Tattva: The Forgotten Concept in Nāgārjuna’s Ontology
Abstract
1. Tattva in Nāgārjuna’s Works
MK 15.6: Those who see self-existence (svabhāva), the self-existence of another entity (parabhāva), an entity (bhāva), or the absence of an entity (abhāva) do not see the truth/reality (tattva) in the Buddha’s teaching.
MK 18.9–11: [9] Not dependent upon another, pacified, free of being projected upon by conceptual projections (prapañcair aprapañcitam), free of mental discriminations (nirvikalpas), and without multiplicity of meanings (anānārtham)—this is the characteristic (lakṣaṇa) of what is real (tattvasya). [10] Whatever arises dependent upon another thing is not that thing, nor is it different from that thing. Thus, (what is real) is neither annihilated nor eternal. [11] Not one, not diverse, not annihilated, not eternal—this is the immortal teaching of the Buddhas, the guides of the world.
MK 22.8: Having sought the Buddha in this fivefold way (mentioned in verse 1) and finding that he does not exist through something else’s reality (tattva-anyatvena), how can he be thought to exist through dependency?
MK 24.8–9: [8] The Buddhas’ teaching of the doctrine rests upon two categories of truths (satye): truth based on worldly conventions (loka-saṃvṛti-satyam) and truth from the point of view of highest purpose (satya-parama-arthatos). [9] Those who do not discern the distinction of these two categories of truths do not discern the profound truth/reality (tattva) in the teachings of the Buddhas.
RV 98: The true reality (tattva-artha) of what was previously imagined by ignorance is now ascertained. When a (real) entity is not found, how can there be its absence (abhāva)?
SS 72: One who has trust, who seeks reality (tattva), who relies upon this teaching that is free of objective supports (i.e., there is no self-existent entity in reality to support any doctrine), and who considers this principle (of dependent-arising) by reasoning (yukti), overcomes the ideas of entities and the absence of entities and becomes tranquil.
YS 30: Seekers of reality (tattva) should first be told “Everything exists.” Later, when they have comprehended the nature of things (artha) and are free of clinging, then teach them emptiness (viviktatā, i.e., “clarity”).
YS 47–48: [47] That affirmation (of self-existence) is the cause of all views. Without it, afflictions do not arise. Thus, if this is thoroughly understood, views and afflictions completely disappear. [48] And how can this be thoroughly understood? By seeing dependent-arising. The Buddha, the best among knowers of reality (tattva-vida), said “What is born from conditions (dependently exists, but from the ultimate point of view it) is not born.”
- Nāgārjuna also speaks of “seeing reality” (tattva-darśana) and variants:
MK 26.10: One who is subject to root-ignorance (avidyā) forms the dispositions (saṃskārā) that are the basis of the cycle of rebirths. Thus, it is the one who is ignorant who performs an action (because of these dispositions and thus is reborn), not the one who knows by seeing reality.
RV 75: This doctrine—profound, leading to happiness, ungraspable, without an objective support—was proclaimed by the perfect Buddhas, the seers of reality (tattvadarśibhiḥ).
RV 105: From the ultimate point of view (parama-arthatas), this cosmos is beyond real (satya) and unreal (anṛta). And thus by seeing the reality (of things), it cannot be asserted that there is real existence (asti, “it is”) or total nonexistence (na-asti, “it is not”) (to the cosmos).
RV 110–11: Just as the birth and death of an elephant created by magic (māyā) are observed, even though by seeing reality there is neither a birth nor a death (since the elephant is illusory), so too the beginning and end of the illusory cosmos are observed, even though from the ultimate point of view there is neither a beginning nor an end (of an illusion).
SS 62: By seeing reality, we see that root-ignorance (avidyā), which arises from the four perverted errors, does not really exist. Thus, the dispositions that are dependent upon root-ignorance cannot arise. Thus, the remaining steps of the dependent-arising leading to a new rebirth also cannot arise.
YS 5: Those who do not see reality imagine “There is the cycle of rebirth, and there is liberation from it (nirvāṇa).” But those who see reality do not imagine that either the cycle or nirvāṇa is real.
- Nāgārjuna also uses “tattvatas” (“from the point of view of reality”), which functions as an adverb:
MK 17.26: If action by its nature has mental afflictions (kleśas), these afflictions are not real; and if the afflictions are not real, what (real) action could there be from the point of view of reality?
MK 23.2: But things that arise dependent upon errors about what is auspicious and what is inauspicious are not found existing through self-existence. Thus, from the point of view of reality there are no afflictions.2
RV 5: By means of insight (prajñā), one knows from the point of view reality.
RV 31–32: Just as the reflection of a face is seen by means of a mirror, even though from the point of view of reality this reflection nevertheless is not anything real, so too the sense of “I” arises dependent upon the bodily aggregates, even though from the point of view of reality it is in fact nothing but like the reflection of a face.
RV 38: In this way (i.e., by destroying karmic action and rebirth), the arising and destruction of causes and effects are destroyed. So too, from the point of view of reality, there is no existence (asti) or nonexistence (na-asti) of the entire cosmos (loka).
RV 47: A cause born before its effect or born simultaneously with its effect is not a real cause. In fact, any notion of production cannot be conceived from either a conventional point of view or the point of view of reality.
RV 64: From the point of view of reality, both the cosmos (loka) and nirvāṇa do not exist in either the future, the past, or the present. How can there really be any difference between them?
RV 65: Since there is no enduring, there is no arising nor ceasing from the point of view of reality. Thus, how can there really be something being born, enduring, and ceasing?
SS 1: Following worldly conventions (laukika-vyavahārāttu), the Buddhas speak of arising, duration, and cessation, being (sat) and non-being (asat), and inferior, middling, and superior. But the Buddhas do not do so from the point of view of reality (tattva).
SS 30: Since the three characteristics of all compound things (i.e., arising, enduring, and ceasing) are not real, from the point of view of reality there is nothing that is either conditioned or unconditioned.
SS 45: If visible form arises from the material elements, it does not arise out of itself but from something else that is empty of self-existence, and hence it does not exist from the point of view of reality. And since it then arises out of something empty of self-existence, it too is empty of self-existence, and so it is not real.
SS 70: Worldly doctrines are not abolished, but from the point of view of reality the Buddha never taught a doctrine.
YS 44: Those who affirm that entities are established from the point of view of reality are overtaken by mistakes about permanence and so forth.
2. The Meaning of Tattva
3. Contemporary Discussions
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
Abbreviations
MK | Fundamental Verses of the Middle Way (Mūla-madhyamaka-kārikā) |
RV | Jewel Garland of Advice (Ratnāvalī) |
SS | Seventy Verses on Emptiness (Śūnyatā-saptati-kārikā) |
VV | Overturning the Objections (Vigrahavyāvartanī) |
YS | Sixty Verses on Argument (Yukti-ṣaṣțika-kārikā) |
1 | On the question of Nāgārjuna’s nihilism, see (Wood 1994; Burton 1999; Siderits and Garfield 2013; Siderits and Katsura 2013; Jones 2018, 2020). |
2 | Some commentators who ignore or downplay tattva take this verse to be Nāgārjuna’s opponent speaking (e.g., Siderits and Garfield 2013, p. 662). But even if this is the case, that does not change what Nāgārjuna meant by tattva. |
3 | The commentary on the MK ascribed to Nāgārjuna and Bhāviveka entitle chapter 13, not “Analysis of the Compounded (Saṃskṛta),” but “Analysis of Reality (tattva),” while Buddhāpalita calls the chapter “Analysis of Emptiness” (Siderits and Katsura 2013, p. 137). |
4 | Tattva is not mentioned in Overturning the Objections, which is more about epistemological matters than ontological ones. |
5 | That is, prapañca is our projection of the conceptual differentiations that we ourselves devise onto what is truly there (tattva), and then seeing phenomenal reality as a collection of distinct self-contained entities. To get a sense of this, think of a Gestalt figure such as the faces/goblet: the black and white colors are reality as it truly is (tattva), but we impose structure on them, thereby creating illusory faces or a goblet and treat them as distinct objects. The faces or goblet do not really exist, but the colored material does. |
6 | Nāgārjuna mentions that tattva is free of discriminations (nirvikalpa) in MK 18.9. He mentions meditative development (MK 24.26, 26.11) and meditative states (RV 95), but he does not discuss meditation or insight-experiences. This does not mean he did not consider them essential for liberation, but only that they are not the topic of interest in these philosophical discussions about the nature of phenomena in these texts. |
7 | One can claim that “tathatā” (“thus-ness”) provides a similar foundation in Prajñāpāramitā thought as tattva in Nāgārjuna’s thought. |
8 | The concepts “emptiness,” “nirvāṇa,” and “dependent-arising” can be said to be empty of self-existence. Emptiness is itself empty (VV 59)—the term is merely another construct and thus empty of self-existence (MK 22.11, 24.18; VV 24). These three terms differ from other ontological terms only in that there is not even a conventional object as its referent: “tables” and “chairs” are empty mental objects, but they are projected onto tattva and thus differ from it in that way. Tattva is a mental object like these three concepts. But since what is denoted by these terms are not entities of any type, it is only the concepts themselves that can be described as empty. |
9 | The closest Nāgārjuna comes to speaking of the that-ness of an individual object is MK 22.8, where he denies the Buddha has reality through the tattva of something else (tattva-anyatvena). But this would be a case of denying individual reality to an object i.e., denying the self-existence of an object. |
10 | Both our conceptions and what is conceptualized are dependently arisen. The concepts arise in the context of other concepts, and what is conceptualized in the world arises from other elements in the world but does not depend on how we conceptualize it. A mountain does not depend on whatever concepts we create, but the category “mountain” does. |
11 | What Tola and Dragonetti (1995) say about emptiness may more properly be said of tattva e.g., emptiness as denoting “true reality” (p. xviii). |
12 | “Darśana” comes from the same root as “dṛṣṭi” (“view”). However, dṛṣṭi is not about the “ultimate point of view” but only about having a position requiring self-existent realities—it is a term of art for claims of a svabhāva metaphysics, not every type of “view” in the everyday sense (see Jones 2015, pp. 146–49). When he speaks of directly seeing reality as it really is (tattva-darśana), he does not connect this to a view. In short, accepting tattva is not to assert a view in his technical sense, and Nāgārjuna advances no views about tattva. |
13 | Later Indian Mādhyamikas, such as Buddhāpalita, Bhāvaviveka, and Candrakīrti, also treated tattva as “reality” or “truth” (Ames 1982, 1986). But whether they treat it as a feature of bhāvas and dharmas rather than something independent from our discriminated entities is not clear. For example, Buddhāpalita equates tattva with the highest reality (paramārtha), but in quoting him, Ames (1986) adds “things” in brackets, so that the sentence reads “seeing [things] as they really are” rather than “tattvatas” meaning “seeing reality” (p. 335). He treats “tattvatas” as that throughout his discussion of Buddhāpalita. Candrakīrti, in his discussion of MK 18.9 (Prasannapadā 372–73), connects tattva to bhāvas once but not the other four times that the word is mentioned. |
14 | |
15 | Affirming tattva beyond the negation of the reality of the nominal phenomenal realities puts Nagarjuna in line with mystics who employ the via negativa but affirm a reality beyond the negatives (see Jones 2024, pp. 383–84). |
References
- Ames, William L. 1982. The Notion of Svābhava in the Thought of Candrakīrti. Journal of Indian Philosophy 10: 161–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ames, William L. 1986. Buddhāpalita’s Exposition of the Mādhyamaka. Journal of Indian Philosophy 14: 313–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Burton, David F. 1999. Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nāgārjuna’s Philosophy. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Burton, David F. 2013. Emptiness in Mahāyāna Buddhism: Interpretations and Comparisons. In A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. Edited by Steven M. Emmanuel. New York: John Wiley and Sons, pp. 151–63. [Google Scholar]
- Ferraro, Giuseppe. 2013. Outlines of a Pedagogical Interpretation of Nāgārjuna’s Two Truths Doctrine. Journal of Indian Philosophy 41: 563–90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ferraro, Giuseppe. 2014. Grasping Snakes and Touching Elephants: A Rejoinder to Garfield and Siderits. Journal of Indian Philosophy 42: 452–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ferraro, Giuseppe. 2017. Realistic-Antimetaphysical Reading Vs Any Nihilistic Interpretation of Madhyamaka. Journal of Indian Philosophy 45: 73–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Garfield, Jay L. 2014. Madhyamaka is not Nihilism. In Nothingness in Asian Philosophy. Edited by Jeeloo Lis and Douglas L. Berger. New York: Routledge, pp. 44–54. [Google Scholar]
- Garfield, Jay L., and Graham Priest. 2023. Madhyamaka, Ultimate Reality, and Ineffability. In Reasons and Empty Persons: Mind, Metaphysics, and Morality: Essays in Honor of Mark Siderits. Edited by Christian Coseru. New York: Springer, pp. 247–58. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, Richard H., trans. 2015. Nāgārjuna: Buddhism’s Most Important Philosopher, Rev. and expanded ed. New York: Jackson Square Books/Createspace. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, Richard H. 2018. Dialetheism, Paradox, and Nāgārjuna’s Way of Thinking. Comparative Philosophy 9: 41–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jones, Richard H. 2020. On What is Real in Nāgārjuna’s ‘Middle Way. Comparative Philosophy 11: 3–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jones, Richard H. 2024. A History of Mysticism. Albany: SUNY Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kalupahana, David J. 1991. The Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna: The Philosophy of the Middle Way. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. First published 1975. [Google Scholar]
- King, Richard. 1989. Śūnyatā and Ajāti: Absolutism and the of Nāgārjuna and Gaudapada. Journal of Indian Philosophy 17: 385–405. [Google Scholar]
- Lindtner, Christian. 1982. Nagarjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nāgārjuna. Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag. [Google Scholar]
- McNamara, Daniel. 2024. The Two Truths Are Not Enough. Unpublished Conference Paper: Madhyamaka in South Asia and Beyond. Available online: https://www.academia.edu/123650397/_The_Two_Truths_Are_Not_Enough_Vienna_Madhyamaka_conference_August (accessed on 15 March 2025).
- Murti, Tirupattur Ramaseshayyer Venkatachala. 1960. The Central Philosophy of Buddhism: A Study of the Madhyamika System, 2nd ed. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Narain, Harsh. 1997. The Madhyamika Mind. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Ruegg, David Seyfort. 1981. The Literature of the Madhyamaka School of Philosophy in India. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz. [Google Scholar]
- Shulman, Eviatar. 2007. Creative Ignorance: Nāgārjuna on the Ontological Significance of Consciousness. Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 30: 139–73. [Google Scholar]
- Siderits, Mark, and Jay Garfield. 2013. Defending the Semantic Interpretation: A Reply to Ferraro. Journal of Indian Philosophy 41: 655–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Siderits, Mark, and Shoryu Katsura. 2013. Nāgārjuna’s Middle Way: Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. Somerville: Wisdom Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Tola, Fernando, and Carmen Dragonetti. 1995. On Voidness: A Study on Buddhist Nihilism. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- Westerhoff, Jan, trans. 2010. Nāgārjuna’s Vigrahavyāvartanī: The Dispeller of Disputes. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Westerhoff, Jan. 2016. On the Nihilist Interpretation of Madhyamaka. Journal of Indian Philosophy 44: 337–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Westerhoff, Jan. 2017. Nāgārjuna on Emptiness: A Comprehensive Critique of Foundationalism. In The Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy. Edited by Jonardon Ganeri. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 93–109. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Thomas E. 1994. Nagarjunian Disputations: A Philosophical Journey Through an Indian Looking-Glass. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Jones, R.H. Tattva: The Forgotten Concept in Nāgārjuna’s Ontology. Religions 2025, 16, 830. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070830
Jones RH. Tattva: The Forgotten Concept in Nāgārjuna’s Ontology. Religions. 2025; 16(7):830. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070830
Chicago/Turabian StyleJones, Richard H. 2025. "Tattva: The Forgotten Concept in Nāgārjuna’s Ontology" Religions 16, no. 7: 830. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070830
APA StyleJones, R. H. (2025). Tattva: The Forgotten Concept in Nāgārjuna’s Ontology. Religions, 16(7), 830. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070830