Research on a General State Formalization Method from the Perspective of Logic
Abstract
1. Introduction
- a unified axiomatization of states as interpretations of formulas, with four axioms (parameter reference, property expressibility, logical closure, temporal causality) and an existence–uniqueness result up to logical equivalence that fills a gap in OIT;
- systematic links to model-theoretic milestones (categoricity, Skolem/non-categoricity, second-order Peano, Scott’s isomorphism theorem) and conditions for characterizing some uncountable structures;
- a cross-disciplinary case library for specification, verification, and measurement;
- an articulation of a deeper unity: many domain-specific notions of state admit uniform logical expression and transformation.
2. Formal Expression of State
2.1. First-Order Formal System Definition
- First-order variables:
- First-order constants:
- First-order function symbols: ;
- brackets: (, );
- First-order predicate symbols: ;
- Logical connectives: ∼ or ¬ (negation), → (implication);
- Quantifiers: ∀ (universal quantifier).
- (1)
- Variables and constants are terms.
- (2)
- If () is a function symbol in and is a term in , then is also a term in .
- (1)
- Each atomic formula is a well-formed formula in ;
- (2)
- If and are well-formed formulas in , then and are both well-formed formulas in ;
- (3)
- If is a well-formed formula in and u is a variable or function symbol in , then is a well-formed formula in .
2.2. Recursive Definition of Higher-Order Formal Systems
2.3. Interpretation of Formal Systems
- The domain is a non-empty set that contains the value range of all elements in , including individuals, properties, relations, and functions.
- The interpretation function J is a mapping that maps symbols in to concrete semantics in the domain and is defined as follows:
- –
- Interpretation of constants and variables: Each constant is interpreted as an element in , i.e., ; each variable is interpreted as an element in , i.e., .
- –
- Interpretation of function symbols: Each function symbol is interpreted as a mapping from to , that is, .
- –
- Interpretation of predicate symbols: Each predicate symbol is interpreted as a mapping from to , i.e., .
- –
- Interpretation of the terms:
- –
- Interpretation of atomic formula:
- –
- Interpretation of logical connectives:
- –
- Interpretation of quantifiers: If , where u is a variable or function symbol, then
2.4. Axiom System for Logical Expression of Ontology Components Under State Decomposition
- Parameter Reference Axiom: Every object , every moment or period , and every function is represented by a unique constant or term in L.
- Property Expressibility Axiom: The properties, form, value, relationship, and other attributes of a set of objects in the entire domain can be expressed through functions and predicates in the formal system.
- Logical Combination and the Closure Axiom:The generation rules of the state space are limited to the following logical operations:
- Implication: If , then it implies that is also a state of ;
- Negation: If , then ;
- Quantification: if is a state predicate, then and belong to S.
Only finitely many applications of these operations may be used to generate new states. - Temporal Causality Axiom: When any attribute, relationship, or state is established at a certain moment, its change or evolution at subsequent moments can be described by the formula in L.
2.5. The State of an Object at a Specific Time
2.6. Relationship to and Distinctions from Existing Frameworks
- (1)
- Modal logic (Kripke structures): Kripke semantics treats states as possible worlds and transitions as accessibility relations, focusing on “reachability/necessity.” In this paper, a state is defined as “the semantic object of formulas under an interpretation,” and Kripke structures can, when needed, be embedded as a specific interpretation (worlds = elements of the domain; R as relations induced by predicates/functions). Our main thrust, however, is to use logical expressive power to unify the semantic construction of “object–property–time,” rather than confining ourselves to the realm of accessibility. In other words, Kripke semantics is a specialized interpretation within our framework, while our framework natively supports higher-order properties, functions, and cross-domain mappings [15].
- (2)
- Linear/branching-time logics (LTL/CTL): LTL/CTL excel at temporal specifications and model checking, targeting safety/liveness over path- or tree-shaped time structures [16]. This paper incorporates the temporal dimension but does not fix time solely as a linear or branching transition system; instead, it incorporates “time” into the domain and interpretation and allows first-order/higher-order predicates to describe intrinsic mathematical properties and cross-domain relations of structures. For engineering use, LTL/CTL specifications can be regarded as a temporal subset of our state language, while our framework provides broader object-level semantics and model-theoretic tools (e.g., types, Scott sentences, and isomorphism metrics).
- (3)
- Dynamic logic (PDL, dynamic first-/higher-order logic): Dynamic logic takes program actions as modalities and is well-suited to characterize executable transformations. Our focus is the unified semantic definition and cross-domain representation of “state,” emphasizing that actions/processes are also treated as interpretable predicates/functions, thereby expressing object properties and evolution laws within a single language. By comparison, dynamic logic is strong in the calculational encapsulation of programmatic transformations, whereas this paper is strong in the semantic unification of cross-disciplinary objects and higher-order structures [17]. The two are complementary: embedding action semantics into our interpretive layer yields greater expressive power for complex object structures.
- (4)
- TLA+: TLA+ centers on state variables and the next-step relation and is well-suited for proving safety and liveness in concurrent/distributed systems [18]. In our approach, TLA+ states and the Next relation can be viewed as instances of interpretations of specific predicates/functions, thereby bringing TLA+ specifications under a unified logical semantics that can interoperate with state models in mathematics, economics, or natural language. Our added value lies in providing model-theoretic tools spanning finite/countable to certain uncountable structures (e.g., Scott sentences and approximation limits), as well as a dual-sided ontology–carrier expression and measurement of “information mappings.”
- (5)
- Abstract State Machines (ASM): ASM describes system behavior using refined states and transition rules [19]. We can translate ASM state families and update rules into a unified predicate–function interpretation with corresponding inferential commitments. The difference is that ASM targets execution-level abstractions for engineering modeling, whereas this paper provides a cross-disciplinary repository of semantic isomorphism and expressibility theorems, enabling states from mathematics/social sciences/language to be aligned and compared with engineering specifications such as ASM/TLA+ on a common semantic foundation.
3. Mathematical Field State Expression
3.1. Formalization of Finite Mathematical Structures
- Relation symbols: (with arity respectively)
- Function symbols: (with arity respectively)
- Constant symbols:
- Individual constants: (corresponding to each element in A)
- Let ; construct the following statement:
- are defined by isomorphic correspondences.By the definition of isomorphism, satisfies all statements in .(⇐) If , then :By Lemma 2, is defined as , which is a bijection.Verify that h maintains the relationship:For any :
3.2. Previous Research on the Formalization of Infinite Structures
- 1.
- Contains all atomic formulas of first-order logic.
- 2.
- If is a set of formulas and , then and are also formulas.
- 3.
- If ϕ is a formula and x is a variable, then and are formulas.
- 4.
- Every formula contains only a finite number of free variables.
3.3. Formalization of Conditional Infinite Structures
- 1.
- Monotonicity:
- 2.
- Countability: for all n
- 3.
- Recursion: There exists a recursive function that computes the Scott sentence for each
- 4.
- Density: (in appropriate topology)
- 5.
- Relationship maintenance: for all , where denotes the number of elements of the relation
- 6.
- Asymptotic uniqueness: Any two sequences are isomorphic to themselves or to each other after adding a finite number of elements from M.
3.4. Formalization of Phenomena in Mathematics
- 1.
- Finite structures. There exists a first-order language L and a set of sentences Γ such that for any L-structure ,(a complete characterization up to isomorphism; see Theorem 2).
- 2.
- Countable structures. There exists a Scott sentence in , such that(a complete characterization up to isomorphism; see Theorem 5).
- 3.
- Uncountable structures satisfying “recursive approximation + local finiteness”. There exists a higher-order theory (allowing countably infinite conjunctions), such that(see Theorems 6 and 7).
4. State Expression in Economics and Sociology
4.1. Logical Characterization in the Field of Economics
- A is a set of agents (individuals, enterprises, institutions, etc.)
- is a relationship (social network, hierarchy, transaction relationship, etc.)
- is a function (utility function, production function, decision rule, etc.)
- is a process (market mechanism, institutional evolution, information dissemination, etc.)
- represent specific agent individuals, enterprises, organizations, etc.
- denote agent variables, t denotes time variables, and s denotes state variables.
- : x is an agent.
- : represents the transition from state s to state under process .
- : indicates that the transition from state s to state under process satisfies the prescribed condition.
- 1.
- (Finite Agents)
- 2.
- Every relation and function is defined over a finite domain and has corresponding predicate and function representations in the base language.
- 3.
- The process involves finite states and finite time.
4.2. Logical Characterization in the Field of Sociology
- 1.
- (finite agent)
- 2.
- Each relation and function is defined over a finite domain and has corresponding predicate and function representations in the base language.
- 3.
- The process involves finite states and finite time.
5. Computer Field State Expression
5.1. Boolean Algebra and the Formalization of Computer Systems
5.2. Predicate Logic Description of a Turing Machine (TM)
- Q is a finite state set.
- Γ is the set of tape symbols (including the blank symbol ⊔).
- is the set of input symbols (excluding ⊔).
- is the state transition function, where L and R indicate whether the read/write head moves left or right.
- is the initial state.
- are the accept and reject states, respectively.
- State: indicates that q is a state.
- Tape Symbol: indicates that a is a tape symbol.
- Tape content: indicates that a is the tape symbol at time t and position p.
- Read/Write Head Position: indicates that the head is at position p at time t.
- Transition function: represents state transition, where d is the direction.
- Initial state: represents the initial state q.
- Accept state (similar to the rejection state): indicates that q is an accepting state.
5.3. Mathematical Formalization of Neural Networks
- Feedforward Network: indicates the connection between , and indicates the lth layer.
- Hierarchical Combination: indicates the hierarchical combination structure of x.
- Combinatorial Completeness: If the lth layer can be represented as , then the th layer can be represented as:
5.4. Formal Expression of States in Computer Science
- 1.
- Boolean circuits, finite automata, and finite-state concurrent models: first-order logic can completely characterize any fixed instance.
- 2.
- Turing machines’ state evolution and computability statements: their behavior and halting properties can be expressed in extensions of first-order or second-order arithmetic/set theory.
- 3.
- Neural networks (with finite depth/width over a given real field or its axiomatization): their topology and forward computation can be described in first- or higher-order logic.
6. State Expression in Natural Language Domain
6.1. Montague Semantics
6.2. Study of English Ambiguity
- means x is a person;
- means x likes a specific book b.
- indicates that b is a book;
- indicates that there exists at least one person x, there exists a book b, and this person likes book b.
- Broad interpretation: There is at least one person who likes this particular book:
- Narrow interpretation: There is a book and at least one person likes it:
6.3. Optimizing Syntax and Semantic Translation Rules
6.3.1. Conjunction Rules
6.3.2. Adjective Rules
- (a)
- if γ contains an occurrence of a member of , then ;
- (b)
- otherwise .
- (a)
- if , then ;
- (b)
- otherwise .
- (a)
- If , then ;
- (b)
- Otherwise .
- (a)
- is translated as ;
- (b)
- John’s is translated as .
- (c)
- In other cases, is translated as .
6.3.3. Clause Rules
6.4. Formalization of Natural Languages
7. Conclusions and Outlook
Author Contributions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
OIT | Objective Information Theory |
FOL | First-order predicate logic |
HOL | Higher-order predicate logic |
ASM | Abstract State Machines |
CTL | Computation Tree Logic |
LTL | Linear Temporal Logic |
PDL | Propositional Dynamic Logic |
TLA+ | Temporal Logic of Actions |
wff (wffs) | well-formed formula (well-formed formulas) |
Appendix A
Appendix A.1
- All symbols of ;
- k-order variables:
- k-order constants:
- k-order predicate variables:
- k order function symbols:
- k-order predicate symbols:
- (1)
- All terms of ;
- (2)
- If () is a k-order function symbol in and are variables, constants, or functions in , then is a k-order term in .
- (1)
- All atomic formulas of ;
- (2)
- If () is a predicate symbol of order k in and are terms in , then is an atomic formula of order k in .
- (1)
- All well-formed formulas for ;
- (2)
- If and are well-formed formulas in , then and are both well-formed formulas in ;
- (3)
- If is a well-formed formula in and u is an argument or function symbol in , then is a well-formed formula in .
Appendix A.2
Appendix A.3
- Cobb–Douglas:
- CES with :
- (1)
- Price normalization and nonnegativity.
- (2)
- Individual feasibility and budget exhaustion. For each ,
- (3A)
- Individual optimality via closed-form demand (Cobb–Douglas).Let . For each and ,
- (3B)
- Individual optimality via KKT conditions (CES or smooth, strictly quasiconcave utilities).Introduce multipliers and . For each and ,
- (4)
- Market clearing.For each ,
Appendix A.4
Symbol | Meaning |
---|---|
Individual variables (elements, times, states depending on context) | |
Individual constants (constant symbols) | |
Function symbols | |
Predicate/relation symbols (also used as higher-order predicate variables) | |
Logical connectives: negation, implication | |
Logical connectives: conjunction, disjunction, biconditional | |
Quantifiers: universal, existential | |
⊨ | Semantic entailment/satisfaction (a structure satisfies a formula) |
Structure A satisfies/does not satisfy | |
⊢ | Syntactic provability |
Logical equivalence/same truth-value (as used in context) | |
Equality/inequality | |
Membership, inclusion, proper inclusion | |
Cardinality of set X | |
Domain, range of a function (when needed) | |
Arity of relation R | |
Summation, product | |
Supremum, infimum (when used) |
Symbol | Meaning |
---|---|
First-order language | |
k-th order language (defined recursively) | |
L | Generic formal system/language |
First-/higher-order variables | |
First-/higher-order constants | |
Function symbols (arity n,order k) | |
Predicate symbols (arity n, order k) | |
Atomic formula | |
Formula formation (negation, implication, quantification) | |
term | Variable, constant, or function term |
WFF | Well-formed formula |
Symbol | Meaning |
---|---|
Interpretation (domain + interpretation function) | |
Domain (nonempty universe) | |
J | Interpretation function mapping symbols to -objects/relations |
Interpretation value of a term/formula (truth value for formulas) | |
L-structure/model | |
Another L-structure | |
Homomorphisms/embeddings/isomorphisms between structures | |
Isomorphism between structures A and B |
Symbol | Meaning |
---|---|
Infinitary logic with countable (co)infinite conjunctions/disjunctions | |
Scott sentence of structure A | |
Set of k-types occurring in models of /in structure M | |
Distance on the space of Scott sentences | |
k-component distance based on symmetric-difference of k-types | |
Recursive approximation sequence of structures | |
Limit structure (with well-defined union of relations) | |
Local finiteness | Controlled local growth of types (as defined in the paper) |
Symbol | Meaning |
---|---|
X | Set of objects |
T | Set of time points or intervals |
State of object x at time t | |
Set of WFFs in L characterizing |
References
- Wiener, N. Cybernetics or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine; The MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Shannon, C.E. The mathematical theory of communication. Bell Syst. Tech. 1948, 27, 379–423. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- von Neumann, J. Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1971; Volume 38. [Google Scholar]
- Kolmogorov, A.N. Three approaches to the quantitative definition of information. Int. J. Comput. Math. 1968, 2, 157–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Xu, J.; Ma, X.; Shen, Y.; Tang, J.; Xu, B.; Qiao, Y. Objective information theory: A Sextuple model and 9 kinds of metrics. In Proceedings of the 2014 Science and Information Conference, London, UK, 27–29 August 2014; IEEE: Piscataway, NJ, USA, 2014; pp. 793–802. [Google Scholar]
- Xu, J.; Ma, X.; Tang, J. Research on model and measurement of objective information. Sci. China Inf. Sci. 2015, 45, 336–353. (In Chinese) [Google Scholar]
- Xu, J.; Liu, Z.; Wang, S.; Zheng, T.; Wang, Y.; Wang, Y.; Dang, Y. Foundations and applications of information systems dynamics. Engineering 2023, 27, 254–265. [Google Scholar]
- Hamilton, A.G. Logic for Mathematicians; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- Xu, J. Information science principles of machine learning: A causal chain meta-framework based on formalized information mapping. arXiv 2025, arXiv:2505.13182. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tarski, A. Contributions to the theory of models. I. In Indagationes Mathematicae (Proceedings); Elsevier BV: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1954; Volume 57, pp. 572–581. [Google Scholar]
- Tarski, A. The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1956. [Google Scholar]
- Goguen, J.A.; Burstall, R.M. Institutions: Abstract model theory for specification and programming. J. ACM (JACM) 1992, 39, 95–146. [Google Scholar]
- Rutten, J.J. Universal coalgebra: A theory of systems. Theor. Comput. Sci. 2000, 249, 3–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tang, G.; Fu, R.; Seiti, H.; Chiclana, F.; Liu, P. A novel bi-objective R-mathematical programming method for risk group decision making. Inf. Fusion 2025, 118, 102902. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, S.A. Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philos. Fenn. 1963, 16, 83–94. [Google Scholar]
- Pnueli, A. The temporal logic of programs. In Proceedings of the 18th Annual Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science (sfcs 1977), Providence, RI, USA, 31 October–2 November 1977; IEEE: Piscataway, NJ, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Harel, D.; Kozen, D.; Tiuryn, J. Dynamic logic. ACM SIGACT News 2001, 32, 66–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lamport, L. The temporal logic of actions. ACM Trans. Program. Lang. Syst. (TOPLAS) 1994, 16, 872–923. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gurevich, Y.; Börger, E. Evolving algebras 1993: Lipari guide. Evol. Algebr. 1995, 40, 2. [Google Scholar]
- Swan, R.G. K-Theory of Finite Groups and Orders; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2006; Volume 149. [Google Scholar]
- Lidl, R.; Niederreiter, H. Finite Fields; Number 20; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Libkin, L. Elements of Finite Model Theory; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2004; Volume 41. [Google Scholar]
- Chang, C.C.; Keisler, H.J. Model Theory; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1990; Volume 73. [Google Scholar]
- Dedekind, R. Was sind und was sollen die zahlen? In Was Sind und Was Sollen Die Zahlen? Stetigkeit und Irrationale Zahlen; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1965; pp. 1–47. [Google Scholar]
- Peano, G. Arithmetices Principia: Nova Methodo Exposita; Fratres Bocca: Caringbah, Australia, 1889. [Google Scholar]
- Scott, D. Logic with denumerably long formulas and finite strings of quantifiers. In The Theory of Models; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2014; pp. 329–341. [Google Scholar]
- Debreu, G. Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 1959; Volume 17. [Google Scholar]
- Shoham, Y.; Leyton-Brown, K. Multiagent Systems: Algorithmic, Game-Theoretic, and Logical Foundations; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Geanakoplos, J. Three brief proofs of arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ. Theory 2005, 26, 211–215. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arthur, W.B.; Durlauf, S.N.; Lane, D.A. The Economy as an Evolving Complex System ii; Adison Wesley: Reading, MA, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Hintikka, J.; Kulas, J. Anaphora and Definite Descriptions: Two Applications of Game-Theoretical Semantics; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin, Germany, 1985; Volume 26. [Google Scholar]
- Hausman, D.M. The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2023. [Google Scholar]
- Thornton, P.H.; Ocasio, W.; Lounsbury, M. The Institutional Logics Perspective: A New Approach to Culture, Structure, and Process; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Borgatti, S.P.; Everett, M.G.; Johnson, J.C.; Agneessens, F. Analyzing Social Networks Using R; Sage: Hemet, CA, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Huth, M.; Ryan, M. Logic in Computer Science: Modelling and Reasoning About Systems; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Hoare, C.A.R. An axiomatic basis for computer programming. Commun. ACM 1969, 12, 576–580. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pierce, B.C. Types and Programming Languages; MIT Press: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Boole, G. The Mathematical Analysis of Logic; CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform: North Charleston, SC, USA, 1847. [Google Scholar]
- Boole, G. An Investigation of the Laws of Thought: On Which Are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities; Walton and Maberly: London, UK, 1854; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
- Turing, A.M. On computable numbers, with an application to the entscheidungsproblem. J. Math 1936, 58, 5. [Google Scholar]
- McCulloch, W.S.; Pitts, W. A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bull. Math. Biophys. 1943, 5, 115–133. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Winskel, G. The Formal Semantics of Programming Languages: An Introduction; MIT Press: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Rogers, H., Jr. Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability; MIT Press: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Montague, R. The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary english. In Approaches to Natural Language: Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford Workshop on Grammar and Semantics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1973; pp. 221–242. [Google Scholar]
- Bennett, M. A variation and extension of a montague fragment of english. In Montague Grammar; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1976; pp. 119–163. [Google Scholar]
- Cooper, R. Quantification and Syntactic Theory; Springer Science & Business Media: Berlin, Germany, 2013; Volume 21. [Google Scholar]
- Andrews, P.B. An Introduction to Mathematical Logic and Type Theory: To Truth Through Proof: Vol 27; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2002. [Google Scholar]
Symbol | Definition |
---|---|
The quantity q demanded by consumer i for good g at price p is q | |
i is a consumer | |
g is a commodity | |
p is a valid price (non-negative) | |
q is a valid quantity (non-negative) | |
Consumer i chooses a bundle of goods b to maximize utility under constraints | |
Consumer i’s budget constraint under price p and income | |
Income of consumer i | |
The bundle b contains a quantity q of the good g | |
The supply of good g by firm f at price p is q | |
f is an enterprise (production unit) | |
Firm f chooses input v and output to maximize profit under price p and factor price w |
Predicate | Semantic Meaning |
---|---|
x and y are friends | |
x smokes | |
x is affected by y | |
x has a higher probability of smoking | |
x and y are in the same social network |
Person | Age | Height | Gender | Occupation |
---|---|---|---|---|
A | 22 | 179 | Male | Student |
B | 54 | 158 | Female | Teacher |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Qiu, S.; Xu, J. Research on a General State Formalization Method from the Perspective of Logic. Mathematics 2025, 13, 3324. https://doi.org/10.3390/math13203324
Qiu S, Xu J. Research on a General State Formalization Method from the Perspective of Logic. Mathematics. 2025; 13(20):3324. https://doi.org/10.3390/math13203324
Chicago/Turabian StyleQiu, Siyuan, and Jianfeng Xu. 2025. "Research on a General State Formalization Method from the Perspective of Logic" Mathematics 13, no. 20: 3324. https://doi.org/10.3390/math13203324
APA StyleQiu, S., & Xu, J. (2025). Research on a General State Formalization Method from the Perspective of Logic. Mathematics, 13(20), 3324. https://doi.org/10.3390/math13203324