around
r on the right-hand side (RHS):
For notational simplicity we denote the conditional mean and variance of
, given
, as
and
, and, given
, as
and
, respectively. Based on Equation (
3), the approximation on the RHS above can be rewritten as
where
because
is a zero-mean risk, and
.
From
, we finally obtain
Based on Equation (
5), we may decompose the total risk premium
into the sum of two terms. The first term
represents the first-order effect of loss aversion on risk attitude. The sign of this effect is always positive as long as
and
. Differentiating both sides of Equation (
5) with respect to
t, we obtain, at
,
which is a special case of Segal and Spivak’s (1990) result
5 at points where the utility function is not differentiable. This shows that, in the reference-dependent utility model of
Guo et al. (
2016), the risk premium
for small risks is proportional to
t rather than
, i.e., loss aversion induces FORA at
r.
The second term
shows the effect of curvature of the utility function
v in Guo’s model in Equation (
3) and is analogous to the classical Arrow–Pratt risk premium associated to the basic utility
u:
where
is the total variance of
. Comparing Equation (
6) with
, it appears that
so the presence of loss aversion lowers the effect of utility curvature by a factor that depends on the upper variance
of the zero-mean risk. This reflects the change in (second-order) risk perception across the reference point induced by loss aversion.
Moreover, by Equations (
5) and (
6),
and, consequently,
Since the focus of our analysis is on small risks, i.e., around
, Equation (
8) implies that loss aversion induces higher risk aversion at
r.
As
Segal and Spivak (
1990) have pointed out, for small risks, a DM is almost risk-neutral under SORA (i.e., for
in Guo’s model) because a differentiable utility function is almost linear in a neighborhood of
r. As the Arrow–Pratt risk premium expressed by Equation (
6) under SORA is proportional to
, the DM evaluates small risks essentially by their expected value and is always willing to take up very small gambles that are in his/her favor.
Conversely, a DM may reject a small gamble under FORA if the expected yield is positive but sufficiently small, which is a consequence of his/her risk attitude being of order 1. By similar arguments,
Segal and Spivak (
1990) have argued (and have proved for binary risks) that people may buy full insurance under FORA even though they have to pay some marginal loading. This behavior will be studied in detail in
Section 3 and
Section 4, where we will extend Segal’s and Spivak’s result to a general loss distribution using Guo’s model and distinguishing the case of proportional insurance from that of deductible insurance.
It is interesting to observe that the first-order term of the total risk premium expressed by Equation (
5) is increasing in each of the two “behavioral” parameters
. As long as
and
, differentiating
with respect to
(respectively,
) gives
Evaluating the overall effect of each parameter on Equation (
5), we obtain
which are both positive under the condition expressed by Equation (
8) discussed above. It thus appears that higher values of
are associated to a higher risk premium that a FORA agent is willing to pay to avoid a sufficiently small fair gamble when
. The intuition underlying these findings is that the first-order effect of an increase in
induces a drop in
that is not compensated by
. The second-order effect of
is more complex; however, as long as we are sufficiently close to the reference point (i.e., under the condition expressed by Equation (
8)), it is the first-order effect that prevails. A similar intuition can also be recovered for the impact of
.
3. Proportional Insurance
We here suppose that insurance is available in the form of proportional coverage (or coinsurance). We characterize the optimal insurance-purchasing decision of a DM with a reference-dependent utility, expressed by (
1), and a reference wealth
r corresponding to the no-risk situation outlined in Equation (
4). The impact of a modification in preferences or in
r will be studied in
Section 3.
A DM who insures a fraction
of his/her initial wealth
6, with
, is charged a proportional premium:
so his/her final wealth is given by
Based on Equation (
1), the DM chooses the optimal proportion of insurance coverage
by maximizing the expected utility of the final wealth specified in Equation (
10):
where
is the loss incurred at the reference wealth
r (henceforth, the
target loss), such that
iff
.
Notice that, under FORA, the utility function
v is not differentiable at
, nor therefore at
. Nevertheless, assuming that
L is continuous at
(together with Lebesgue’s dominated convergence theorem) guarantees that
where
. The previous equation can be also written as
where
is the classical expected utility of terminal wealth and
. It thus appears that
can be decomposed into a first term based on EU maximization with respect to the initial utility function
u and a second term taking into account gain–loss utility à la
Guo et al. (
2016) (hence considering both
and
).
Proposition 1. Consider an EU-maximizing agent whose reference-dependent utility, expressed by Equation (1), exhibits FORA at the target wealth r specified in Equation (4). Define the lower and upper partial expectations of L with respect to the target loss as, respectively,where is assumed continuous at .
Ifthe agent will purchase full insurance coverage, i.e., , even when the insurance premium has a positive loading .
If the opposite inequality holds in Equation (17), then the agent will purchase partial insurance coverage, i.e., .
Finally, if equality holds in the condition expressed by Equation (17) and V is a strictly concave function, then the agent will also purchase full insurance coverage, i.e., .
Proof. Based on Equation (
11), we notice that the expected utility
is a concave function of the decision variable
. The optimal level of insurance coverage
is consequently found by studying the sign of
in Equation (
12). Since
, evaluating
at
gives
which is strictly positive under the condition expressed by Equation (
17). It follows that
is a constrained optimum (when over insurance is prohibited). The last two statements follow immediately from the sign of
and from the concavity of
V. ☐
Under the general definition of loss aversion as the behavioral phenomenon that losses matter more than gains, the ratio
, which determines the occurrence of the condition expressed by Equation (
17), may be interpreted as an index of loss aversion in the style of
Köbberling and Wakker (
2005). It is the magnitude of this index that can induce a rational, EU-maximizing agent to purchase full insurance coverage at a loaded price in violation of Mossin’s theorem but in accordance with common observation for some agents (see, e.g.,
Borch 1990). Our result shows that the amount of loss aversion required to trigger the realization of Equation (
17) is determined by the partial moment ratio
, which compares the DM’s upside potential (the expectation of loss deviations below the threshold
, in the numerator) to his/her downside risk exposure (the expectation of loss deviations in excess of
, in the denominator). This moment ratio is the analogue of a portfolio performance index that is well known in the quantitative finance literature as the Omega measure (see, e.g.,
Bertrand and Prigent (
2011) and the references therein). We will accordingly denote the RHS of Equation (
17) by
In the context of investment decisions, a (subjectively modified) version of the Omega measure has been shown to determine the optimal portfolio choice of a cumulative prospect theory (CPT) agent in a one-period economy with one risk-free and one risky asset (
Bernard and Ghossoub 2010). More recently, the Omega measure expressed by Equation (
18) has appeared in a stochastic dominance rule of order
that
Müller et al. (
2016) have introduced to explain why some classes of utility-maximizing investors prefer to purchase a risk-free rather than a risky asset (or portfolio). As far as we know, our condition expressed by Equation (
17) represents the first evidence of a link between the Omega measure and the optimal insurance choice.
Based on the decomposition,
the Omega measure expressed by Equation (
18) may be rewritten as
which implies that
if and only if
. This leads to an optimality of full coverage when insurance is fairly priced, since the loss aversion measure
—which appears on the LHS of Equation (
17)—is greater than 1 as long as
and
. Additionally, from
it follows that
is an increasing function of
k and exceeds 1 as long as the insurance premium is positively loaded. Consequently, for given values of the behavioral parameters
and
, there is a range of values of the loading factor
k such that the condition expressed by Equation (
17) is verified for
, leading to the optimality of full insurance coverage. The value of
can be determined from Equation (
17) once the shape of the loss distribution
is specified.
Comparative Statics Results
An interesting question relates to the comparison of the optimal coverage proportions implied by FORA in the reference-dependent utility model of
Guo et al. (
2016) and by SORA in a classical EU model where the utility function is twice differentiable and concave at all wealth levels. This is considered in the following proposition.
Proposition 2. The optimal proportion of insurance coverage that maximizes Equation (11) is always larger than the optimal proportion of insurance coverage implied by a conventional utility function u that exhibits SORA at all wealth levels.
Proof. Consider a conventional utility function of terminal wealth
that is always twice differentiable, with
and
as implied by SORA. The optimal proportion
of insurance coverage induced by
is found by maximization of
defined in Equation (
14). Owing to the concavity of
u,
is the unique solution to
where
is the relative weight of gain–loss utility that appears in Equation (
2).
For a DM with reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (
1), the optimal proportion of insurance coverage is determined by the sign of
in Equation (
13). Evaluating the latter at
and subtracting the LHS of Equation (
19) gives
which is positive under loss aversion because
. It follows that the optimal proportion
of insurance coverage in the reference-dependent utility model expressed by Equation (
1) is larger than
. ☐
Intuition would suggest that an increase in either loss aversion or in the gain–loss component of the utility function stimulates a higher demand for insurance coverage. The next proposition shows that this indeed the case.
Proposition 3. For a DM with reference dependent utility expressed by Equation (11) and target expressed by Equation (4), the optimal proportion of insurance coverage increases as either λ or η increases.
Proof. Evaluating the first-order condition expressed by Equation (
13) at the optimal coverage
gives
Differentiating
in
gives
which, in view of the concavity of
, implies that
is increasing in
.
Differentiating
in
gives
The condition expressed by Equation (
21) implies
Plugging this into Equation (
22) yields:
which, in view of the concavity of
, implies that
is increasing in
. ☐
As shown in
Section 2, increasing either
or
entails an increase in the first-order term of the total risk premium at the reference point
r.
The result of the above proposition is consistent with a well-established stream of the portfolio selection literature in which reference dependence and loss aversion are shown to determine the increasing demand for capital protection (
Bertrand and Prigent (
2011), for instance, make this point for constant proportion portfolio insurance (CPPI) strategies that offer increased protection against downside risk exposure). However, contrary to the mainstream thinking in the field, we here consider a reference-dependent utility function expressed by Equation (
3) that has no convex portions. Our results may consequently be interpreted as direct implications of FORA as they do not presume risk loving attitudes below the reference point
r.
As previously mentioned, the choice of r is of crucial importance to reference-dependent utility models. For this reason, we here investigate the behavior of the optimal insurance coverage as a function of the target r taken into account.
Based on the condition expressed by Equation (
27), the final wealth of a DM who insures a fraction
of the potential loss
L is given by
. Hence, for a general target
r, it follows that
Let and, as previously, .
A loss-averse DM chooses the optimal proportion of insurance coverage
by maximizing the expected utility of his/her final wealth:
Proposition 4. The optimal proportion of insurance coverage that maximizes Equation (23) is (non-strictly) decreasing in r for and (non-strictly) increasing in r for .
Proof. Differentiating Equation (
23) with respect to
and following the same steps as those outlined in previous developments, we obtain
where the first term is independent of the choice of
r. It follows that
so
is decreasing in
r for
and increasing in
r for
. The argument above together with the concavity of
in
implies the result. ☐
As shown by the above result, our choice of reference point identifies a crucial level of wealth for loss-averse decision-makers. In particular, compared to the frequently used “status quo” (), the optimal insurance proportion related to the safe alternative is lower or equal.
4. Deductible Insurance
We now suppose that insurance is available in the form of a straight deductible policy. This repays the DM for losses in excess of a predefined deductible level
, according to the indemnity function:
The price for obtaining deductible
is specified by the insurance premium, which is assumed proportional to the expected indemnity:
where
is the loading factor, and
As argued in
Schlesinger (
1985), at the agent’s choice of a deductible level
D, it is reasonable to assume
which implies that the extra cost of lowering the deductible by 1 unit does not exceed the increase in final wealth when the realized loss
l exceeds
D (see Footnote 1 in
Schlesinger (
1985)).
The DM now faces a kinked payoff function:
with
where the last inequality holds at the agent’s choice of a deductible
D as a consequence of the condition expressed by Equation (
26).
Based on the reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (
1), the DM chooses the optimal deductible
by maximizing the expected utility of his/her final payoff:
where
is the agent’s reference wealth, as specified in Equation (
4), and
is the corresponding level of loss, with
.
Assuming that
is continuous at
and
D, and denoting the corresponding density function by
, we have
for any
. After some calculation and rearrangement, this gives the following first-order condition for EU maximization at an interior point:
Using Equation (
25), Equation (
31) can be written as
According to
Schlesinger (
2013), the first and third term in the above equation can be interpreted, for an agent with utility function
u, as the marginal benefit of premium savings from increasing
D conditional on a loss lower than
D, and the marginal cost of a higher deductible given that the loss exceeds
D, respectively. The second addend in Equation (
32) is an additional term due to the gain–loss component of Guo’s model that lowers the marginal benefit when the loss is lower than
, taking into account the behavioral parameters
. This extra term depends on the ratio
that is increasing in each parameter
and tends to zero when either
or
, converging to the case of a SORA agent with conventional utility
u (see Equation (16) in
Schlesinger (
2013)).
Evaluating
at an interior solution
of Equation (
31) gives
where
. Based on Equation (
28) and on the concavity of
u, the above expression is negative if
at all values
that solve the first-order condition expressed by Equation (
31). The inequality in Equation (
33) holds at the agent’s choice of an optimal deductible as a consequence of Equation (
26). It follows that any
that solves the first-order condition expressed by Equation (
31) identifies an optimal insurance policy (as guaranteed by Equation (
33)).
Proposition 5. Consider a FORA agent with reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (1) and reference wealth . The agent chooses the optimal level of deductible insurance, , by maximizing the expected utility specified in Equation (29). Assume the loading factor k satisfieswhere .
Ifthe agent will purchase full insurance coverage, i.e., . If the inequality in Equation (35) is reversed, then .
Proof. In view of Schlesinger’s condition expressed by Equation (
26), it is reasonable to study an agent’s decision to purchase full coverage when
which implies that the agent could still derive an economic benefit when the level of deductible is lowered to zero. The condition expressed by Equation (
36) is satisfied if
has a point mass
at 0 and the loading factor
k is bounded above as in Equation (
34). In this case, taking the limit of Equation (
30) for
gives
which is negative under the condition expressed by Equation (
35). Since Equation (
36) implies Equation (
33) in
, it follows that
is a constrained optimum (when overinsurance is prohibited). If the inequality in the condition expressed by Equation (
35) is reversed, the sign of Equation (
37) is positive and
, i.e., partial coverage is preferable. ☐
In the past decade, a number of empirical and experimental studies on insurance-purchasing decisions have extensively documented that some customers purchase low deductibles despite costs significantly above fair price. However, fitting these choices to a standard EU model and assuming that preferences exhibit SORA at all wealth levels yields unrealistic large measures of absolute risk aversion (
Sydnor 2010). This is typically regarded as a major puzzle in insurance economics (
Schmidt 2016).
The result of the above proposition shows that FORA is a plausible explanation of consumers’ preferences for low deductibles, possibly leading to the purchase of full coverage even at a loaded price. As shown in the condition expressed by Equation (
35), this decision depends on the loss aversion coefficient
and on the relative probabilities of experiencing/not experiencing a loss. The role of these probabilities has already emerged in a study of insurance demand that
Schmidt (
2016) has recently carried out by graphical analyses in a different framework, based on a single-argument value function that is specified as a power function of gains and losses (as in conventional prospect theory). Interestingly,
Schmidt (
2016) also considers the “safe alternative” (i.e., the fully insured position) as a possible reference point, but restricts attention to binary risks and fair insurance contracts. Differently than
Schmidt (
2016), we model reference dependence using a two-argument utility function expressed by Equation (
3) that has no convex portions, and we derive results for a general loss distribution with a positively loaded insurance premium. Our analysis can thus help explain why, in real-world circumstances, risk-averse agents may be willing to purchase full coverage even at costs that exceed the expected value of the insurance contract.
As shown in Equation (
32), the presence of FORA in Guo’s model alters the economic trade-off of a conventional SORA agent by lowering the marginal benefit of increasing the deductible level, given that the loss is lower than
D. The following proposition shows that FORA stimulates insurance demand by inducing the choice of a lower deductible relative to SORA.
Proposition 6. Denote the optimal deductible for a FORA agent by with reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (3) and reference wealth . If the condition expressed by Equation (33) is verified and H is concave in D, then , where is the optimal deductible implied by a conventional utility function that exhibits SORA at all wealth levels.
Proof. If we consider a twice differentiable utility function
u with
and
, the optimal deductible is found by maximization of the expected utility
where
are defined by Equation (
27). Since we assume proportional insurance pricing, the first-order condition
identifies a unique global maximizer
, which is the optimal deductible for a SORA agent (cf.
Meyer and Ormiston (
1999)). It follows that
For a FORA agent with the reference-dependent utility specified in Equation (
1), the optimal deductible is determined by the sign of
in Equation (
30) under the condition expressed by Equation (
33). Evaluating
at
and subtracting the LHS of Equation (
38) gives, after some manipulation,
Since
for all
, we have
which is negative if
Since
implies that
, the condition expressed by Equation (
33) implies Equation (
39). It follows that the optimal deductible
under FORA is lower than the optimal deductible
under SORA, i.e., FORA stimulates the demand for insurance coverage. ☐
5. Deductible or Proportional?
A cornerstone result in the theory of insurance economics is Arrow’s theorem of the deductible. The theorem states that a straight deductible policy is the optimal insurance contract for all risk-averse DMs whenever the insurer’s costs are proportional to the indemnity payment and the insurer is risk-neutral (
Arrow 1974).
In this section, we extend Arrow’s fundamental result to FORA preferences, building on a stochastic dominance rule for comparing risks in the presence of a reference point that has been recently proposed by
Guo et al. (
2016).
Definition 1. (Guo et al. 2016) Consider the reference-dependent utility specified in Equation (1) and assume , where Assume are pre-specified lower bounds for the parameters and the reference point r is given. A random variable is said to second-order-stochastically dominate another random variable relative to r, written as , iffor all , , .
As proved in
Guo et al. (
2016), conventional second-order stochastic dominance (
) is a sufficient condition for
relative to a fixed reference point, as illustrated in the following proposition.
Proposition 7. (Guo et al. 2016) Let the reference point r be fixed. For any two random variables and , implies , but the converse is not true.
Based on this result, we now extend the validity of Arrow’s theorem to the reference-dependent utility model expressed by Equation (
1).
Proposition 8. Consider a FORA agent with reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (1) and a fixed reference wealth , as specified in Equation (4). As a hedge against a potential random loss L valued in , the agent selects an insurance contract that stipulates an indemnity and requires the payment of a premium , with . If is non-decreasing and for all l, the optimal insurance contract contains a straight deductible D, i.e., .
Proof. It is well known (see, e.g.,
Eeckhoudt and Gollier (
1992);
Gollier and Schlesinger (
1996)) that, for a given insurance premium
, the indemnity schedule
second-order-stochastically dominates any non-negative and non-decreasing indemnity function
with the same premium
. By Proposition 7 above,
implies that
. Therefore, according to Definition 1, the deductible contract is preferred by all FORA agents with reference-dependent utility expressed by Equation (
1) and a fixed target
r specified in Equation (
4). Since we can make this argument for any level
of the insurance premium, this concludes the proof. ☐
The logic behind deductible insurance is that of concentrating coverage on the states with the largest losses. Originally, Arrow proved that this logic is optimal for all risk-averse EU-maximizers. Other authors (see
Gollier and Schlesinger (
1996), for a detailed overview) have subsequently extended Arrow’s result beyond the classic EU framework using preference functionals consistent with first- and second-degree stochastic dominance.
In the above proposition, we prove that the validity of Arrow’s theorem is preserved under FORA in view of the coherence between the reference-dependent utility function expressed by Equation (
3) and the definition of second-degree stochastic dominance with respect to a fixed reference point provided in
Guo et al. (
2016). The question of whether this result could be extended to other types of reference-dependent preferences (with possibly stochastic reference points) is still an open one, and we leave it for further research.
6. Discussion and Conclusions
Some decision-makers pay attention not only to their final wealth but also to its position with respect to a reference value.
Recently,
Guo et al. (
2016) have suggested an interesting model of choice belonging to that line of research and they have looked at its implications for the stochastic dominance literature. An interesting feature of the model above is that it introduces loss aversion and gain loving without affecting the local index of risk aversion away from the reference point. In this way, one can better isolate the pure effect of these attitudes upon optimal choices under risk.
In the present paper, we have examined how insurance demand would behave in such an environment. It appears that the reference level
r adopted by the decision-maker plays a major role. As recently argued in
Schmidt (
2016), a possible choice of the reference level is the so-called safe alternative, i.e., the sure amount of wealth, the decision-maker could obtain if s/he were to select full insurance. For values of
r equal to the safe alternative, we have found that, under a strictly positive loading, the second component of the utility function besides final wealth always stimulates insurance demand.
The proposed model yields plausible explanations for a range of consumer choices observed in real insurance markets. In particular, decision-makers within the reference-dependent utility model of
Guo et al. (
2016) will (a) always choose a lower deductible (or a higher coinsurance rate) relative to classic risk-averse EU-maximizers and (b) be willing to purchase full insurance even at a loaded price, subject to appropriate conditions on their degree of loss aversion. Interestingly, in the case of proportional insurance, these conditions are related to the Omega measure, a performance index that has been widely used in mathematical finance and in the portfolio management literature (see, e.g.,
Bertrand and Prigent (
2011) and the references therein).
Whereas the mainstream of literature has focused on binary risks and/or fair insurance contracts (see, e.g.,
Schmidt (
2016), for a recent contribution and an accurate literature review), in the present work we have considered a general loss distribution and a positively loaded insurance premium. Our results are consequently relevant for understanding the characteristics of real insurance markets, and provide a new perspective on consumers’ tendency to over-insure modest risks (
Sydnor 2010).
These findings add to a range of possible explanations that have been suggested in the literature to rationalize a surprisingly high demand for insurance, such as probability weighting (
Jaspersen et al. 2018), consumption commitments (
Chetty 2006), and menu effects (
Kamenica 2008).
It is worth mentioning that Guo’s model presumes separability between consumption utility and gain–loss utility, which adds tractability to the problem. Alternative points of view have been recently proposed in the literature. In particular,
Gollier (
2016) integrates consumption utility and regret within a non-separable model, whereas
Andersen et al. (
2018) argue in favor of more flexible models that allow for partial rather full asset integration.
Another specificity of Guo’s model is the assumption that initial wealth is fixed and known to the agent. This assumption has been discussed and relaxed, for instance, by
Barberis et al. (
2006), who have emphasized the role of background risks from extra-experimental income or wealth. However, when these background risks are independent of the insurable risk, they induce diversification benefits that may offset first-order risk aversion. A promising direction to develop a model with multiple sources of risks may be found, for instance, in
Dionne and Li (
2014), who suggest that foreground and background risks may not be independent but rather associated in a form of positive/negative expectation dependence.