With Socrates on Your Heels and Descartes in Your Hand: On the Notion of Conflict in John Dewey’s Democracy and Education
Abstract
:A Socrates is thus led to declare that consciousness of ignorance is the beginning of effective love of wisdom, and a Descartes to say that science is born of doubting.[1] (p. 147)
1. Introduction: Conflicts as Gadflies and Their Role in Education
What is to be done with these facts of disharmony and conflict? After we have discovered the place and consequences of conflict in nature, we have still to discover its place and working in human need and thought. What is its office, its function, its possibility, or use? In general, the answer is simple. Conflict is the gadfly of thought. It stirs us to observation and memory. It instigates to invention. It shocks us out of sheep-like passivity, and sets us at noting and contriving. Not that it always effects this result; but that conflict is a sine qua non of reflection and ingenuity. When this possibility of making use of conflict has once been noted, it is possible to utilize it systematically to substitute the arbitration of mind for that of brutal attack and brute collapse.[2] (p. 301)
And now, Athenians, I am not going to argue for my own sake, as you may think, but for yours, that you may not sin against the God by condemning me, who am his gift to you. For if you kill me you will not easily find a successor to me, who, if I may use such a ludicrous figure of speech, am a sort of gadfly, given to the state by God; and the state is a great and noble steed who is tardy in his motions owing to his very size, and requires to be stirred into life. I am that gadfly which God has attached to the state, and all day long and in all places am always fastening upon you, arousing and persuading and reproaching you. You will not easily find another like me, and therefore I would advise you to spare me. I dare say that you may feel out of temper (like a person who is suddenly awakened from sleep), and you think that you might easily strike me dead as Anytus advises, and then you would sleep on for the remainder of your lives, unless God in his care of you sent you another gadfly.[3] (p. 2)
2. Notions of Conflict in Democracy and Education
2.1. Traditional versus Progressive Education
Natural instincts are either disregarded or treated as nuisances—as obnoxious traits to be suppressed, or at all events to be brought into conformity with external standards. Since conformity is the aim, what is distinctively individual in a young person is brushed aside, or regarded as a source of mischief or anarchy. Conformity is made equivalent to uniformity. Consequently, there are induced lack of interest in the novel, aversion to progress, and dread of the uncertain and the unknown. Since the end of growth is outside of and beyond the process of growing, external agents have to be resorted to induce movement toward it. Whenever a method of education is stigmatized as mechanical, we may be sure that external pressure is brought to bear to reach an external end.[1] (p. 43)
2.2. Past versus Future
Development, in short, has taken place by the entrance of shortcuts and alterations in the prior scheme of growth. And this suggests that the aim of education is to facilitate such short-circuited growth. The great advantage of immaturity, educationally speaking, is that it enables us to emancipate the young from the need of dwelling in an outgrown past. The business of education is rather to liberate the young from reviving and retraversing the past than to lead them to a recapitulation of it. The social environment of the young is constituted by the presence and action of the habits of thinking and feeling of civilized men. To ignore the directive influence of this present environment upon the young is simply to abdicate the educational function.[1] (p. 59)
2.3. Closing Off versus Opening Up Education
The essential point is that isolation makes for rigidity and formal institutionalizing of life, for static and selfish ideals within the group. That savage tribes regard aliens and enemies as synonymous is not accidental. It springs from the fact that they have identified their experience with rigid adherence to their past customs. On such a basis it is wholly logical to fear intercourse with others, for such contact might dissolve custom. It would certainly occasion reconstruction. It is a commonplace that an alert and expanding mental life depends upon an enlarging range of contact with the physical environment. But the principle applies even more significantly to the field where we are apt to ignore it—the sphere of social contacts. Every expansive era in the history of mankind has coincided with the operation of factors which have tended to eliminate distance between peoples and classes previously hemmed off from one another. Even the alleged benefits of war, so far as more than alleged, spring from the fact that conflict of peoples at least enforces intercourse between them and thus accidentally enables them to learn from one another, and thereby to expand their horizons. Travel, economic and commercial tendencies, have at present gone far to break down external barriers; to bring peoples and classes into closer and more perceptible connection with one another.[1] (p. 69)
2.4. Personal versus National Education
One of the fundamental problems of education in and for a democratic society is set by the conflict of a nationalistic and a wider social aim. (...) This contradiction (for it is nothing less) between the wider sphere of associated and mutually helpful social life and the narrower sphere of exclusive and hence potentially hostile pursuits and purposes, exacts of educational theory a clearer conception of the meaning of “social” as a function and test of education than has yet been attained. Is it possible for an educational system to be conducted by a national state and yet the full social ends of the educative process not be restricted, constrained, and corrupted?[1] (p. 77)
The emphasis [of democratic education] must be put upon whatever binds people together in cooperative human pursuits and results, apart from geographical limitations. (...) This conclusion is bound up with the very idea of education as a freeing of individual capacity in a progressive growth directed to social aims. Otherwise a democratic criterion of education can only be inconsistently applied.[1] (p. 78)
2.5. Knowledge versus Thinking
To say that thinking occurs with reference to situations which are still going on, and incomplete, is to say that thinking occurs when things are uncertain or doubtful or problematic. Only what is finished, completed, is wholly assured. Where there is reflection there is suspense. The object of thinking is to help reach a conclusion, to project a possible termination on the basis of what is already given. Certain other facts about thinking accompany this feature. Since the situation in which thinking occurs is a doubtful one, thinking is a process of inquiry, of looking into things, of investigating. Acquiring is always secondary, and instrumental to the act of inquiring. It is seeking, a quest, for something that is not at hand. (...) It also follows that all thinking involves a risk. Certainty cannot be guaranteed in advance. The invasion of the unknown is of the nature of an adventure; we cannot be sure in advance. The conclusions of thinking, till confirmed by the event, are, accordingly, more or less tentative or hypothetical.[1] (p. 116)
2.6. Easy versus Difficult Education
The material of thinking is not thoughts, but actions, facts, events, and the relations of things. In other words, to think effectively one must have had, or now have, experiences which will furnish him resources for coping with the difficulty at hand. A difficulty is an indispensable stimulus to thinking, but not all difficulties call out thinking. Sometimes they overwhelm and submerge and discourage. The perplexing situation must be sufficiently like situations which have already been dealt with so that pupils will have some control of the meanings of handling it. A large part of the art of instruction lies in making the difficulty of new problems large enough to challenge thought, and small enough so that, in addition to the confusion naturally attending the novel elements, there shall be luminous familiar spots from which helpful suggestions may spring.[1] (p. 122)
2.7. Certainty versus Uncertainty
The mind of man is taken captive by the spoils of its prior victories; the spoils, not the weapons and the acts of waging the battle against the unknown, are used to fix the meaning of knowledge, of fact, and truth.[1] (p. 146)
In its honorable sense, knowledge is distinguished from opinion, guesswork, speculation, and mere tradition. In knowledge, things are ascertained; they are so and not dubiously otherwise. But experience makes us aware that there is difference between intellectual certainty of subject matter and our certainty. We are made, so to speak, for belief; credulity is natural. The undisciplined mind is averse to suspense and intellectual hesitation; it is prone to assertion. It likes things undisturbed, settled, and treats them as such without due warrant. Familiarity, common repute, and congeniality to desire are readily made measuring rods of truth. Ignorance gives way to opinionated and current error,—a greater foe to learning than ignorance itself. A Socrates is thus led to declare that consciousness of ignorance is the beginning of effective love of wisdom, and a Descartes to say that science is born of doubting.[1] (p. 147)
Even in the case of failure, we are inclined to put the blame not on the inadequacy and incorrectness of our data and thoughts, but upon our hard luck and the hostility of circumstance. We charge the evil consequence not to the error of our schemes and our incomplete inquiry into conditions (thereby getting material for revising the former and stimulus for extending the latter) but to untoward fate. We even plume ourselves upon our firmness in clinging to our conceptions in spite of the way in which they work out.[1] (p. 147)
2.8. Domesticated versus Wild Education
Not merely manual training specifically so called but many traditional kindergarten exercises have erred here. Moreover, opportunity for making mistakes is an incidental requirement. Not because mistakes are ever desirable, but because over zeal to select material and appliances which forbid a chance for mistakes to occur, restricts initiative, reduces judgment to a minimum, and compels the use of methods which are so remote from the complex situations of life that the power gained is of little availability.[1] (p. 153)
Only by starting with crude material and subjecting it to purposeful handling will he gain the intelligence embodied in finished material. In practice, overemphasis upon formed material leads to an exaggeration of mathematical qualities, since intellect finds its profit in physical things from matters of size, form, and proportion and the relations that flow from them. But these are known only when their perception is a fruit of acting upon purposes which require attention to them.[1] (p. 153)
2.9. Person versus Society
His “knowledge” is second-handed; it is only a knowledge that others prize unselfishness as an excellence, and esteem him in the degree in which he exhibits it. Thus there grows up a split between a person’s professed standards and his actual ones. A person may be aware of the results of this struggle between his inclinations and his theoretical opinions; he suffers from the conflict between doing what is really dear to him and what he has learned will win the approval of others. But of the split itself he is unaware; the result is a kind of unconscious hypocrisy, an instability of disposition.[1] (p. 181)
The imagination is the medium of appreciation in every field. The engagement of the imagination is the only thing that makes any activity more than mechanical.[1] (p. 181)
An adequate recognition of the play of imagination as the medium of the realization of every kind of thing which lies beyond the scope of direct physical response is the sole way of escape from mechanical methods in teaching. (...) It is by imagination that symbols are translated over into a direct meaning and integrated with a narrower activity so as to expand and enrich it.[1] (p. 182)
2.10. Dualism as a Problem of Its Own
As livelihood and leisure are opposed, so are theory and practice, intelligence and execution, knowledge and activity. The latter set of oppositions doubtless springs from the same social conditions which produce the former conflict; but certain definite problems of education connected with them make it desirable to discuss explicitly the matter of the relationship and alleged separation of knowing and doing.[1] (p. 201)
Experience is always hovering, then, on the edge of pretense, of sham, of seeming, and appearance, in distinction from the reality upon which reason lays hold.[1] (p. 203)
2.11. Theory versus Practice
Only the single, the uniform, assures coherence and harmony. Out of experience come warrings, the conflict of opinions and acts within the individual and between individuals. From experience no standard of belief can issue, because it is the very nature of experience to instigate all kinds of contrary beliefs, as varieties of local custom proved. Its logical outcome is that anything is good and true to the particular individual which his experience leads him to believe true and good at a particular time and place. Finally practice falls of necessity within experience. Doing proceeds from needs and aims at change. To produce or to make is to alter something; to consume is to alter. All the obnoxious characters of change and diversity thus attach themselves to doing while knowing is as permanent as its object. To know, to grasp a thing intellectually or theoretically, is to be out of the region of vicissitude, chance, and diversity. Truth has no lack; it is untouched by the perturbations of the world of sense. It deals with the eternal and the universal. And the world of experience can be brought under control, can be steadied and ordered, only through subjection to its law of reason.[1] (p. 203)
2.12. Knowledge versus Thinking
Yet there is a valid distinction between knowledge which is objective and impersonal, and thinking which is subjective and personal. In one sense, knowledge is that which we take for granted. It is that which is settled, disposed of, established, under control. What we fully know, we do not need to think about. In common phrase, it is certain, assured. And this does not mean a mere feeling of certainty. It denotes not a sentiment, but a practical attitude, a readiness to act without reserve or quibble. Of course we may be mistaken. What is taken for knowledge—for fact and truth—at a given time may not be such. But everything which is assumed without question, which is taken for granted in our intercourse with one another and nature is what, at the given time, is called knowledge. Thinking on the contrary, starts, as we have seen, from doubt or uncertainty. It marks an inquiring, hunting, searching attitude, instead of one of mastery and possession.[1] (p. 226)
Knowledge, grounded knowledge, is science; it represents objects which have been settled, ordered, disposed of rationally. Thinking, on the other hand, is prospective in reference. It is occasioned by an unsettlement and it aims at overcoming a disturbance. Philosophy is thinking what the known demands of us—what responsive attitude it exacts. It is an idea of what is possible, not a record of accomplished fact. Hence it is hypothetical, like all thinking. It presents an assignment of something to be done—something to be tried. Its value lies not in furnishing solutions (which can be achieved only in action) but in defining difficulties and suggesting methods for dealing with them. Philosophy might almost be described as thinking which has become conscious of itself—which has generalized its place, function, and value in experience.[1] (p. 248)
Philosophy was stated to be a form of thinking, which, like all thinking, finds its origin in what is uncertain in the subject matter of experience, which aims to locate the nature of the perplexity and to frame hypotheses for its clearing up to be tested in action.[1] (p. 253)
2.13. Vocational versus Cultural Education
When educators conceive vocational guidance as something which leads up to a definitive, irretrievable, and complete choice, both education and the chosen vocation are likely to be rigid, hampering further growth. In so far, the calling chosen will be such as to leave the person concerned in a permanently subordinate position, executing the intelligence of others who have a calling which permits more flexible play and readjustment. And while ordinary usages of language may not justify terming a flexible attitude of readjustment a choice of a new and further calling, it is such in effect. If even adults have to be on the lookout to see that their calling does not shut down on them and fossilize them, educators must certainly be careful that the vocational preparation of youth is such as to engage them in a continuous reorganization of aims and methods.[1] (p. 238)
There is a standing danger that education will perpetuate the older traditions for a select few, and effect its adjustment to the newer economic conditions more or less on the basis of acquiescence in the untransformed, unrationalized, and unsocialized phases of our defective industrial regime. Put in concrete terms, there is danger that vocational education will be interpreted in theory and practice as trade education: as a means of securing technical efficiency in specialized future pursuits. Education would then become an instrument of perpetuating unchanged the existing industrial order of society, instead of operating as a means of its transformation.[1] (p. 242)
2.14. Certainty versus Uncertainty
If there are genuine uncertainties in life, philosophies must reflect that uncertainty. If there are different diagnoses of the cause of a difficulty, and different proposals for dealing with it; if, that is, the conflict of interests is more or less embodied in different sets of persons, there must be divergent competing philosophies. With respect to what has happened, sufficient evidence is all that is needed to bring agreement and certainty. The thing itself is sure. But with reference to what it is wise to do in a complicated situation, discussion is inevitable precisely because the thing itself is still indeterminate. One would not expect a ruling class living at ease to have the same philosophy of life as those who were having a hard struggle for existence.[1] (p. 249)
3. Discussion and Conclusions
Under such conditions, men take revenge, as it were, upon the alien and hostile environment by cultivating contempt for it, by giving it a bad name. They seek refuge and consolation within their own states of mind, their own imaginings and wishes, which they compliment by calling both more real and more ideal than the despised outer world.[1] (p. 264)
In other words, there is a tendency to identify the self—or take interest—in what one has got used to, and to turn away the mind with aversion or irritation when an unexpected thing which involves an unpleasant modification of habit comes up. Since in the past one has done one’s duty without having to face such a disagreeable circumstance, why not go on as one has been? To yield to this temptation means to narrow and isolate the thought of the self—to treat it as complete. Any habit, no matter how efficient in the past, which has become set, may at any time bring this temptation with it. To act from principle in such an emergency is not to act on some abstract principle, or duty at large; it is to act upon the principle of a course of action, instead of upon the circumstances which have attended it.[1] (p. 267)
Author Contributions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Dewey, J. Democracy and Education; Merchant Books: Seaside, OR, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. Human Nature and Conduct. An Introduction to Social Psychology; Holt: New York, NY, USA, 1922. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. ; Jewett, B., Translator; Apology. Available online: http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/1/6/5/1656/1656-h/1656-h.htm (accessed on 21 December 2016).
- Graff, G. Beyond the Culture Wars. How Teaching the Conflicts Can Revitalize American Education; W.W. Norton: New York, NY, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Dascal, M. G.W. Leibniz. The Art of Controversies; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Dahrendorf, R.G. Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1959. [Google Scholar]
- Dascal, M. Traditions of controversy and conflict resolution: Can past approaches help to solve present conflicts (Chapter 15). In Traditions of Controversy; Dascal, M., Chang, H., Eds.; John Benjamins: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2007; pp. 281–295. [Google Scholar]
- Eberg, J. Conflicten Maken Mensen. (Conflicts Make People) Waarom zijn er Conflicten en Waar Komen ze Vandaan? Noordhoff Uitgevers: Groningen, The Netherlands, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Glasl, F. Handboek Conflict Management; SWP: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Conflict. In Cambridge Dictionary; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2016; Available online: http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/english/conflict (accessed on 21 December 2016).
- Tagore, R. Nationalism; MacMillan and Co.: London, UK, 1918. [Google Scholar]
- Festinger, L. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Riesman, D. The Lonely Crowd. A Study of the Changing American Character; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Freire, P. Pedagogy of the Oppressed; Continuum: New York, NY, USA, 2005; pp. 125–183. [Google Scholar]
- Schutz, A. Deweyan Democracy and Schools: Why Hasn’t It Happened? How Would Dewey the Pragmatist Respond Today? In Proceedings of the Dewey Democracy and Education Centennial Conference, Washington, DC, USA, 6–7 April 2016.
- Johnson, D.W.; Johnson, R.T. Creative Controversy: Intellectual Challenge in the Classroom, 4th ed.; Interaction Book Co.: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Johnson, D.W. Constructive Controversy. Theory, Research, Practice; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Good, J.A. John Dewey’s “Permanent Hegelian Deposit” and the Exigencies of War. J. Hist. Philos. 2006, 44, 293–313. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pring, R. John Dewey; Bloomsbury: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
Number | Chapter | Page | Nature of Conflict |
---|---|---|---|
1 | 4. Education as Growth | 34 | Traditional versus Progressive |
2 | 6. Education as Conservative and Progressive | 59 | Past versus Future |
3 4 | 7. The Democratic Concept in Education | 69 77 | Closing off versus Opening up Personal versus National |
5 | 11. Experience and Thinking | 116 | Knowledge versus Thinking |
6 | 12. Thinking in Education | 122 | Easy versus Difficult |
7 | 14. The Nature of Subject Matter | 146–147 | Certainty versus Uncertainty |
8 | 15. Play and Work | 153 | Domesticated versus Wild |
9 | 18. Values in Education | 181 | Person versus Society |
11 | 20. Intellectual and Practical Studies | 178–245 203 | Dualism as a problem of its own Theory versus Practice |
12 | 22. Individual and World | 226 | Knowledge versus Thinking |
13 | 23. Vocational Aspects | 238 | Vocational versus Cultural Education |
14 | 24. Philosophy of Education | 249 | Certainty versus Uncertainty |
© 2017 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license ( http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Pouwels, J.; Biesta, G. With Socrates on Your Heels and Descartes in Your Hand: On the Notion of Conflict in John Dewey’s Democracy and Education. Educ. Sci. 2017, 7, 7. https://doi.org/10.3390/educsci7010007
Pouwels J, Biesta G. With Socrates on Your Heels and Descartes in Your Hand: On the Notion of Conflict in John Dewey’s Democracy and Education. Education Sciences. 2017; 7(1):7. https://doi.org/10.3390/educsci7010007
Chicago/Turabian StylePouwels, Jan, and Gert Biesta. 2017. "With Socrates on Your Heels and Descartes in Your Hand: On the Notion of Conflict in John Dewey’s Democracy and Education" Education Sciences 7, no. 1: 7. https://doi.org/10.3390/educsci7010007
APA StylePouwels, J., & Biesta, G. (2017). With Socrates on Your Heels and Descartes in Your Hand: On the Notion of Conflict in John Dewey’s Democracy and Education. Education Sciences, 7(1), 7. https://doi.org/10.3390/educsci7010007