Wittgenstein on the Grammar of Unshakeable Religious Beliefs
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. Lecture on Religious Beliefs
Suppose somebody made this guidance for this life: believing in the Last Judgement. Whenever he does anything, this is before his mind. In a way, how are we to know whether to say he believes this will happen or not?
But he has what you might call an unshakeable belief. It will show, not by reasoning or by appeal to ordinary grounds for belief, but rather by regulating for all in his life.This is a very much stronger fact—foregoing pleasures, always appealing to this picture. This is [sic] one sense must be called the firmest of all beliefs, because the man risks things on account of it which he would not do on things which are by far better established for him. Although he distinguishes between things well-established and not well-established.Lewy: Surely, he would say it is extremely well-established.First, he may use “well-established” or not use it at all. He will treat this belief as extremely well-established, and in another way as not well-established at all.If we have a belief, in certain cases we appeal again and again to certain grounds, and at the same time we risk pretty little—if it came to risking our lives on the ground of this belief.There are instances where you have a faith—where you say “I believe”—and on the other hand this belief does not rest on the fact on which our ordinary everyday beliefs normally do rest.
Suppose someone is ill and he says: “This is a punishment,” and I say: “If I’m ill, I don’t think of punishment at all.” If you say: “Do you believe the opposite?”—you can call it believing the opposite, but it is entirely different from what we would normally call believing the opposite.I think differently, in a different way. I say different things to myself. I have different pictures […].Here believing obviously plays much more this role: suppose we said that a certain picture might play the role of constantly admonishing me, or I always think of it. Here, an enormous difference would be between those people for whom the picture is constantly in the foreground, and the others who just didn’t use it at all.
The point is that if there were evidence, this would in fact destroy the whole business.Anything that I normally call evidence wouldn’t in the slightest influence me.Suppose, for instance, we knew people who foresaw the future; make forecasts for years and years ahead; and they described some sort of a Judgement Day. Queerly enough, even if there were such a thing, and even if it were more convincing than I have described, belief in this happening wouldn’t be at all a religious belief.Suppose that I would have to forego all pleasures because of such a forecast. If I do so and so, someone will put me in fires in a thousand years, etc. I wouldn’t budge. The best scientific evidence is just nothing […].We don’t talk about hypothesis, or about high probability. Nor about knowing.In a religious discourse we use such expressions as: “I believe that so and so will happen,” and use them differently to the way in which we use them in science.
But I would ridicule it [making the religious belief reasonable], not by saying it is based on insufficient evidence. I would say: here is a man who is cheating himself. You can say: this man is ridiculous because he believes, and bases it on weak reasons.
3. The Grammar of Religious Belief
- It does not rest on normal grounds for belief.
- It is totally regulating for one’s life.
- One is willing to take great risks based on it.
LIFE-REGULATING: A belief that regulates your entire life.RISK: A belief you are willing to take great risks based on.GROUNDLESS: Evidence is irrelevant to the language game the belief is part of.12UNSHAKEABLE: LIFE-REGULATING + RISK + GROUNDLESSRELIGIOUS: ?
Wittgenstein is plainly right that religious belief involves the things he says it does: the use of a set of distinctively religious concepts in describing and thinking about the world; a commitment to lead one’s life in a certain way; and a certain pattern of evaluations of oneself and others. But is he right that that is all there is to religious belief? In particular, is he right to deny that religious belief essentially involves a host of factual beliefs[?]
[I]t seems plausible to think, his account does not accurately capture the character of the beliefs that most religious believers have actually held, either now or in previous generations.
4. Concluding Remarks
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For a comprehensive discussion and overview of secondary literature, see Carroll (2014). See also Schönbaumsfeld (2023), particularly section 1.4. I will—as Wittgenstein himself did—focus on Christianity. See Andrejč and Weiss (2019) for interreligious themes. I will interact minimally with the secondary literature, but it will be obvious to those familiar with it that the results we arrive at in this text will undermine much that has been attributed to Wittgenstein and consequently also some of the criticism of his position, for instance, Nielsen (1967) and Law (2017). In this text I want to maintain a sharp focus on what Wittgenstein himself says, and I hope to demonstrate the consequences for the secondary literature in future work. For a recent text arguing that Wittgenstein holds a form of non-cognitivism in this lecture, see Pichler and Sunday Grève (2025). For the claim that non-cognitivism has a strong foothold in the secondary literature, consider Ellis (2025): “Those who endorse Wittgenstein’s later approach to religion, who I shall refer to as Wittgensteinians, are traditionally presented as non-cognitivists since they deny the importance and relevance of evidence and truth in religion”. He continues in a footnote: ibid. fn. 1, “Cottingham (2017, p. 639) acknowledges the commonality of this presentation; Glock (1996, p. 321) describes Wittgenstein as having a non-cognitivist view of religious language; and Pichler and Sunday Grève (2025) address the non-cognitivist presentation throughout”. Hyman (2001) also attributes non-cognitivism to Wittgenstein. Furthermore, I will later discuss Child (2011, p. 224), who gives voice to the view that Wittgenstein both “deny that religious belief essentially involves a host of factual beliefs” and that “his account does not accurately capture the character of the beliefs that most religious believers have actually held, either now or in previous generations.” (ibid. p. 225). A similar view is found in Pichler and Sunday Grève (2025) (see footnote 31 for a relevant passage). On a more cautionary note, Law (2017, p. 1187) observes that it is widely accepted that Wittgenstein regarded grammatical investigations of religious utterances—such as “We will face a Judgement Day”—as “very different to the way in which we typically use the superficially similar sentences […] ‘We will come before a judge and jury’”. As will become clear, I do not fundamentally disagree with Law’s point, though I caution against attributing to Wittgenstein the stronger claim that religious language must always or necessarily diverge from non-religious language. |
2 | The lecture as we have it was not penned by Wittgenstein himself but by Yorick Smythies. This may lead one to be skeptical about relying too heavily on the source. A prominent interpreter puts it this way: “The text of the ‘Lectures on Religious Belief’ is doubly unreliable: For one thing, the students writing those notes may have misunderstood or misremembered what Wittgenstein said. For another thing, what Wittgenstein said in those improvised and informal classes may well have been tentative or carelessly phrased.” Schröder (2007, fn. 4). Such exegetical concerns will not occupy me. If one wishes, one can replace every instance where I say the philosopher ‘Wittgenstein’ in this text with ‘Smythies-Wittgenstein’. I believe the lecture is entirely consistent with other things we know Wittgenstein himself wrote, but I will not defend this further here. See Pichler (2025), who argues that it is not consistent with remarks Wittgenstein later made on the subject. See also Pichler (2025, note 3) for a discussion of whether Wittgenstein actually gave this lecture. |
3 | This is not to say that there are no epistemological or metaphysical consequences following from how we talk about religious beliefs. |
4 | I will call it a language game even though Wittgenstein himself does not explicitly use this phrase in the lecture. |
5 | |
6 | Beyond the purely linguistic analysis, Wittgenstein also refers to the Bible: “Anyone who reads the Epistles will find it said: not only that it is not reasonable, but that it is folly. Not only is it not reasonable, but it doesn’t pretend to be.” Wittgenstein (1966, p. 58) |
7 | One can, of course, turn it around and say that it is the religious person who misunderstands the language game. It is not a belief he has; rather, it is an interaction of thoughts, images, and orientations that lie behind his expression of believing in Judgment Day. But our example is based on the religious person’s seemingly normal linguistic statement. This is what he expresses. Our task is to describe religious language use. |
8 | More on this in the next section. |
9 | Based on this, one might be tempted to attribute a form of non-cognitivism to Wittgenstein. |
10 | My aim is to demonstrate that Wittgenstein’s lecture on religious belief can be read in a manner analogous to how I believe we ought to read the Philosophical Investigations. It is not the phenomenon itself he discusses directly, but rather he examines how we speak about it—and through this, explores its possibilities (see Philosophical Investigations §90 (Wittgenstein 2009)). However, the claim that the lecture is compatible with the Investigations is highly contested in the secondary literature. For a recent critique of such a reading see Pichler and Sunday Grève (2025), and it is not something that can simply be assumed at the outset. For another example, Richter (2001) argues that Wittgenstein’s remarks on religion are clearly incompatible with the Investigation unless they are understood as part of a strictly personal dialogue. In constrast, the present text proposes an alternative approach. I do not claim to offer a novel interpretation of religious belief-statements through the lens of the Investigations. Rather, I am to show that, despite initial appearances, the lecture does not stand in a problematic relation to the Investigations. Moreover, I argue that it does not commit Wittgenstein to a general non-cognitivist stance on religious belief-statements, nor to the view that religious belief-statements must be unshakeable. These points will be developed in the sections that follow. |
11 | This point warrants further emphasis. Introducing the distinctions is done to help make explicit Wittgenstein’s description of the particular language game under discussion. These distinctions are not intended to essentialize Wittgenstein’s position nor to overlook key insights from the Philosophical Investigations such as familiy resemblance. On the contrary, the central claim of the paper is precisely that the lecture describes a situation in which it is accurate to say that someone uses a religious statement in an unshakeable way, while simultaneously showing how this does not essentialize nor generalize to belief-statements, in general making it look as if Wittgenstein denies (or accepts) cognitivism. On the other hand, it is a common misunderstanding to think that Wittgenstein categorically rejects the possibility of clear boundaries or explicit definitions. His point, rather, is that such clarity should not be presumed to be the norm, nor should it be regarded as inherently superior or exhaustive of linguistic practice. In some cases, a sharply defined concept is precisely how we use language—see for instance Philosophical Investigations §§68-9. I do not claim that Wittgenstein employs the term unshakeable with precise boundaries in this lecture, even if the distinctions I introduce might initially suggest otherwise. My argument is that, even if he did, this would not entail a commitment to non-cognitivism, nor would it reflect a misunderstanding of religious practice. The mistaken interpretation is to read Wittgenstein as offering in this lecture a general grammar of religious belief. What he is doing, rather, is describing a specific context in which it may not be appropriate to interpret a religious utterance as a cognitive statement. Moreover, Wittgenstein is not committed to the view that even an unshakeable belief must be non-cognitive. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to clarify these points. |
12 | Note that we define this as irrelevant to the language game—in this way, we avoid situations where individuals, due to personal shortcomings, refuse to consider evidence they should have considered, etc. Wittgenstein is not concerned with such epistemological points; rather, he aims to describe language games. |
13 | If one makes an analogy between UNSHAKEABLE and hinge beliefs, then an UNSHAKEABLE belief will not necessarily be something we call religious. I will not discuss hinge beliefs further. For a critical discussion of Duncan Pritchard’s use of hinge beliefs in religious epistemology, see Coliva (2025). Using another distinction introduced by Price (1965), we could say that an unshakeable belief might both be a belief-in and a belief-that depending on the situation. For a recent application of the distinction between a belief-in and a belief-that to questions of Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion, see Ellis (2025). |
14 | We can also, à la Pascal’s wager, imagine that you are willing to take disproportionately large risks based on this because the consequences, if it turns out to be correct and you do not account for it, would be so catastrophic. However, it would be a very peculiar reading to interpret Wittgenstein as saying that LIFE-REGULATING, RISK, and GROUNDLESS are directly dependent on each other. It makes little sense, for example, to say that one is willing to take risks because evidence is irrelevant. Or that one is willing to let something be life-regulating because it is groundless. |
15 | We also have little reason, in addition to more general worries about precise boundaries of natural language, to attribute to Wittgenstein the claim that RELIGIOUS = GROUNDLESS. |
16 | Wittgenstein does not seem to reject the fact that there are distinctively religious statements: “We come to an island and we find beliefs there, and certain beliefs we are inclined to call religious. What I’m driving at is, that religious beliefs will not… They have sentences, and there are also religious statements. These statements would not just differ in respect to what they are about. Entirely different connections would make them into religious beliefs, and there can easily be imagined transitions where we wouldn’t know for our life whether to call them religious beliefs or scientific beliefs.” Wittgenstein (1966, p. 58) |
17 | As I will argue in more detail later, I maintain that elements outside the person herself and her mental content are equally decisive in determining whether we, and Wittgenstein, would call it a religious belief. This should not be a surprising result within the context of the Philosophical Investigations, where meaning is often located in use and context rather than in internal states alone. Nevertheless, this reading contrasts with prominent interpretations of the lecture, which some take to be in tension with Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. My aim is to show that such tension is not inevitable and that the lecture can be read in a way that is fully consonant with the broader methodological commitments of the Investigations. |
18 | |
19 | It may be interesting to compare the use of “superstition” in 5.1361 of Wittgenstein (1922). |
20 | Particularly prominent is the use of various passages in Culture and Value (Wittgenstein 1998). An important exception in the secondary literature is Schröder (2007), who makes the distinction we have made here. However, Schröder’s focus is mainly on the person Wittgenstein, and in my opinion, he is not sensitive enough to what Wittgenstein says about the grammar of religious beliefs. For example, he states that Wittgenstein makes a “rhetorical overstatement” (p. 456) when he rejects that there is a contradiction between the religious person and the atheist. My point, rather, is that the entire purpose of the lecture is to show that there is no contradiction in this particular language game by examining the grammar of religious beliefs. |
21 | Schröder (2007, p. 453) seems to agree: “Wittgenstein was concerned only with the type of faith he found appealing; he was not interested in describing all possible forms of religious belief, or the essence of religious belief.” |
22 | It is important to note that Child does not rely solely on Wittgenstein’s lecture. Regarding other secondary literature and how other thinkers have used Wittgenstein’s ideas to address substantial questions in the philosophy of religion, Mulhall (2011) is a good place to start. My position is, of course, that this is precisely the type of substantial philosophy Wittgenstein aims to challenge. |
23 | “Father O’Hara was a professor of physics and mathematics at Heythrop College, London, who participated in a BBC debate about science and religion in the 1930s, and who thought that recent developments in relativity theory and quantum mechanics provided evidence for the existence of God.” Schönbaumsfeld (2023, p. 25). |
24 | |
25 | See for example §88 in Philosophical Investigations. |
26 | The quote in footnote 16 approaches this point. |
27 | The role that such evidence plays can vary significantly between a religious and a non-religious context. Particularly, evidence in a religious context does not necessarily serve to rationalize religious beliefs. What characterizes your religious belief is not (necessarily) that you base it on evidence but rather how you relate to evidence about historical facts. “In a religious discourse we use such expressions as: “I believe that so and so will happen”, and use them differently to the way in which we use them in science. Although, there is a great temptation to think we do. Because we do talk of evidence, and do talk of evidence by experience. We could even talk of historic events. It has been said that Christianity rests on an historic basis. It has been said a thousand times by intelligent people that indubitability is not enough in this case. Even if there is as much evidence as for Napoleon. Because the indubitability wouldn’t be enough to make me change my whole life. It doesn’t rest on an historic basis in the sense that the ordinary belief in historic facts could serve as a foundation. Here we have a belief in historic facts different from a belief in ordinary historic facts. Even, they are not treated as historical, empirical, propositions. Those people who had faith didn’t apply the doubt which would ordinarily apply to any historical propositions. Especially propositions of a time long past, etc.” Wittgenstein (1966, pp. 57–8). |
28 | Thus, when Pichler and Sunday Grève (2025, p. 72) ask why “Wittgenstein appears to have been so blind at times to the ways in which religious people actually use religious belief statements is an interesting and difficult question”, the fact of the matter, at least as it pertains to this lecture, is that he shows no such blindness. One might of course have other reasons for attributing a substantial philosophy of religion or the project of mapping the complete grammar of religious statements to Wittgenstein; my aim has simply been to show that one does not find the resources for such a claim in this lecture. |
References
- Andrejč, Galen, and Duncan H. Weiss, eds. 2019. Interpreting Interreligious Relations with Wittgenstein: Philosophy, Theology, and Religious Studies. Leiden: Brill, vol. 9. [Google Scholar]
- Carroll, Timothy D. 2014. Wittgenstein within the Philosophy of Religion, 1st ed. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Child, William. 2011. Wittgenstein, 1st ed. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Citron, Gabriel. 2012. Simple Objects of Comparison for Complex Grammars: An Alternative Strand in Wittgenstein’s Later Remarks on Religion. Philosophical Investigations 35: 18–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Coliva, Annalisa. 2025. Against Quasi-Fideism. Religions 16: 365. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cottingham, John. 2017. Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. In A Companion to Wittgenstein. Edited by Hans-Johann Glock and John Hyman. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy 63. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell, pp. 639–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ellis, David. 2025. Between Knowledge and Certainty: The Grammatical Duality in Wittgenstein’s View of Religious Belief. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fassio, Davide. 2014. Truth and the Aim of Belief. Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Glock, Hans-Johann. 1996. A Wittgenstein Dictionary. The Blackwell Philosopher Dictionaries. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Hyman, John. 2001. The Gospel According to Wittgenstein. In Wittgenstein and Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Mark Addis and Robert L. Arrington. London: Routledge, pp. 1–11. [Google Scholar]
- Law, Stephen. 2017. Wittgensteinian Accounts of Religious Belief: Noncognitivist, Juicer, and Atheist-Minus. European Journal of Philosophy 25: 1186–1207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malcolm, Norman. 1993. Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View? New York: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mulhall, Stephen. 2011. Wittgenstein on Religious Belief. In The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nielsen, Kai. 1967. Wittgensteinian Fideism. Philosophy 42: 191–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pichler, Alois. 2025. ‘For If There Is No Resurrection of the Dead, Then Christ Has Not Been Raised Either’: Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Status of Christian Belief Statements. Religions 16: 306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pichler, Alois, and Sebastian Sunday Grève. 2025. Cognitivism about Religious Belief in Later Wittgenstein. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 97: 61–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Price, Henry Habberley. 1965. Belief ‘In’ and Belief ‘That’. Religious Studies 1: 5–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Richter, Duncan. 2001. Missing the Entire Point: Wittgenstein and Religion. Religious Studies 37: 161–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. 2023. Wittgenstein on Religious Belief, 1st ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schröder, Sascha. 2007. The Tightrope Walker. Ratio 20: 442–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by Charles Kay Ogden. London: Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1966. Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief. Edited by Cyril Barrett. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1998. Culture and Value. Revised edition. Edited by Georg Henrik von Wright. Translated by Peter Winch. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009. Philosophical Investigations, 4th ed. Edited by Peter Michael Stephan Hacker and Joachim Schulte. Translated by Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe, Peter Michael Stephan Hacker, and Joachim Schulte. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Søderstrøm, S.O. Wittgenstein on the Grammar of Unshakeable Religious Beliefs. Religions 2025, 16, 857. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070857
Søderstrøm SO. Wittgenstein on the Grammar of Unshakeable Religious Beliefs. Religions. 2025; 16(7):857. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070857
Chicago/Turabian StyleSøderstrøm, Sindre Olaussen. 2025. "Wittgenstein on the Grammar of Unshakeable Religious Beliefs" Religions 16, no. 7: 857. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070857
APA StyleSøderstrøm, S. O. (2025). Wittgenstein on the Grammar of Unshakeable Religious Beliefs. Religions, 16(7), 857. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070857