Previous Article in Journal
The Role of Self-Adaptors in Lexical Retrieval
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Mismatches and Mitigation at CS-PF Interface: The Curious Case of li

Linguistics, Department of Languages, Literature, and Communication, Institute of Language Sciences, Faculty of Humanities, Utrecht University, 3512 JK Utrecht, The Netherlands
Languages 2025, 10(9), 210; https://doi.org/10.3390/languages10090210
Submission received: 31 May 2025 / Revised: 29 July 2025 / Accepted: 14 August 2025 / Published: 26 August 2025
(This article belongs to the Special Issue SinFonIJA 17 (Syntax, Phonology and Language Analysis))

Abstract

Taking the domain of polar questions in Bosnian/Croatian/Montenegrin/Serbian (BCMS) as the empirical background, the paper probes into the syntax–phonology (CS-PF) interface and discusses insertion and movement as PF-repair strategies mitigating against the lack of convergence at PF. Contra previous accounts, the analysis treats li (lexicalization of Q) as a ‘run-of-the-mill’ 2P clitic in BCMS, whose host cannot always be provided by syntax. I provide evidence against Prosodic Inversion—‘the usual suspect’ for post-syntactic movement in Slavic—thus adding to the body of evidence that Prosodic Inversion does not take place in BCMS. I argue that the PF Movement in such cases has to be raising and adopt Local Dislocation to account for them. Probing into the interaction between Future I and polar questions provides further insights into the ordering of PF Movement operations in BCMS.

1. Introduction

Due to its suitability to inform issues at the syntax–phonology interface, the nature of the cliticization has been one of the central subjects of inquiry in the literature on Slavic clitics. Over the last two decades, persuasive evidence has been presented in favor of the so-called ‘weak phonology approach’ to cliticization in Serbo-Croatian (SC) or Bosnian/Croatian/Montenegrin/Serbian (BCMS) (see Bošković, 1995 et seq.) Syntax provides well-formed syntactic structures to phonology, and the role of phonology is to pick out the convergent one(s) among them. Though the brunt of BCMS data (see Bošković, 1995, 2001; Franks, 1998/2010; Stjepanović, 1998, 1999, among others) can be accounted for under this approach, recent data arrived through large-scale experiments (see Marelj et al., 2024) suggest that there are configurations in which post-syntactic operations need to take place in BCMS as well.
The paper is organized as follows: Section 2 provides the necessary background regarding the nature of clitics, in general, and BCMS clitics and the cliticization process, in particular. Section 3 focuses on the long-noted puzzling behavior of clitic li in l-participle-li construction in BCMS and provides an account for it. Taking the experimental data that suggest that judgements about the relevant data are more graded than standardly assumed (see Marelj et al., 2024) as a starting point, Section 4 discusses their implications for CS-PF interface in BSCM. Section 4 further probes into the interaction between Future I and polar questions, thus providing insights into the ordering of PF operations in BCMS. Section 5 concludes the paper.

2. Light Preliminaries

2.1. CS-PF Interface and the Nature of Clitics

Clitics, standardly understood as syntactically independent and phonologically dependent—‘prosodically deficient’—elements (in the way that the comparable non-affixal forms/elements are not) are a ‘poster child’ for CS-PF mismatches, responsible for the lack of isomorphism between syntactic and phonological structures involving them.1
To mitigate against convergence problems at PF, language uses various insertion, movement, and deletion strategies. Being prosodically weak, i.e., unable to serve as an independent prosodic domain, clitics must become a part of an adjacent domain for stress assignment purposes. To ensure convergence (i.e., pronounceability) at PF, a PF Movement strategy called Prosodic Inversion (Halpern, 1992/1995) is often argued to apply in such cases in Slavic (see Izvorski et al., 1997; Embick & Izvorski, 1997; Rudnickaya, 2000, among others). After attaching itself to its host, the clitic forms a prosodic word with it. Though dependent on their host prosodically, clitics are, typically, nonselective with respect to the category of their hosts.2

2.2. BCMS 2P Clitics in General and li in Particular

The main protagonist of the paper is the interrogative clitic li, a default lexicalization of Q in polar questions in BCMS. As illustrated in (1), the clitic li clusters with the canonical (auxiliary and pronominal) second position (2P) clitics:3,4
1.Kupujetelimuga?
buy.PRS.2PLQhim.DAThim.ACC
‘Are you buying it for him?’
As further illustrated in (2), BCMS 2P clitics appear in a stringent linear order, with li heading the cluster, followed by auxiliary clitics (apart from AUX.3SG je ‘is’), in turn, followed by pronominal clitics:5
2.li ⪧ AUX[−3SG] ⪧ DATφ ⪧ ACCφ ⪧ GENφ ⪧ AUX[3SG]φ
The linear order of clitics matches the hierarchical arrangement of projections, but, as we will see directly, in BCMS, they cluster together only prosodically, not syntactically.
3.[CP discourse-related clitics [TP auxiliary clitics [vP/VP pronominal clitics]]]
As the contrast between (4a) and (4b) shows, rather than second in their clause, BCMS clitics occur in the second position of their Intonational Phrase (I-phrase—#), the behavior originally noted and elaborated by Browne (1975/2004) and Radanović-Kocić (1988). If the first element of the clause forms a separate I-phrase, BCMS 2P clitics do not follow it directly, but must appear second in their own I-phrase. Since prosodically ‘heavy’ elements get parsed as their own I-phrases, clitics do not appear directly following them (4a), even if that means that they occur after the 3rd, 7th, or nth word in a clause (4b).
4.a.#Ja##tvojamama#,#samtikupilaprsten.
IyourmotherAUX1SGyou.DATbuy.PRT.3SG.Fring.ACC
b.#Ja##tvojamama#kupilasamtiprsten.
Iyourmotherbuy.PRCT.3S.FAUX1SGyou.DATring.ACC
‘I, your mother bought you a ring.’
The pattern with appositives (4) is due to Radanović-Kocić (1988, 1996). The contrast further obtains with clausal subjects, parentheticals, and fronted heavy constituents (see Radanović-Kocić, 1988, 1996; Bošković, 2001, for discussion and elaboration).
The 2Phood of BCMS clitics is, thus, computed prosodically and a single host is sufficient for the entire cluster (5). Provided, however, each of clitics can satisfy its 2Phood appropriately, even clause-mate clitics need not cluster together. This is illustrated in (6), where both the ‘neutral’ (6a) and the ‘marked’ variant (6b), illustrating the clause-mate-clitics split, are grammatical:6
5.a.[X]ω CL CL CL
b.kupujete li mu ga (cf. (1))
6.a.IvaniStipesugadaliMariji.
IvaniStipeAUX.3PLit.ACCgive.PRCT.3PLMary.DAT
‘Ivan and Stipe gave it to Mary.’
b.%DaligaMarijisuIvaniStipe.
Give.PRT.3PLit.ACCMary.DATAUX.3PLIvanandStipe
‘Give it to Mary, Ivan and Stipe did.’Wilder and Ćavar (2002)
Further, in BCMS, their prosodic requirement can be computed either with respect to the first prosodic word (W1) or the entire constituent phrase (P1):7
7.a.[Tajpesnik]mičitaknjigu.(P1)
that.DEMpoetme.DATread.PRS.3SGbook.ACC
‘That poet reads a book to me.’
b.[Tajmipesnik]čitaknjigu.(W1)
that.DEMme.DATpoetread.PRS.3SGbook.ACC
‘That poet is reading a book to me.’
The most striking piece of evidence that syntax is responsible for the clitic placement (see Ćavar & Wilder, 1994, 1996; Franks & Progovac, 1994; Progovac, 1996; Progovac, 2000; Franks & King, 2000; Stjepanović, 1998; and especially Bošković, 1995 et seq., particularly Bošković, 2001: pp. 11–36) are the so-called ‘syntactic fortresses’ (Halpern, 1992/1995). As illustrated in (8), if one of the possibilities for calculating 2Phood within the I-phrase (W1 or P1, as in (7)) violates the rules of syntax, it is avoided since it leads to ungrammaticality. In (8b), the clitics split the head of the phrase from its complement, which leads to a syntactic violation (see Schütze, 1994; Progovac, 1996; Franks, 1998/2010, among others for elaborate discussion), but is otherwise unproblematic in terms of PF (studenti ‘students’ is the first prosodic word in the I-phrase of the cluster, which makes it a perfect host for the clitic). Clearly, we must be dealing with a syntactic restriction, since PF is not able to tell apart complements from non-complements (compare the ungrammatical (8b) with the grammatical (7b)).
8.a.[Studentiistorije]sumugakupili.
studentshistory.GENAUX.3PLhim.DAThim.ACCbuy.PRTC.3PL
b.*[Studentisumugaistorije]kupili.
studentsAUX.3PLhim.DAThim.ACChistory.GENbuy.3PL
‘Students of history bought it for him.’
To sum, though 2Phood is computed prosodically, clitic placement is accomplished in syntax (hence, the ordering in (2) becomes less of a mystery) and as expected, it follows syntactic rules (8). Provided no syntactic violations occur, the host of the clitics can be of any category: X0, XP, an argument, or an adjunct. For completeness, I add (9a) with an X0 and (9b) with an adjunct XP host, respectively.
9.a.Kupujumugastudentiistorije.
buy.PRS.1PLhim.DAThim.ACCstudentshistory.GEN
‘Students of history are buying it for him.’
b.Danasmugastudentiistorije
todayhim.DAThim.ACCstudentshistory.GEN
kupili.
buy.PRS.1PL
‘Students of history are buying it for him today.’

3. Puzz-Li-ing

3.1. Data

Originally observed by Rivero (1993) and first discussed at length in Bošković (1995), (10) captures the contrast relevant to this paper. Whereas a finite verb ljubi (‘kisses’) makes a perfect host for the clitic li (10a), the corresponding l-participle poljubio (‘kissed’) is argued to be unable to host it (10b).8
This behavior of li seems truly puzzling; recall that, cross-linguistically, nonselectivity with respect to the category of the host is generally taken to be the hallmark characteristic of clitics, a trait that is further exhibited by all the other 2P clitics in BCMS, since they are regularly hosted by l-participle (see (6b), for instance)
10.a.LjubiliMariju?
kiss.PRS.3SGQMarija.ACC
‘Does he kiss Marija?’
b.*PoljubiolijeMariju?
kiss.PRCT.SG.MQAUX.3SGMarija.ACC
intented: ‘Did he kiss Marija?’

3.2. Previous Accounts

The common denomination of previous accounts for the contrast in (10) is that li is unlike any other clitic in BCMS, either with respect to its syntactic or its phonological behavior. Specifically, li is uniquely ‘choosy’ in syntax with respect to the syntactic category of its host, thus allowing only X0 to host it (see Migdalski, 2006, 2009 for discussion and elaboration) or li forces Prosodic Inversion (PI) across two phonological boundaries, which is illicit (see Schwabe, 2004 for discussion and elaboration).
Either line of reasoning faces empirical problems of either undergeneration (11a) or overgeneration (11b).
11.a.Šta/koji poklonlisimikupio?
what/which presentQAUX.2SG.me.DATbuy.PRCT.M.SG
‘(I wonder) what/what kind of present did you buy me?’
b.*?PoljubiolibejašeMariju?
kiss.PRCT.M.SGQAUX.IMPF.3SGMarija.ACC
intended: ‘Had he kissed Mary?’
In (11a), li is hosted by a phrase and the sentence (though requiring contextual furnishing) is perfectly grammatical in BCMS, thus challenging the main prediction of Migdalski’s account. On the other hand, an example like (11b), predicted to be grammatical under Schwabe’s account, is out. Namely, li is the only clitic in (11b) i.e., there is no PI process involving other clitics—(11b) features a non-clitic auxiliary bejaše—yet the sentence is ungrammatical.9

3.3. Current Account

3.3.1. Bag of Assumptions: ‘Run-of-the-Mill’ Clitic and Participle

The account I present here (see also Marelj et al., 2024) treats li as a ‘run-of-the mill’ BCMS clitic. For the purposes of the current discussion, it would suffice to treat it is an operator clitic found in the left periphery and as standardly assumed, base generated/externally merged in C0 (Rivero, 1993; Bošković, 1995; Progovac, 2005, among others). As for the l-participle, it is a ‘run-of-the-mill’ participle in that it is [-finite].10 In languages in which V-to-C movement takes place in finite clauses, only finite verbs move to C. Non-finite verbs in such languages never do (see Roberts, 1991; Zwart, 1995; Den Dikken & Hoekstra, 1997, among others). Indeed, for (10), the core of the account boils down to [+/-finite] distinction; the ability of verbs and the inability of participles to move to C (see Bošković (1995) for elaborate discussion).11
Unlike in canonical verb-second languages (German, Dutch, Afrikaans, Frisian, Danish, Norwegian, and Swedish), the standard tests for I/T-C movement give less straightforward results in BCMS for a variety of reasons, some of which (e.g., the negation head being a proclitic) have nothing to do with the verb movement. Putting aside interrogatives, the evidence that finite verbs can move to C is, however, sufficiently supported in BCMS. For instance, under ellipsis, in Fragment Answer, rather than the presence of a raised finite AUX or Do-support, as it is the case in English, in BCMS, it is finite verbs themselves that survive ellipsis; kupujem (‘buy.PRS.1SG’) in (12) and mislim (think.PRS.3SG) in (13) (see also Progovac, 2005, et seq. for discussion and elaboration):12
12.Q:Dalimineštokupuješ?
PRTQme.DATsomething.ACCbuy.PRCT.M.SG
‘Are you buying me something?’
A:Kupujem.
buy.PRS.1SG
‘I am.’
13.Q:MisliliponekadnaMariju?
think.PRS.3SGQsometimesonMarija.ACC
‘Does he sometimes think about Marija?’
A:Misli.
think.PRS.3SG
‘He/she does.’

3.3.2. Analysis

Polar Questions at CS-PF Interface: [+finite]V0-li
The analysis is couched in terms of Rizzi (1997, 2001, 2004) and Rizzi and Bocci (2017) finely articulated left periphery, which, for ease of exposition, I briefly present here. Rizzi proposes a finely articulated CP-domain, with several discourse-related phenomena formalized in terms of hierarchically ordered phrases. The domain hosts topicalization, focalization, scope, discourse related elements, clause typing and (non)finiteness, the highest and the lowest heads, respectively, in this domain (14c). The clause type (declarative, interrogative, etc.) is expressed by Force. Since complementizers show a degree of sensitivity to finiteness, FinP is found as the lowest head within the articulated CP-domain. In English, for instance, Force in finite declarative is lexicalized as that and Force in non-finite declarative as for (14), but not all positions need to be lexicalized, of course. Since we are dealing with polar questions, next to ForceP, Interrogative Phrase (IntP) is of interest for our discussion. For English, Rizzi (2001) and Rizzi and Bocci (2017) argue that IntP hosts complementizers like if, both in root and embedded questions.13
14.a.I believe that Mary will win the election.that[+finite, +declarative]
b.I would prefer for Mary to win the election.for[−finite, +declarative]
c.[Force [Int [Top[Foc [Fin]]]]]
It is standardly assumed in the literature that clitic li licenses polar question. Couched in terms of finely articulated CP domain, I argue that li is located in F0 or, more precisely, Force in polar questions is lexicalized as li.
Quite like other clitics, though a fully-fledged autonomous syntactic element, to ensure convergence at PF, li must find a host. Hosts can, in principle, be of any category, but the cliticization (i.e., incorporation of the clitic into an adjacent prosodic domain for stress purposes) can occur only if the host is placed by syntax into a position that allows PF Merger (see Bošković, 2001 et seq.) to take place. This means that since li is in F, the highest head in the CP-domain, a legitimate host must either be externally merged in F or move/undergo internal merge to F in syntax.14
In (10a), repeated here as (15a) being [+finite], the verb is a legitimate host for the clitic in F0. As illustrated in (15a) and (quite like obligatorily in polar questions in Germanic), the movement of finite verbs takes place. The trigger for V-to-C movement has never been answered satisfactorily (see Zwart, 2020 for elaborate discussion). For the purposes of our discussion, we can treat it as the illocutionary Force feature—a [+Q] on F. Importantly, it is a syntactically motivated movement that correlates with [+/-finiteness], so that only finite verbs are able to check the relevant feature (be it via Move/Internal Merge or Agree).15 Consequently, the verb moves to F, left adjoining to li (15b). It is to this syntactically well-formed structure that the process of PF Merger of Bošković (1995, 2001) applies to, thus satisfying the prosodic requirement of li. The clitic and the host are adjacent, and the role of PF Merger is simply to put the clitic (i.e., elements lacking word-level prosodic structure) with an adjacent host to form a phonological word (ω) (15c). Hence, PF Merger—a version of Morphological Merger of Marantz (1988), adopted and adapted by Bošković (1995 et seq.)—is all that is needed for convergence at PF.16
15.a.LjubiliMariju?
kiss.PRS.3SGQMarija.ACC
’Does he kiss Mary?’
b.CS: [ForceP [F ljubi +li]….. [FinP [Fin ljubi ][TP [T ljubi] [vP/VP ljubi Mariju]]]]]]
c.PF: [[ljubi] ω li]ω
Polar Questions at CS-PF Interface: l-Participle-li
The l-participle in BCMS does not seem to be as low as its English counterpart (see Progovac, 2005 for discussion and elaboration). As an illustration, observe that in Fragment Answer cases illustrated in (16), whereas l-participle in BCMS survives ellipsis, its English counterpart does not, and the raised AUX or Do-support is needed.
16.Q:Dalisiminešto
PRTQAUX.2SGme.DATsomething
kupio?
buy.PRCT.SG.M
‘Have you bought me something?’
A:Kupiosam.
buy.PRCT.SG.MAUX.1SG
‘I have’.
Though it is able to escape vP/VP ellipsis, thus clearly finding itself in a position higher than its English counterpart, the participle in BCMS cannot move as high as a finite verb in BCMS. For one thing, participles cannot move past TP-adverbs (see Bošković, 1995, et seq., a.o.) Note first that adverbs like pravilno (‘correctly’) have two possible attachment sites, yielding two different readings. One possibility for pravilno is to be vP/VP-adjoined, yielding the manner reading. Its sentential reading, on the other hand, arises when it is TP-adjoined. As illustrated in (18a), provided the participle odgovorio (‘answered’) stays in situ/within the vP-domain, both the manner and the sentential readings are available, since both attachment sites are higher than the in situ position of the participle. In (17b), the participle must move overtly to host the clitic (17b). Clearly, this movement has to be lower than T, since the only available reading in (17b) is still the manner reading. It also has to be higher than vP, since the participle hosts auxiliary. The reader is referred to Bošković (1995) who convincingly argues that l-participles is, and the auxiliary clitics can, be found lower than T.
17.a.JovanjepravilnoodgovorioMileni.
JovaniscorrectlyansweredMilena.DAT
‘Jovan gave Milena a correct answer.’(manner reading)
‘Jovan did the right thing in answering Milena.’(sentential reading)
b.OdgovoriojepravilnoMilena.
‘He gave Milena a correct answer.’
*‘He did the right thing in answering Milena.’(Bošković, 1995: p. 249)
It is standardly assumed in the literature on BCMS that participles—externally merged within vP/VP—consequently move to a position in which AUXs are externally merged (the AuxP (‘lower’ AuxP)—see Progovac, 1996; Ćavar & Wilder, 1994; Bošković, 1995 among others):
18.[Aux odgovorio je [VP odgovorio Mariji]]
Finally, note that when the non-clitic version of AUX is used in Fragment Answer, only the AUX survives the ellipsis (19). Given auxiliary clitics are ‘special clitics’—a type of clitic that exhibit syntactic positions often different from the positions of their non-clitic counterparts—and given they need a host, the conclusion is that whatever the position of odgovorio je is (17b), it must be lower than that of the full form auxiliary jesam in (19) as the presence of the participle in (19) results in ungrammaticality.
19.Q:Dalisimineštokupio?
PRTQAUX.2SGme.DATsomething.ACCbuy.PRCT.SG.M
‘Have you bought me something?’
A:Jesam. *Jesamkupio*Kupiojesam
AUX.1SG AUX.1SGbuy.PRCT.SG.Mbuy.PRCT.SG.M.AUX.1SG
‘I have.’ Intended: ‘I have.’Intended: ‘I have.’
Returning to the contrast in (10) and the ungrammaticality of the example (10b), repeated here as (20a), note that since l-participles in Slavic do not move as high as C in syntax (see Bošković, 1995 et seq.; Embick & Izvorski, 1997, among others), they are not legitimate candidates to host li, and the ungrammaticality of (20a) in BCMS is expected. Since the prosodic requirements of li cannot be met (20c), an otherwise syntactically well-formed output (20b) is filtered out by PF.
20.a.*PoljubiolijeMariju?
kiss.PRCT.SG.MQAUX.3SG.Marija.ACC
intented:’Has he kissed Maria?’
b.CS: [C/F li [ T [AUX poljubio+je [vP/VP Marija
c.PF: # li…poljubio..je

3.3.3. Predictions

Under the account presented here, only elements that undergo external merge in C/Force or are independently moved/undergo internal merge to C/F in syntax can host li. It follows then, that, in contrast with [+finite] verbs, not only l-participles, but other [-finite] forms are expected to be poor hosts for li, since none of them are able to move to the C/F in syntax. As illustrated in (21a) and (22a), this prediction is borne out:17
21.a.*Otićiliželite?[infinitive]
leave.INFQwant.PRS.2PL
b.Želiteliotići?[finite V movement to C/F]
want.PRS.2PLQleave.INF.
‘Would you like to leave?’
22.a.*?Pojedenelisujagode?
eat.PASS.PRCT.PL.FQAUX.3PLstrawberries
[passive participle]
b.Dalisupojedenejagode?
PRTQAUX.3PLeaten.PASS.PRCT.PL.Fstrawberries
[da-insertion in C/F]
‘Have the strawberries been eaten?’
Recall that language uses different strategies to mitigate against convergence problems at PF, be it insertion, movement, or deletion. BCMS is no exception here. Both insertion and movement are illustrated in (21)–(22). Since the finite verb (želite ‘want’) moves in syntax (21b), PF Merger forms a prosodic word from the host and the clitic, while in cases like (22b), da-insertion ensures that the clitic li satisfies its prosodic requirement.
To sum, the data we have looked at so far support the ‘weak phonology approach’ to clitics in BCMS, as proposed and particularly developed by Bošković (1995) et seq., and as best summed-up in slogan form as ‘syntax proposes, phonology disposes’ (Franks, 1998/2010), meaning that, to a large extent, it is syntax that is responsible for the ordering of clitics, with phonology having but a filtering role on its outputs. The empirical data seem to suggest that clitics of the left periphery like li can be supported by finite, but not non-finite verbal forms in BCMS, since only finite verbal forms can move as high as C/F in syntax.

4. A Second Look at Polar Questions at CS-PF Interface

4.1. Larger Data Sets—More Complexities

A large-scale online truth-value judgment/acceptability task experiment (see Marelj et al., 2024) shows, however, that rather than in a binary fashion (grammatical vs. ungrammatical), the l-participle-li construction is judged as graded. Namely, though both finite verbs and XPs were significantly more likely to be judged as acceptable hosts for the clitic li, l-participle was not completely rejected. Rather, the likelihood of saying ‘yes’ to sentences like (10b)/(20a) was 36% (see Marelj et al., 2024 for details and elaboration).
Hence, though a subset of native speakers shows a clear contrast between data like (10a)/(15a) and (10b)/(20a), in terms of grammaticality judgments, the gradient judgments of others seem to suggest that in the absence of ‘proposals by syntax’, ‘phonology’ sometimes does more than just ‘filtering’ alone.

4.2. Post-Syntactic Movement: Lowering or Raising?

Since non-finite forms do not move to C/F in syntax, the acceptability of (23) suggests that rather than just putting adjacent elements together, we must allow for a version of PF Merger that, crucially, allows some reordering/rearrangement of elements at PF, in line with the original formulation of Morphological Merger (Marantz, 1988).
23.% Poljubio li je Mariju?
This being the case, the next question that arises here is whether the process that reorders l-participle and li so that the prosodic requirement of li can be satisfied is that of lowering (of li) or raising (of l-participle).
Recall that Prosodic Inversion (PI) is a ‘usual suspect’ in Slavic (see Halpern, 1992/1995; Izvorski et al., 1997; Embick & Izvorski, 1997; Rudnickaya, 2000, among others) when it comes to repairing prosodically ill-formed strings. PI (Halpern, 1992/1995)—a last-resort option to satisfy the licensing requirements of phonological material—attaches a clitic to the right of the edge of the ω, at the closest relevant prosodic boundary (24).
24.Prosodic Inversion (PI):
[ [ ]ω ___ ]ω attach an enclitic to the right edge of a phonological word to form
another phonological word
As elaborately argued in Franks (2008, 1998/2010), in the case of negative polar questions in Bulgarian, PI seems to be an elegant solution. For brevity, I briefly present the data and the core of his analysis here. In Bulgarian, proclitic ne (NEG) is postaccenting i.e., it not only forms a prosodic word with the element to its right, but if that element is itself not a prosodic word, ne shifts the stress to it and then procliticizes onto it. As a results, if it is another clitic that follows ne directly, the clitic will become stressed. This situation is illustrated in (25), with pronominal clitic me (me) bearing stress.
25.Nepitaxa.
NEGmeask.AOR.IMP.3P
‘They didn’t ask me.’ (Vakareliyska, 2023: p. 9)
Quite like in BCMS, clitic li is a 2P enclitic in Bulgarian, while, unlike in BCMS, auxiliary and pronominal clitics are V-adjacent and normally not separable. Further, predictably, li (Q) is located higher than auxiliary and pronominal clitics in Bulgarian as well. Quite like in BCMS, the order ‘li > aux/pronominal clitics’ is normally rigidly retained at PF. Negative polar questions present a unique environment in Bulgarian where this rigid ordering does not apply. In such questions, li (which is otherwise an enclitic in C0) appears not only lower than the pronominal clitics, but further splits the otherwise inseparable cluster, as exemplified in (26).
As elaborately argued by Franks (2008, 1998/2010), the way to straightforwardly account for the surface position of li in cases like (26) is via PI. If the syntax leaves li (an enclitic in C0) with no host to its left, at PF, it gets to be lowered and attaches at right edge of the prosodic word. Now, given ne is postaccenting, it is ne MÚ that becomes a prosodic word that li attaches to. Since PI entails lowering of li and attaching it at the right edge of the first prosodic word, the process ends up splitting, otherwise not separable sequence of V-adjacent clitics. Thus, li ends up as an enclitic on ne MÚ, while the rest of the V-adjacent clitics—gi e—in (26) procliticize, as expected, on pokazvala.
26.9li [ω ne mú] [ω gi e pokázvala] → [[ω ne mú] + li] [ω gi e pokázvala]
In BCMS, PI does not, however, seem to be the right answer for l-participle-li cases.18 In BCMS, PI overgenerates by predicting both the acceptable clitic ordering and the unacceptable ones. Specifically, for a case like (27a), PI would predict both the order in (27b) and in (27c), whereas native speakers’ judgements are consistent only with (27b).
27.a.#lipoljubiojeMariju?
Qkiss.PRCT.SG.MAUX.3SG.Marija.ACC
b.#[poljubio]ω li ω] je] ω Mariju
c.#[poljubio]ω je ω] li] ω Mariju
In case of l-participle li string in BCMS, PI would lower li and attach it to the right of the edge of the ω at the closest relevant prosodic boundary, which could either be ‘[poljubio]ω’ alone or ‘[ [ poljubio]ω je]ω’.
Rather than ‘lowering’, it is the process of ‘raising’ that is required here. There are two possibilities. Either Local Dislocation (Embick & Noyer, 2001; Embick, 2007, 2010) or a kind of process that applies to clitics with purely prosodic dependency and which they conveniently label leaning on a host (Embick & Noyer, 2001, fn.6). Crucially, if it is leaning on a host kind of process, unlike in Embick and Noyer, it has to involve raising of the participle, rather than lowering of li (PI).
Assume, for the moment, that it is Local Dislocation (LD) that takes place in polar li-question in BCMS. LD takes place under adjacency (28) and correctly predicts the only acceptable order at PF is (28).
28.F[Q]   ⌢   PRCT → [[PRCT] [F[Q]]]
The proposal raises two immediate issues that need to be addressed. Namely, given Embick and Noyer’s conception of LD, ‘ontological demotion’ of l-participle from M(orphological)-Word to Subword is also expected to take place as a result of it. Clearly, this, however, is not the case. In cases like (23), l-participle remains an M-Word. The fact that l-participle is an M-Word, to begin with, leads to the second issue. Namely, whereas LD can apply to both M-words and Subwords, it cannot target ‘ontologically’ mismatched objects, which, given Embick and Noyer’s treatment of clitics and affixes as syntactically on a par (i.e., Subwords), would exactly be the case here.
Across different languages and within the general architecture of Distributed Morphology (DM), other researchers argue that clitics are an independent syntactic category (see, for instance, Kramer, 2014; Preminger, 2014; Despić, 2017, and, most elaborately, Arregi & Nevins, 2012). Specifically, for BCMS, couched in DM, Despić (2017) offers an elegant account of the availability of ellipsis in cases of clitics and unavailability of ‘suspended affixation’ in BCMS, the crux of which is that the former are M-Words, while affixes are Subwords. As illustrated in (29), quite like other clitics, li can be easily elided, and as typical of ellipsis, this always happens in the second conjunct.
29.Volišlijeicenišlije
Love.PRES.2SGQAUX.3SGandrespectQAUX.3SG
‘Do you love her and respect her?’
As for the lack of ‘ontological demotion’, recall that participles in BCMS (Slavic) are complex, always carrying a sub-set of φ-features (number and gender). Considering this, it is not implausible that they remain ‘unaffected’ by LD because ‘ontological demotion’ would lead to the loss of information (see also Despić, 2017, who reasons along the same lines).
To sum, the proposal here draws a parallel between the finite verb and its corresponding participle in polar questions in BCMS. Both finite verbs and participles involve Movement. However, while finite verbs move in syntax, participles move at PF, undergoing a variant of Morphological Merger of Marantz, 1988 (as understood in Harley & Noyer, 1999; Embick & Noyer, 2001).19

4.3. Ordering of PF Operations: Future I and PQ

The way Polarity Questions (PQ) strategies have been discussed so far might suggest that the inventory of PQ strategies in BCMS is rather sparse. This, however, is not the case. BCMS has a rich inventory of PQ strategies. As illustrated in (30), apart from da-insertion (22b) there is je-insertion, and both da and je have contracted forms, da l’ and je l’ (30b) and (30c), respectively. Further, there is zar, a non-clitic lexicalization of Q (30d). As it only appears in two specific biased contexts (see Todorović, 2024 for discussion and elaboration), zar seems to function as a pragmatically conditioned allomorph of li.20
30.a.Jelisunestale?
PRTQAUX.3PLdisappear.PRCT.3PL.F
‘Have they disappeared?’
b.Je l’ su nestale?
c.Da l’ su nestale?
d.Zarnisunestale?
QNEG.AUX.#PLdisappear.PRCT.3PL.F
‘Haven’t they disappeared?’
Note now that all of these additional strategies take place at Vocabulary Insertion (VI), an operation at PF. Distributed Morphology is a late insertion model; only abstract features are present at the level of Syntax, while all vocabulary insertion takes place post-syntactically at VI. In Section 4.2, it has been argued that the process by which l-participle-li construction is derived takes place at PF, and involves post-syntactic movement (raising) of participle to ensure convergence i.e., pronounceability at PF and it was proposed that the process in question is Local Dislocation (Embick & Noyer, 2001 et seq.)
Embick and Noyer (2001) and Embick (2007, 2010) provide evidence that Local Dislocation applies after Vocabulary Insertion. There is evidence in BCMS polar questions that also suggest that the PF Movement in l-participle-li questions can only take place after VI. Moreover, in what follows, I will show that in Future I polar questions, l-participle PF Movement takes place only after another instance of LD has taken place.
Before presenting and discussing the data, a brief excursion into Despić’s (2017) analysis of Future I is needed. Examples in (31) illustrate Future I in BSCM, formed from the 2P future clitic and an infinitive (31d). Despić (2017) proposes that whenever the future auxiliary appears at the I-phrase boundary and directly precedes an infinitive (31a), Local Dislocation (31b) takes place in order for the 2P requirement of FUT to be met. This post-syntactic re-ordering is followed by the final -i reduction in Standard Croatian and the full ti-reduction (truncation of the infinitive) in Standard Serbian. The full reduction—‘ontological demotion’ of INF—is further followed by place assimilation typical of stem-affix combinations (see Despić, 2017, for details and elaboration), as in (31c). It seems reasonable to conclude that these phonological changes the clitic and the infinitive undergo can only be explained if the movement occurs post-syntactically. Note, further, that when there is an element that can independently satisfy 2P requirement of FUT, available for insertion at VI, no post-syntactic reordering occurs (compare (31d) with (31e)).
31.a.#ćejesti
FUTeat.INF
b.T[fut]  ⌢  V → [[V] [T[fut]]]
c.proJešćeš (/s/changes to/ʃ /in front of/t͡ɕ/)
eat.AUX.FUT.2SG
‘You will eat.’
d.Tićešjesti?
youAUX.FUT.2SGeat
You will eat.’
e.?*Tiješćeš.
Youeat-AUX.FUT.2SG
This small digression allows us to take a deeper look into the ordering of post-syntactic operations in BCMS by exploring the interaction between Future I and polar questions.
First, Future I polar questions (32) demonstrate that BCMS has to allow for some (well-defined) cases of PF Movement. Namely, regardless of one’s particular account, it seems reasonable to conclude that the newly ‘minted’ M-word ješćeš can only be created at PF. This being the case, the operation that is further responsible for its raising to support li (32) must also occur at PF. Hence, we can conclude that the two PF movements are ordered with LD of INF and FUT taking place first, followed by the LD of the synthetic future form ješćeš and li.
32.Ješćešlijagode?
eat.AUX.FUT.2SGQstrawberries
‘Will you eat strawberries?’
Crucially, both instances of PF Movements in BCMS occur after VI, which, further, provides an additional argument that neither of them can be PI. Namely, if phonological material (e.g., da) is inserted at VI, thus being able to satisfy the 2P requirement of clitics (li and ćeš in 33a), post-syntactic reordering—LD of FUT and INF will not take place (compare (33a) with (33b)), since, recall, a single host (da in (34))—inserted at VI—is sufficient to take over the 2P requirement of all the clitics.
33.a.Dalićešjestijagode?
PRTQFUT.2SG.eat. INFstrawberries
‘Will you eat strawberries?’
b.?*Daliješćešjagode?
PRTQeat.FUT.2SGstrawberries
The behavior of synthetic future is quite different from finite verbs, because the ‘finiteness’ of synthetic future is a ‘mirage’, arising from PF reordering of the infinitive and the future clitic. To that extent, note the contrast between (33b) and sentences in (34). Sentences in (34) feature a finite verb and both are, as expected, perfectly fine, since the host is supplied either via movement in syntax or via insertion at VI.
34.a.Dalijedešjagode?
daQeat.PRS.2SGstrawberries
b.Jedeš lijagode?
Eat.PRS.2SG Qstrawberries
‘Are you eating strawberries?’
To sum up, among the PF processes that take place in BCMS, insertion at VI takes place before PF Movement attested in the language. It then seems reasonable to conclude that if 2P requirement of clitics can be satisfied at VI, that is the preferred option. Viewed from this perspective, it is, perhaps, not surprising that the default strategy in BCMS is argued to be that of insertion (see Todorović, 2024; Šimík, forthcoming, for discussion and elaboration). The PF Movement in the case of l-participle-li is truly the last-last resort option when it comes to polar questions in BCMS. Though last-last resort, its application is still to be preferable since the syntactically well-formed structure results in an unpronounceable string at PF. Namely, given that something like (35) holds, an example like (23), repeated here as (36b), should be understood as an instance of a PF repair that allows integration of the clitic into the prosodic structure.
35.Full Interpretation:
In order to be well-formed at PF (i.e., pronounced), phonetic content has to be
incorporated into prosodic structure. (Anderson, 2005: p. 39)
36.a.li {poljubio}ω →{{poljubio} ω li}
b.%Poljubio li je Mariju?
In other words, PF convergence—the need for every prosodic word to be pronounced—forces this last-last resort, post-syntactic mechanism to apply here. Otherwise, if the PF Movement were not to take place, li would not be integrated into the prosodic structure and the string, though grammatical, would remain unpronounceable.21

5. Conclusions

By exploring the behavior of 2P clitics in the left periphery of the clause, this paper probes into the nature of CS-PF interface in BCMS, a language where the positioning of clitics is argued to be accomplished in syntax and where the role of PF is restricted to filtering out the outputs provided by it. Though the brunt of BCMS data (see Bošković, 1995, 2001; Franks, 1998/2010; Stjepanović, 1999, among others) can be accounted for under this approach, recent data on polar questions, arrived through large-scale experiments (see Marelj et al., 2024) as well as data on polar Future I questions suggest that there are well-defined configurations in which post-syntactic operations need to take place in BCMS as well. Contra previous analyses, the account presented here treats li (lexicalization of Q) as a ‘run-of-the-mill’ 2P clitic in BCMS, whose host, when illicit to be provided by movement in syntax, can be provided by post-syntactic movement. I provide evidence against Prosodic Inversion—‘the usual suspect’ for post-syntactic movement in Slavic—thus adding to the body of evidence that PI does not take place in BCMS. I argue that the PF Movement in such cases has to be one of raising and adopt Local Dislocation (Embick & Noyer, 2001; Embick, 2007, 2010) to account for them. Probing into the interaction between Future I and polar questions provides further insights into the ordering of the PF Movement operations in BCMS.

Funding

The research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

The original contributions presented in this study are included in the article. Further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Boban Arsenijeviċ, Željko Bošković, Steven Franks, Catherine Rudin, Marko Simonović, Radek Šimik, Guy Tabachnick, the audiences of XIV Workshop on Formal Linguistics at the Federal University of Rio de Janeiro, 19th Annual Meeting of the Slavic Linguistic Society, SinFonija 17, two anonymous Reviewers of the paper for this volume and the editors for helpful and insightful comments. All errors remain my own.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Notes

1
The insight that clitics are phonologically dependent has been held in the majority of both typologically and theoretically oriented works. A clitic is ‘a linguistic element whose phonological form is deficient in that it lacks prosodic structure at the level of the Prosodic Word’ (Anderson, 2005: p. 23). Clitics lack stress, either due to their inability to bear it or to be targeted by rules of stress assignment (see Dixon, 2007; Franks, 2016; Marušič et al., 2024, to name but a few). With the ambitious goal to cover clitics in the ‘world’s languages’, Haspelmath (2023) is a notable exception to this view, but the account is not devoid of challenges (see Haspelmath, 2023 for details and Marelj (n.d.) for discussion).
2
The cross-linguistic ‘nonselectivity’ (Haspelmath, 2023) or ‘promiscuous attachment/promiscuity’ (Zwicky, 1987, p. 136) has been argued to be one of the hallmark characteristics of clitics. Technically, the criterion is either viewed as a ‘tendency’ (see Zwicky & Pullum, 1983, p. 503) or understood as ‘categorical’, whereby ‘any deviation from full class selectivity means that the element in question must be a clitic rather than an affix’ (see Haspelmath, 2023, p. 36). Note, in passing, that Bulgarian and Macedonian clausal clitics (otherwise, ‘run-of-the-mill’ clitics) are host-sensitive (V-adjacent) and thus pose a problem for the categorical view.
3
Second-position or ‘2P’ clitics are also known as Wackernagel clitics because it was Jackob Wackernagel who observed that they appear in second position in their respective clause in early Indo-European languages. As pointed out by Anderson (1993), it is less known that Wackernagel also proposed this as a basis for the ‘Verb Second’ phenomenon.
4
Since Hamblin (1973), the most common way of modelling the lack of truth-conditions in polar questions is to give them the denotation of the set of propositions which constitute the question’s possible answers: {p, ¬p}, which for an utterance in (1) correspond to ‘You are buying it for him’ and ‘You are not buying it for him’.
5
As indicated in (2), the only exception to this rigid ordering is AUX.3SG je (‘is’), argued to be losing clitichood (see Browne, 1975/2004; Schütze, 1994, among others). Being too ‘weak’ to host the rest of the clitics, but ‘strong’ enough to prevent other clitics from satisfying their 2P requirement if adjacent to the host, it must occur cluster-final (see Bošković, 1995, 2001 for elaboration and discussion).
6
The symbol % means that the sentence is not judged as grammatical by all speakers.
7
There are intriguing interpretative differences between the W1 and P1 sentences. Since they will not bear on the argument here, for brevity, I gloss over them. The reader is referred to Diesing et al. (2009); Diesing (2010); and Diesing and Zec (2011) for discussion and elaboration.
8
This type of participle is attested in all Slavic languages, with no comparable variant in Germanic or Romance. Though English translation might suggest otherwise, this is not an instance of a passive participle, but an active one. It combines with the finite form of the auxiliary to be to form perfect tenses and (partially) agrees in φ-features (number and gender, but—crucially—not person) with Subject.
9
For Schwabe’ (2004) account, the relevant point of the mapping between syntax and phonology is (i):
(i)a.lisimuihdavao
QAUX.2SGmu.DATthem.ACCgive.PRCT.SG.M
b.[CP li [TP si mu ih davao [AgrsSP si mu ih davao…]]]
c.li {davao} ω si mu ih→li {{davao} ω si}c mu ih
d.li {{davao}ω si mu ih}c→*{{davao}ω li}c si}c mu ih
If there is an auxiliary clitic (e.g., AUX.2SG in (i)) in the derivation and the potential host for it is a participle (davao in (i)), the former cliticizes onto its host as soon as the latter is available (ic), crucially, before the PI of li and the participle can take place. For that reason, in order to cliticize onto the participle, li needs to cross two phonological boundaries, which is illicit. Hence, under Schwabe’s account, the violation that accounts for the unacceptability of (10b) occurs in any instance of a polar li-question, where the host is a participle, and the cluster contains an auxiliary clitic. It is for that reason that its validity is tested by using a non-clitic auxiliary (11b).
10
This statement needs no further categorization for BCMS, in particular or Slavic, in general. I have nothing to say about participles and finite verbs in Akhvakh (see Creissels, 2009), for instance, short of that they certainly require attention and further research.
11
The relevance of the feature [+finite] for movement to C has long been noted. For instance, in Germanic, verbal elements that otherwise overtly join each other to form verbal complexes (see Roberts, 1991; Zwart, 1995; Den Dikken & Hoekstra, 1997, among others) get split, with only finite verbs moving to C, and [-finite] ones being forced to stay behind.
12
Since it does not bear on the argument here, I leave the nature of da for further research. For the purposes of discussion here, it is not relevant whether it is treated as a ‘dummy’ morph inserted in morphology as a PF-repair, rather than a complementizer or a tonic form of li. Crucially, it is inserted at VI and its insertion satisfies the 2Phood of li. See Section 4 for more discussion and elaboration.
13
For brevity, the structure in (14c) is simplified to reflect only those layers that are relevant for the discussion here.
14
Though less precise, in terms of the issues at the core of the paper, by and large, it would be inconsequential if, instead of a finely articulated CP-domain, li was treated as located in C.
15
For insightful discussion regarding the topic, see Ilc and Milojević Sheppard (2002); Roberts (2010), for instance.
16
Since it does not bear on the argument here, for brevity, I do not discuss a possible alternative analysis with li lexicalizing Int. (along the lines of the cases of lexicalized ForceP and IntP in Spanish, for instance—see Demonte & Fernández-Soriano, 2009).
17
For additional empirical evidence, the reader is referred to Marelj et al. (2024).
18
The reader is referred to Ćavar and Wilder (1994, 1996); Franks and Progovac (1994); Progovac (1996); Franks (1998/2010); Franks and King (2000); and especially Bošković (2001: pp. 11–36), for a comprehensive overview of the arguments against PI in BCMS.
19
As discussed in Marelj et al. (2024), whereas computer-based acceptability tasks allow for a generous quantity of data, they also have their drawbacks. For one thing, the experiment was designed in such a way that the sentences were presented in isolation, without any contextual furnishing related to the markedness/neutrality of different PQ-strategies in BCMS. Todorović (2024); Šimík (forthcoming) argue that the default strategy appropriate in the so-called ‘quiz scenarios’ in BCMS is da-li and a positive form of the verb/verbal complex. It is not inconceivable that (at least) a subset of participants considered the l-participle-li sentences inappropriate, rather than ungrammatical. Hence, the relatively low acceptance rate of the l-participle-li construction could, to an extent, be an artifact of the experimental design. Further research is needed to corroborate/refute this. A paper-and-pen experiment, for instance, that allows probing into both discourse and prosodic information would be a good start.
20
It has been argued that je li is a full/non-clitic forms/counterpart of the clitic li (Browne, 1975/2004; Radanović-Kocić, 1988; Bošković, 2001; Franks, 2016). The same has been argued for da li, with je li being ‘colloquial style’ (Browne, 1975/2004). Short of the fact that they satisfy 2Pness of li, the nature of—particularly da—is not entirely clear and I leave the issue for further research not least because of the complexities it brings. It is well-known that da is a complementizer, clause-typing embedded [+finite, +declarative] clauses (i.e., Znam da radiš (I know that you are working)). Intriguingly, another instance of da finds itself in subjunctive (Želim da radiš (I want you to work)), root optative (Da te bar vidim!/(If only I could see you)), and imperative clauses (Da se nisi usudio!(Don’t you dare!)) It, however, does not appear in matrix if-clauses or, most crucially, in polar zar-questions. Short of being biased PQs, zar-polar questions differ from li-ones only with respect to the fact that unlike li, zar is not a clitic. Last but not least, though the mechanics of the ‘allomorphy selection’ here are outside of the scope of the paper, it has long been noted that not all allomorphy is phonologically optimal and that there are cases of allomorphs sensitive to syntactic or lexical contexts (see De Belder, 2020, for an elaborate discussion, references, and an insightful proposal).
21
As it is outside of the scope of this paper, the intriguing questions pertaining to the (potential) pragmatic differences between PQ strategies in BCMS is not explored here. I concur with the conclusion (see Šimík, forthcoming) that da-li questions are neutral, but I also note that, for me, it is difficult to pin down if, and (if yes) what kind of pragmatic differences exist between da-li and je-li. Da-li might be the most frequently used and in that sense ‘default’, but that doesn’t necessarily entail that it is the default strategy pragmatically, since (as elaborately discussed by Šimík, forthcoming), ‘the function of a polar question is rarely just to ask a question’. Very often, PQ conveys speaker’s attitude (bias) towards the possible answer(s). In Negative Polar Questions the fine nuances among different biased questions are clearly demonstrable (see Todorović, 2024 for discussion and elaboration), but it is much harder to demonstrate these in Positive Polar Questions. There are clearly registral differences, with the contracted da’l and je’l being more informal and there are (perhaps) descriptive or (prescriptive) areal differences across the Serbo-Croatian continuum. In terms of their interpretation, the only clearly biased PQ strategies (to my mind) are the zar and l-participle-li one. Both da-li, je-li PQs and the finite-V-li PQ can all, minimally, be construed as pragmatically neutral.

References

  1. Anderson, S. R. (1993). Wackernagel’s revenge: Clitics, morphology, and the syntax of second position. Language, 69(1), 68–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Anderson, S. R. (2005). Aspects of the theory of clitics. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  3. Arregi, K., & Nevins, A. (2012). Morphotactics: Basque auxiliaries and the structure of spellout. Springer. [Google Scholar]
  4. Bošković, Ž. (1995). Participle movement and second position cliticization in Serbo-Croatian. Lingua, 96, 245–266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Bošković, Ž. (2001). On the nature of the syntax-phonology interface: Cliticization and related phenomena. In North-holland linguistic series: Linguistic variation (Vol. 60). Elsevier Science Ltd. [Google Scholar]
  6. Browne, W. (2004). Serbo-Croatian enclitics for English-speaking learners. In Kontrastivna analiza engleskog i hrvatskog ili srpskog jezika (pp. 105–134). Institut za lingvistiku Filozofskog fakulteta. (Original work published 1975). [Google Scholar]
  7. Creissels, D. (2009). Participles and finiteness: The case of Akhvakh. Linguistic Discovery, 7(1), 106–130. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Ćavar, D., & Wilder, C. (1994). Clitic third in Croatian. Eurotyp Working Papers, 6, 19–61. [Google Scholar]
  9. Ćavar, D., & Wilder, C. (1996). On cliticization in Croatian: Syntax or prosody? ZAS Papers in Linguistics, 6, 51–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. De Belder, M. (2020). A split approach to the selection of allomorphs: Vowel length alternating allomorphy in Dutch. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics, 5(1), 42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Demonte, V., & Fernández-Soriano, O. (2009). Force and finiteness in the Spanish complementizer system. Probus, 21, 23–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Den Dikken, M. D., & Hoekstra, E. (1997). Parasitic participles. Linguistics, 35, 1057–1089. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Despić, M. (2017). Suspended morphology in Serbian: Clitics vs. affixes. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics, 2(1), 12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Diesing, M. (2010). Clitics revisited. In Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics (FASL) 18: The Cornell meeting. Michigan Slavic Publishers. Available online: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/322086922_Clitics_Revisited (accessed on 13 August 2025).
  15. Diesing, M., Filipović-Ðurdjević, D., & Zec, D. (2009). Clitic placement in Serbian: Corpus and experimental evidence. In S. Winkler, & S. Featherston (Eds.), The fruits of empirical linguistics (Vol. 2, pp. 59–74). De Gruyter Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Diesing, M., & Zec, D. (2011). Interface effects: Serbian clitics. Syntax & Semantics, 37, 1–30. [Google Scholar]
  17. Dixon, R. M. W. (2007). Clitics in English. English Studies, 88(5), 574–600. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Embick, D. (2007). Linearization and local dislocation: Derivational mechanics and interactions. Linguistic Analysis, 33, 2–35. [Google Scholar]
  19. Embick, D. (2010). Localism versus globalism in morphology and phonology. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. Embick, D., & Izvorski, R. (1997). Participle-auxiliary word orders in Slavic. In Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics: The cornell meeting (pp. 210–239). Michigan Slavic Publishers. Available online: https://www.ling.upenn.edu/~embick/partaux.pdf (accessed on 13 August 2025).
  21. Embick, D., & Noyer, R. (2001). Movement operations after syntax. Linguistic Inquiry, 32, 555–595. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Franks, S. (2008). Clitic placement, prosody, and the Bulgarian verbal complex. Journal of Slavic Linguistics, 16(1), 91–137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Franks, S. (2010). Clitics in Slavic. Glossos 10: Contemporary issues in Slavic linguistics. Available online: http://slaviccenters.duke.edu/projects/glossos-journal/issues/issue-10 (accessed on 13 August 2025). (Original work published 1998).
  24. Franks, S. (2016). Clitics are/become minimalist. In F. Lanko Marušić, & R. Zaucer (Eds.), Formal studies in Slovenian syntax: In honor of Janez Orešnik (pp. 91–128). John Benjamins. [Google Scholar]
  25. Franks, S., & King, T. H. (2000). A handbook of Slavic clitics. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  26. Franks, S., & Progovac, L. (1994). On the placement of Serbo-Croatian clitics. Indiana Linguistic Studies, 7, 69–78. [Google Scholar]
  27. Halpern, A. (1995). On the placement and morphology of clitics. CSLI Publications. (Original work published 1992). [Google Scholar]
  28. Hamblin, C. L. (1973). Questions in montague grammar. Foundations of Language, 10, 41–53. [Google Scholar]
  29. Harley, H., & Noyer, R. (1999). Distributed morphology. Glot International, 4, 3–9. [Google Scholar]
  30. Haspelmath, M. (2023). Types of clitics in the world’s languages. Linguistic Typology at the Crossroads, 3, 1–59. [Google Scholar]
  31. Ilc, G., & Milojević Sheppard, M. (2002). Verb movement and interrogatives. Linguistica, 42(1), 161–176. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  32. Izvorski, R., King, T. H., & Rudin, C. (1997). Against li lowering in Bulgarian. Lingua, 102(2–3), 187–194. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Kramer, R. (2014). Clitic doubling or object agreement: The view from Amharic. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 32, 593–634. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Marantz, A. (1988). Clitics, morphological merger, and the mapping to phonological structure. In M. Hammond, & M. Noonan (Eds.), Theoretical morphology: Approaches in modern linguistics (pp. 253–270). Emerald Group Publishing. [Google Scholar]
  35. Marelj, M. (n.d.). Indo-European: Slavic. In E. Bonet, & D. Pescarini (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of clitics. Oxford University Press.
  36. Marelj, M., Bosnić, A., & Spitzers, M. (2024). The clitic li at the syntax-phonology interface: An experimentally informed account. In S. Halupka-Rešetar, S. Martínez Ferreiro, & N. Ilić (Eds.), Studies in language and mind 5 (pp. 79–99). Filozofski fakultet Novi Sad. [Google Scholar]
  37. Marušič, F. L., Mišmaš, P., & Žaucer, R. (2024). Placement and ordering of the (en) clitics. In D. Šipka, & W. Browne (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of Slavic linguistics (pp. 365–384). Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  38. Migdalski, K. (2006). The syntax of compound tenses in Slavic [Ph.D. thesis, Tilburg University]. [Google Scholar]
  39. Migdalski, K. (2009). On two types of Wackernagel cliticization in Slavic. In J. Reich, M. Babyonyshev, & D. Kavitskaya (Eds.), Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics: The yale meeting (pp. 147–162). Michigan Slavic Publications. [Google Scholar]
  40. Preminger, O. (2014). Agreement and its failures. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  41. Progovac, L. (1996). Clitics in Serbian/Croatian: Comp as the second position. In A. Halpern, & A. Zwicky (Eds.), Approaching second: Second position clitics and related phenomena (pp. 411–428). CSLI Publications. [Google Scholar]
  42. Progovac, L. (2000). Where do clitics cluster? In F. Beukma, & M. den Dikken (Eds.), Clitics phenomena in European languages (pp. 249–258). John Benjamins. [Google Scholar]
  43. Progovac, L. (2005). A syntax of Serbian: Clausal architecture. Slavica Publishers. [Google Scholar]
  44. Radanović-Kocić, V. (1988). The grammar of Serbo-Croatian clitics: A synchronic and diachronic perspective [Doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign]. [Google Scholar]
  45. Radanović-Kocić, V. (1996). Placement of Serbo-Croatian clitics: A prosodic approach. In A. Halpern, & A. Zwicky (Eds.), Approaching second: Second position clitics and related phenomena (pp. 429–445). CSLI Publications. [Google Scholar]
  46. Rivero, M.-L. (1993). Bulgarian and Serbo-Croatian yes-no questions: Vº raising to li vs. li hopping. Linguistic Inquiry, 24(4), 567–575. [Google Scholar]
  47. Rizzi, L. (1997). The fine structure of the left periphery. In L. Haegeman (Ed.), Elements of grammar: A handbook of generative syntax (pp. 281–337). Kluwer. [Google Scholar]
  48. Rizzi, L. (2001). On the position “Int(errogative)” in the left periphery of the clause. Current Studies in Italian Syntax, 14, 267–296. [Google Scholar]
  49. Rizzi, L. (2004). Locality and left periphery. In A. Belletti (Ed.), Structures and beyond: The cartography of syntactic structures (pp. 223–251). Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  50. Rizzi, L., & Bocci, G. (2017). Left periphery of the clause: Primarily illustrated for Italian. In M. Everaert, & H. C. van Riemsdijk (Eds.), The Wiley Blackwell companion to syntax (pp. 1–30). Wiley Online Library. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  51. Roberts, I. (1991). Excorporation and minimality. Linguistic Inquiry, 22(2), 209–218. [Google Scholar]
  52. Roberts, I. (2010). Agreement and head movement. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  53. Rudnickaya, E. (2000). The derivation of yes-no li questions in Russian: Syntax and/or phonology? In T. H. King, & I. Sekerina (Eds.), Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics: The Philadelphia meeting (pp. 347–362). Michigan Slavic Publications. [Google Scholar]
  54. Schütze, C. (1994). Serbo-Croatian second position clitics placement and the phonology-syntax interface. In A. Carnie, H. Harley, & T. Bures (Eds.), MIT working papers in linguistics 21 (pp. 373–473). MIT. [Google Scholar]
  55. Schwabe, K. (2004). The particle li at the left periphery of Slavic yes/no questions. In H. Lohnstein, & S. Trissler (Eds.), The syntax and semantics of the left periphery (pp. 385–430). De Gruyter Mouton. [Google Scholar]
  56. Stjepanović, S. (1998). On the placement of Serbo-Croatian clitics: Evidence from VP ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry, 29(3), 527–537. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Stjepanović, S. (1999). What do second position cliticization, scrambling, and multiple Wh-fronting have in common? [Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut]. [Google Scholar]
  58. Šimík, R. (forthcoming). Polar question semantics and bias: Lessons from Slavic/Czech. In B. Gehrke, & R. Šimík (Eds.), Topics in the semantics of Slavic languages. Language Science Press.
  59. Todorović, N. (2024). What are we asking with a polar question in Serbian? Journal of Slavic Linguistics, 32(3), 1–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  60. Vakareliyska, C. (2023). When the question is why, not how: Stress on a clitic that immediately follows a negator in Bulgarian. Slovo: Journal of Slavic Languages, Literature and Cultures, 63, 8–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Wilder, C., & Ćavar, D. (2002). Verb movement, cliticization, and coordination. In P. Kosta, & J. Frasek (Eds.), Current approaches to formal Slavic linguistics (pp. 365–375). Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
  62. Zwart, J.-W. (1995). A note on verb clusters in the Stellingwerfs dialect. In M. den Dikken, & K. Hengeveld (Eds.), Linguistics in the Netherlands 1995 (pp. 215–226). John Benjamins. [Google Scholar]
  63. Zwart, J.-W. (2020). Head movement and morphological strength. Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics, 2, 1–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  64. Zwicky, A. M. (1987). Suppressing the Zs. Journal of Linguistics, 23(1), 133–148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Zwicky, A. M., & Pullum, G. K. (1983). Cliticization vs. inflection: English n’t. Language, 59(3), 502–513. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Marelj, M. Mismatches and Mitigation at CS-PF Interface: The Curious Case of li. Languages 2025, 10, 210. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages10090210

AMA Style

Marelj M. Mismatches and Mitigation at CS-PF Interface: The Curious Case of li. Languages. 2025; 10(9):210. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages10090210

Chicago/Turabian Style

Marelj, Marijana. 2025. "Mismatches and Mitigation at CS-PF Interface: The Curious Case of li" Languages 10, no. 9: 210. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages10090210

APA Style

Marelj, M. (2025). Mismatches and Mitigation at CS-PF Interface: The Curious Case of li. Languages, 10(9), 210. https://doi.org/10.3390/languages10090210

Article Metrics

Article metric data becomes available approximately 24 hours after publication online.
Back to TopTop