Can Madhyamaka Support Final Causation? ‘Groundless Teleology’ in Mahāyāna Buddhism, C.S. Peirce, and Chaos Theory
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Madhyamaka: Existential Nihilism or Pragmatic Realism?
The point is rather straightforward: Since everything is co-dependently originated—and thus all conventional ‘truth’ equally empty of intrinsic nature—then the Four Noble Truths are also ultimately ‘empty’ (qua nonexistent or merely conventional). If true, a dreaded nihilistic domino effect ensues that finally obliterates the distinction between virtuous action and its ignoble counterpart. When pushed to its logical terminus, spiritual practice does not have any karmic efficacy or soteriological promise, there can be no Buddhas, and the dharma is meaningless—quite the disaster for a Buddhist!If all this is empty—neither arising nor ceasing—it follows for you that the Four Noble Truths do not exist. Due to the non-existence of the Four Noble Truths, knowledge, abandonment, cultivation and realization would be impossible…[Hence] you deny the real existence of the fruits of karma and [the distinction between] good and bad actions, and all conventional practices.
[The] meaning of the term ‘dependent origination’ is just the meaning of the term ‘emptiness’. However, the meaning of the term ‘emptiness’ is not the meaning of the term ‘non-existence.’ Having mistakenly superimposed the meaning of ‘emptiness’ on the meaning of the term ‘non-existence’ you criticize us. Therefore, you do not understand the meaning of the term ‘emptiness.’
Indeed, it is to say the opposite. [For] existence itself must be reconceived. What is said to be ‘like a dream, like an illusion’ is their existence in the mode in which they are ordinarily perceived/conceived—as inherently existent. Inherent existence simply is an incoherent notion. The only sense that ‘existence’ can be given is a conventional, relative sense. And in demonstrating that phenomena have exactly that kind of existence and that dependent arising has exactly that kind of existence, we recover the existence of phenomenal reality in the context of emptiness.(1995, p. 177)
3. Causal Relata and Time in Madhyamaka
it is our cognitive act of cutting up the world of phenomena in the first place which creates the particular assembly of objects that constitutes a causal field, which then in turn gives rise to the notions of cause and effect. This entails that the causal field, cause and effect are empty of svabhāva … If the objects in our everyday world owe their existence to a partly habitual, partly deliberate process of cutting up the complex flow of phenomena into cognitively manageable bits, the causal relations linking them cannot exist independently of us, since their relata do not do so either.(2009, pp. 98–99)
Arnold leverages these verses to stress that the conceptual individuation of temporal events in Madhyamaka necessarily refers to general expectations apropos their futural significance:even the restriction of cause and effect to a single causal continuum cannot be considered real, because [the restriction] is conceptual (kālpanika) insofar as the effect has not arisen; given the reference (apekṣā) to the state of future phenomena, the conventional designation of things like “effects” is not actually true.
[No] causal relata can be individuated except relative to the expectations of an observer who in the first instance takes there to be some event of causation, his or her taking of which determines (inter alia) the scale at which anything will count as ‘cause’ or ‘effect.’ To say that reference to an ‘effect’ necessarily ‘depends on the state of future phenomena’ is thus to say that it depends on some perspective from which a complete, temporally extended event of causation could be in view—that it depends on there being something that is in the first instance taken, or conceived, as such an event, any reference to which remains, to that extent, “notional”…What Prajñākaramati suggests is that causal relations obtain, by temporal definition, between events—and ‘events’ do not just individuate themselves.(2021a, p. 20)
4. Peirce on Facts vs. Events
So far as the conception of cause has any validity … the cause and its effect are two facts. Now, Mill seems to have thoughtlessly or nominalistically assumed that a fact is the very objective history of the universe for a short time, in its objective state of existence in itself. But that is not what a fact is. A fact is an abstracted element of that. A fact is so much of the reality as is represented in a single proposition. If a proposition is true, that which it represents is a fact. If according to a true law of nature as major premise it syllogistically follows from the truth of one proposition that another is true, then that abstracted part of the reality which the former proposition represents is the cause of the corresponding element of reality represented by the latter proposition. Thus, the fact that a body is moving over a rough surface is the cause of its coming to rest. It is absurd to say that its color is any part of the cause or of the effect. The color is a part of the reality; but it does not belong to those parts of the reality which constitute the two facts in question.
5. Peirce’s Pragmatic Account of Final Causation
We must understand by final causation that mode of bringing facts about according to which a general description of result is made to come about, quite irrespective of any compulsion for it to come about in this or that particular way; although the means be adapted to the end. The general result may be brought about at one time in one way, and at another time in another way. Final causation does not determine in what particular way it is to be brought about, but only that the result shall have a certain general character.
6. Strange Attractors and Groundless Teleology
Take, for example, the phenomenon of the diffusion of gases. Force has very little to do with it, the molecules not being appreciably under the influence of forces. The result is due to the statistics of the equal masses, the positions, and the motions of the molecules, and to a slight degree only upon force, and that only insofar as there is a force, almost regardless of its character, except that it becomes sensible only at small distances. These features of a gas, that it is composed of equal molecules distributed according to a statistical law, and with velocities also distributed according to a statistical law, is an intellectual character. Accordingly, the phenomenon of diffusion is a tendency toward an end; it works one way, and not the opposite way, and if hindered, within certain limits, it will, when freed, recommence in such way as it can. Not only is an end an intellectual idea, but every intellectual idea governing a phenomenon produces a tendency toward an end. It is very easy to see by a general survey of nature, that force is a subsidiary agency in nature.
7. Conclusion: Buddhist Teleology and Ethics in a Groundless World
Nor must any synechist say, ‘I am altogether myself, and not at all you.’ If you embrace synechism, you must abjure this metaphysics of wickedness. In the first place, your neighbors are, in a measure, yourself, and in far greater measure than, without deep studies in psychology, you would believe. Really, the selfhood you like to attribute to yourself is, for the most part, the vulgarest delusion of vanity.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For an overview of various classical Indian interpretations of Madhyamaka as nihilistic, see (Westerhoff 2016); for contemporary nihilistic readings, see, for example, (Wood 1994; Burton 2001; Tola and Dragonetti 1995; Oetke 1991, 1996). |
2 | Cf., e.g., (Westerhoff 2016; Siderits 2007). As Siderits (107) notes, there is a trivial Cartesian sense in which the thesis that ‘nothing exists’ is self-contradictory, for knowledge of the premise already disproves its purported assertoric content: after all, the very thought that ‘nothing exists’—even if it is sensible to say only ‘apparent’ as such—is still presumably something that exists (viz., the apparent nature of things). However, even more pressingly, the idea that ‘nothing exists’ sounds an awful lot like an assertion about the ultimate nature of reality as such—which a standard reading of Madhyamaka would doubtlessly disavow. For the central tenet of Madhyamaka is the idea that ‘emptiness’ does not mean that ‘nothing exists’ simpliciter, but rather only that nothing exists with intrinsic nature (svabhāva)—viz., nothing exists in a self-subsistent manner independently of everything else. Indeed, the whole spiel of Madhyamaka is its characteristic rhetorical withdrawal from any judgments about the ultimate nature of reality, opting instead for a ‘middle path’ between the binary extremes of strict existence or non-existence: e.g., astīti śāśvatagrāho nāstīty ucchedadarśanam/tasmād astitvanāstitve nāśrīyeta vicakṣaṇaḥ (MMK: 15.10); evaṃ hetuphalotpādaṃ paśyaṃstatkṣayam eva ca/nāstitāmastitāṃ caiva naiti lokasya tattvataḥ (RV 1.38; see Hahn 1982, p.5). |
3 | Although some comparative work has been done on Peirce and Buddhism—cf., e.g., (Lettner 2021; D’Amato 2003)—these are mostly focused on Peirce’s semiotics, which is indeed relevant to the current subject, but is ultimately beyond the scope of this paper. For a reading of Peirce that compliments my own interpretation here, see, in particular, the conclusion of Arnold’s (2021b) article. I should also note, though, that in this paper I am only interested in the general problem of final causation, and, specifically, whether any robust or modified ‘realist’ version thereof can make sense in the context of Madhyamaka’s anti-foundationalism. The other elements of Peirce’s philosophy and theology can be effectively bracketed, as I am only using his naturalized understanding of teleology to achieve clairty on this matter. |
4 | These sorts of constructive pragmatic readings of Madhyamaka, among other things, challenge Rortyan, anti-realist interpretations (e.g., Brons 2020). Such ‘deconstructionist’ pragmatic approaches tend to over-emphasize, I think, the anti-essentialism of Madhyamaka, such that they inadvertently reify the notion of anti-essentialism itself in a way that the Madhyamaka would balk at; for this overlooks its principal significance as a methodological commitment, not a positive predicative claim about the ‘ultimate nature of reality.’ Although Siderits does not invoke Peirce as a more compatible pragmatic realist, he notes that “Rorty’s form of antirealism is precisely the sort from which I have been at pains to distance Madhyamaka” (2015, p. 216, fn. e). See also Harris (2010) for a relevant argument to the effect that Madhyamaka avoids the ethical tensions of Rorty’s anti-foundational liberalism because the Buddhist, precisely through his recognition of the co-dependent origination of impermanence and suffering, is “motivated to adopt only identities that are committed to eliminating the suffering of self and others. Therefore, his compassion for others is not in tension with a commitment to private self-creation” (p. 71). Harris’ analysis thus directly bears on the way the Madhyamaka might offer a constructive teleology that attenuates the potential nihilism of anti-foundationalist epistemologies. |
5 | yadi śūnyam idaṃ sarvam udayo nāsti na vyayaḥ/caturṇām āryasatyānām abhāvas te prasajyate//parijñā ca prahāṇaṃ ca bhāvanā sākṣikarma ca/caturṇām āryasatyānām abhāvān nopapadyate…śūnyatāṃ phalasadbhāvam adharmaṃ dharmam eva ca/sarvasaṃvyavahārāṃś ca laukikān pratibādhase (MMK 24:1-2, 6; cf. Siderits and Katsura: p. 171). |
6 | atra brūmaḥ śūnyatāyāṃ na tvaṃ vetsi prayojanam/śūnyatāṃ śūnyatārthaṃ ca tata evaṃ vihanyase (MMK 24: 7). |
7 | evaṃ pratītyasamutpādaśabdasya yo ’rthaḥ sa eva śūnyatā śabdasyārthaḥ na punarabhāvaśabdasya yo’rthaḥ sa śūnyatāśabdasyārthaḥ/abhāvaśabdārthaṃ ca śūnyatārtha mityadhyāropya bhavānasmānupālabhate/tasmācchūnyatāśabdārthamapi na jānāti (La Vallée Poussin 1903–1913, sec. 491, pp. 15–17, cf. Westerhoff 2016, pp. 339–40). |
8 | yaḥ pratītyasamutpādaḥ śūnyatāṃ tāṃ pracakṣmahe/sā prajñaptir upādāya pratipat saiva madhyamā//apratītya samutpanno dharmaḥ kaścin na vidyate/yasmāt tasmād aśūnyo hi dharmaḥ kaścin na vidyate (MMK: 24.19). |
9 | See Ferraro (2013) for a criticism of this ‘semantic reading’, and Siderits and Garfield (2013) for a respective defense. |
10 | yathā māyā yathā svapno gandharvanagaraṃ yathā/tathotpādas tathā sthānaṃ tathā bhaṅga udāhṛtam (MMK 7: 34). |
11 | Huntington, for instance, draws attention to the affinity between James’ conception of truth and Madhyamaka: “His pragmatic definition is to a very great extent compatible with the Madhyamika’s analysis of truth as a function of what can be put into practice—what can be embodied in the thoughts, words, and actions that go to make up a form of life” (Huntington 1989, p. 44). Indeed, even though Huntington (2007) and Garfield (2008) disagree about the ultimate place of reason in Madhyamaka, they both concur that the kind of truth the Madhyamaka dialectic presupposes is constitutively practical. (I would even venture to suggest that the differences between the views of Huntington and Garfield apropos Madhyamaka are, respectively, analogous to the rift between James and Peirce over the ultimate place of reason itself in pragmatic philosophy). |
12 | Cf. Siderits (2007, p. 182) and Garfield (1995, p. 91, fn. 7; 2002, p. 99). Arnold similarly argues that Nāgārjuna’s identification of ultimate and conventional reality—and thus that even the proposition of everything as ‘empty’ must itself perforce be ‘empty’—amounts to the ‘theoretical’ prioritization of practical reason over the reifications of theoretical reason itself; for it makes no sense to theoretically distinguish ‘ultimately real’ causes from the conventional framework of existents whereby they are conceptually determined as such: “‘Emptiness’ … is not itself what there really is; rather, it characterizes what exists—specifically, as existing dependently, which is the only way that anything can—and is therefore only intelligible relative to existents … I want to suggest that we thus understand Madhyamaka arguments as meant to support a ‘theoretical’ claim whose very content is that theoretical reason cannot coherently be thought to trump practical reason—and that this may be useful in understanding what it means for Madhyamaka to propose an analysis (of existents as empty) that itself is ‘empty’” (Arnold 2008, p. 144). |
13 | I surmise this is likely due, inter alia, to the Abhidharma tradition he inherits that assumes a strict distinction between particulars and universals (e.g., there is nothing like Kantian ‘schemata’ in Buddhist philosophy). Of course, things are further complicated by the fact that artha in Sanskrit can mean goal/object/referent/aim., etc. The Sanskrit language therefore already suggests that, insofar as intentionality itself presupposes some practical standpoint, the mere existence of conceptual content implies that the distinction between ‘object’ and ‘objective’ is mostly a theoretical matter. |
14 | Famously for Kant, the attribution of causal efficacy to general ideas is afforded only in virtue of the aesthetic and teleological capacities of reflective judgment, which goes beyond a mere ‘determining’ form of judgment that subsumes empirical particulars under general forms of the understanding. Specifically, while the latter involves applying a general concept to a particular, the former involves moving from a particular to a general concept. Reflective judgment therefore involves the free play of the imagination and understanding to realize unknown universals. This is most evident in the experience of beauty, where reflective judgment bridges the gap between empirical ‘isness’ and normative ‘oughtness.’ |
15 | na cāsty arthaḥ kaścid āhetukaḥ kva cit … nāsty akāryaṃ ca kāraṇam (MMK: 4.2-3); also cf. pratītya kārakaḥ karma taṃ pratītya ca kārakam/karma pravartate nānyat paśyāmaḥ siddhikāraṇam; na cājanayamānasya hetutvam upapadyate/hetutvānupapattau ca phalaṃ kasya bhaviṣyati (MMK 8.12; 20.22). |
16 | In a pertinent series of essays, Hayes (1994), Taber (1998), Westerhoff (2009), and Arnold (2021a) debate about the apparent fallacies of equivocation (Hayes), or lack thereof (Taber, Arnold, Westerhoff) in Nāgārjuna’s argumentation in the MMK 1.3, which connects this conversation over causal dependence to the asymmetry of causation discussed further below. |
17 | This response would help defend Nāgārjuna against Hayes’s charge that the Buddhist authors do not distinguish between “saying that a thing exists at all and saying that it exists under a given description” (1994, p. 315). Westerhoff claims, accordingly, that “[t]he failure to distinguish between existential and notional dependence has resulted in considerable confusion in the contemporary commentarial literature, primarily in connection with the so-called principle of co-existing counterparts” (2008, pp. 28–29, fn. 40). Taber originally stated this principle with respect to a potential fallacy committed by Nāgārjuna, namely, “that a thing cannot be a certain type unless its counterpart exists simultaneously with it” (1998, p. 216). While such a definition accords perfectly well with, say, a notional form of dependence (‘North America’ mutually depends upon ‘South America’) in the case of existential dependence, this would entail a symmetry of cause and effect in “blatant contradiction of common sense” (ibid., 238). |
18 | Indeed, this might be Nāgārjuna’s whole point. As Arnold (2021a) maintains, Nāgārjuna may not conflate existential with notional dependence in his arguments about causation, but rather may present an argument precisely to the effect that the distinction between existential and notional dependence is practically unwarranted because the conventional determination of the particular relata in any efficient causal relation always already presupposes certain general concepts associated with the mental faculties (i.e., of either memory or expectation). |
19 | Cf. (Kalupahana 1991, p. 61; Westerhoff 2009, pp. 97–98). Note that early Buddhist texts do not distinguish between cause (hetu) and supporting conditions (pratyaya); the two terms are often used synonymously (cf. Ronkin 2005, p. 222). |
20 | Nāgārjuna explicates the mutual dependence of the causal field and the effect in MMK 20.24: “An effect is not made with a causal field, nor without a causal field. How can there even be a causal field of supporting conditions without an effect?” na sāmagrīkṛtaṃ phalaṃ nāsāmagrīkṛtaṃ phalam/asti pratyayasāmagrī kuta eva phalaṃ vinā? (MMK: 20.24b). |
21 | Cf. Devendrabuddhi’s commentary on the SP: “[Opponent:] A [causal] relation [is] situated in two [places]. [Reply:] Why? Since these two [places], i.e., cause and effect, do not occur together. For when the cause is present, there is no effect—and, at the time of that effect, there is no cause, as it doesn’t make sense for both cause and effect to exist at the same time. Further, because non-momentary things do not exist, there is no existence of cause and effect or a simultaneous existent. Even reference to the doctrine of non-momentariness does not apply in this case, since two real things that occur at the same time could not be found such that there would be a present relation between the two. Alternatively, if something is not situated in two [existents], how is it a relationship? Not at all. A relation distinguished by cognition would [only] be constructed by conceptualization”. dviṣṭhaḥ. kiṅ kāraṇam. tayoḥ kāryakāraṇayor asahabhāvataḥ. tathā hi yadā kāraṇaṃ tadā na kāryam, tatkāle vā na kāraṇam, tulyakālaṃ kāryakāraṇānupapatteḥ. akṣaṇikānām apy abhāvatvān na kāryakāraṇabhāvaḥ sahabhāvo vety akṣaṇikavādodāharaṇam apy atrāyu-ktam, yato na vastubhūtau sahabhāvinau vidyete yena dvayor vartamānaḥ sambandhaḥ syāt. adviṣṭhe ca bhāve sambandhatā katham. naiva. buddhyā vyākṛtya sambandho vikalpena nirmitaḥ syāt (SP[V]: 7; see Steinkellner 2022). |
22 | The last horn of the opening tetralemma of the MMK makes this point explicit: “Not from itself, not from another, not from both, nor without cause: Never in any way is there any existing thing that has arisen.” |
23 | In addition to Prajñākaramati, Bhāviveka also notes this in his commentary on MMK 1:3 in the Prajñāpradīpa (Pandeya 1988–1989, p. 26). |
24 | janyajanakaikatvaikasantatipratiniyamo ’py anutpanne kārye kālpanikatayā vastuto na saṅgacchate/na cānāgatāvasthitadharmāpekṣayā kāryādivyavahāro vāstavaḥ (BCAP 356, 12–14 in La Vallée Poussin 1901–1914, cf. Arnold 2021a, p. 20). |
25 | The implicit oppositional targets here are the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika realists that believe that the past, present, and future exist substantially, like the absolute time of Newtonian mechanics; or, in the Buddhist Sarvāstivādins context, simultaneously in the form of temporal dharmas that represent the phases of the causal process (saṃskṛtalakṣaṇa). |
26 | pratyutpanno ’nāgataś ca yady atītam apekṣya hi/pratyutpanno ’nāgataś ca kāle ’tīte bhaviṣyataḥ (MMK: 19.1). |
27 | pratyutpanno ’nāgataś ca na stas tatra punar yadi/pratyutpanno ’nāgataś ca syātāṃ katham apekṣya tam//anapekṣya punaḥ siddhir nātītaṃ vidyate tayoḥ/pratyutpanno ’nāgataś ca tasmāt kālo na vidyate (MMK: 19.2–3). |
28 | See my own forthcoming (2025) article on the role of apekṣā in Yogācāra and Śaiva idealism (Berger 2025). |
29 | |
30 | Note that, as with many topics in Peirce’s corpus, he does not address the problem of final causation in any one text or paper—Peirce notoriously never had the funding to compose a monograph systematically laying out his metaphysical system—but they are scattered, rather, throughout his articles and manuscripts. I must therefore bring together writings from somewhat different periods to explain his ideas on the subject and their relevance to Madhyamaka. |
31 | |
32 | In this sense, Thirds are akin to Kantian ‘schema’, which are temporal rules that apply to the imagination as it mediates between objective intuitions and pure concepts of the understanding. They are concept-like, but not fully determinate—viz., something between intuitions and concepts, and thus undermine the strict distinction between the intuitive and discursive cognition upon which Kant had built his system. Peirce accordingly insists that “[Kant’s] doctrine of the schemata can only have been an afterthought, an addition to his system after it was substantially complete. For if the schemata had been considered early enough, they would have overgrown his whole work” (Peirce 1931/1968, CP 1.35). |
33 | Peirce attributes the erroneous conflation of fact and event to Mill specifically: “Mill’s singularity is that he speaks of the cause of a singular event. Everybody else speaks of the cause of a ‘fact’, which is an element of the event. But, with Mill, it is the event in its entirety which is caused. The consequence is that Mill is obliged to define the cause as the totality of all the circumstances attending the event…He thus deprives the word of all utility. As everybody else but Mill and his school more or less clearly understands the word, it is a highly useful one. That which is caused, the causatum, is, not the entire event, but such abstracted element of an event as is expressible in a proposition, or what we call a ‘fact’. The cause is another ‘fact’” (Peirce 1998, EP II: 315, 1904). |
34 | For instance, Boler writes that “Peirce is so worried lest we admit of knowing anything except in terms of events of experience and so happy with his analysis of real potency, that he talks his way into a metaphysical bind where he can no longer distinguish what is not an event from what is not actual … [Hence, Peirce] force[s] into the future what is quite comfortable in the present” (Boler 1964, p. 392). See Rosenthal (1968) for a defense of Peirce against this charge. |
35 | Peirce’s pragmatic maxim states, accordingly, that the conceptualization of an object coextends with one’s implicate conception of the object’s practical effects: “Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object” (Peirce 1931/1968, CP 5.402, 1878). Misak (Misak 2013, pp. 57–60) emphasizes that James and Peirce primarily diverged on the nature of the pragmatic maxim—for while James construed it as a theory of truth, Peirce viewed it as a theory of meaning. Although James would often deny this charge (while also acknowledging the ‘slipshod’ language of some of his essays on pragmatic truth), his interpretation of pragmatism was often taken to entail a potential epistemologization of ‘truth’ in a manner Peirce and other philosophers at the time found highly problematic—if not downright silly (cf. especially Russell 1992). It was for this reason that Peirce sought to distance his own theory from James. As Misak (60) notes, the “difference between the ‘truth’ as a product of the individual as opposed to truth as a product of the community over time is at the heart of the dispute between James and Peirce”. |
36 | In Peirce’s words, “an efficient cause, detached from a final cause in the form of law, would not even possess efficiency … final causation without efficient causation is helpless: mere calling for parts is what a Hotspur, or any man, may do; but they will not come without efficient causation. Efficient causation without final causation, however, is worse than helpless, by far; it is mere chaos; and chaos is not even so much as chaos, without final causation: it is blank nothing” (Peirce 1998, EP II: 121–124). |
37 | Peirce writes that “every purpose, although it relates to action upon an individual subject is in itself general. In the inception of its first fulfillment, whether in reality or in imagination, it is broadly general and simple (Peirce 1967, MS 1343, 14–5). Helmut Pape adds that this entails “every purpose, desire, every law of nature and every habit has to be vague, that is, it never does specify all the properties of the objects described completely. It is also general insofar as no specific individual or finite set of individuals is sufficient to characterize a natural class completely” (Pape 1993, 583). |
38 | T.L Short gives a germane example: “a man whose purpose it is to become president might try to achieve that purpose in any of several different ways, and the sort of president he becomes, if he is successful, will be influenced by the route to the presidency that he took” (373). |
39 | Moreover, although Peirce speaks here specifically with respect to the telos of human personality, Hulswit rightly notes that this description is “applicable to the idea of teleology in general: learning from the developmental aspect of our own human purposes, we can inductively infer that all final causes in nature are, at least in principle, subject to evolution” (1996, p. 197). |
40 | This is evident in Peirce’s description of his own speculative cosmogony: “In the beginning,—infinitely remote,—there was a chaos of unpersonalized feeling, which being without connection or regularity would properly be without existence. This feeling, sporting here and there in pure arbitrariness, would have started the germ of a generalizing tendency. Its other sporting would be evanescent, but this would have a growing virtue. Thus, the tendency to habit would be started and from this with the other principles of evolution all the regularities of the universe would be evolved. At any time, however, an element of pure chance survives and will remain until the world becomes an absolutely perfect, rational, and symmetrical system, in which mind is at last crystallized in the infinitely distant future” (Peirce 1931/1968, CP 6.33). |
41 | The technical discussion of dynamical systems and attractors follows Smith (Smith 1998, pp. 2–8). |
42 | In mathematical terms, this typically involves the stipulation of a set of interlinked n differential equations in the form dxi/dt = Fi (x1, x2…xn) where i = 1, …, n. In most cases, Fi will signify functions of both the state variables xi and certain further parameters that represent certain constants whose quantities do not change but whose values influence the evolution of xi. |
43 | Image taken from Wolfram’s model: https://demonstrations.wolfram.com/PhaseSpaceOfASimplePendulum/ (accessed on 10 December 2024). |
44 | Image taken from https://demonstrations.wolfram.com/LorenzEquationsSensitiveDependenceOnInitialConditions/ (accessed on 10 December 2024). Note that the two-dimensional image does not accurately portray the three-dimensional attractor, whose chaotic trajectory never actually overlaps. |
45 | See https://www.dynamicmath.xyz/strange-attractors/ (accessed on 10 December 2024) for several examples. |
46 | For instance, the complexity theorist Stuart Kauffman has suggested that cell differentiation could be governed according to certain strange attractors (Kauffman 1969, 1971, 1993). |
47 | I am borrowing this wonderful image from Varela et al. (2017, p. 235). |
References
- Arnold, Dan. 2005. Buddhists, Brahmins, and Belief: Epistemology in South Asian Philosophy of Religion. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Arnold, Dan. 2008. Transcendental Arguments and Practical Reason in Indian Philosophy. Argumentation 22: 135–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arnold, Dan. 2021a. Location, Location, Location! Thoughts on the Significance of a Grammatical Point for Some Mādhyamika Arguments. In A Road Less Traveled. Felicitation Volume in Honor of John Taber. Edited by Vincent Eltschinger, Birgit Kellner, Ethan Mills and Isabelle Ratié. Wien: UNIVERSITÄT WIEN. [Google Scholar]
- Arnold, Dan. 2021b. Pragmatism as Transcendental Philosophy, Part 2: Peirce on God and Personality. American Journal of Theology & Philosophy 42: 3–71. [Google Scholar]
- Berger, Jesse R. A. 2025. On the Role of Apekṣā in Dharmakīrti’s Sambandhaparīkṣā. A Comparison of the Intentional Relation in Buddhist and Śaiva Idealism(s). The Journal of Buddhist Philosophy. forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
- Boler, John. 1964. Habits of Thought. In Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, 2nd ed. Moore and Robin. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brons, Robin. 2020. Rorty, Buddhism, and Ethics without Essence. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 56: 19–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Burton, David F. 2001. Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nāgārjuna’s Philosophy. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- D’Amato, Mario. 2003. The semiotics of signlessness: A Buddhist doctrine of signs. Semiotica 2003: 185–207. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ferraro, Giuseppe. 2013. A Criticism of M. Siderits and J. L. Garfield’s ‘Semantic Interpretation’ of Nāgārjuna’s Theory of Two Truths. Journal of Indian Philosophy 41: 195–219. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Forster, Paul. 2011. Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Garfield, Jay. 2002. Empty Words. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Garfield, Jay. 2023. Can’t Find the Time: Temporality in Madhyamaka. Philosophy East and West 73: 877–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Garfield, Jay L. 1995. The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Garfield, Jay L. 2008. Turning a Madhyamaka Trick: Reply to Huntington. Journal of Indian Philosophy 36: 507–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hahn, Michael. 1982. Nāgārjuna’s Ratnāvalī. Bonn: Indica et Tibetica Verla. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, Stephen. 2010. Antifoundationalism and the Commitment to Reducing Suffering in Rorty and Madhyamaka Buddhism. Contemporary Pragmatism 7: 71–89. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hayes, Richard P. 1994. Nāgārjuna’s Appeal. Journal of Indian Philosophy 22: 299–378. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Höffe, Otfried. 1994. Immanuel Kant. Translated by Marshall Farrier. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hulswit, Menno. 1996. Teleology: A Peircean Critique of Ernst Mayr’s Theory. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 32: 182–214. [Google Scholar]
- Hulswit, Menno. 1997. Peirce’s Teleological Approach to Natural Classes. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 33: 722–72. [Google Scholar]
- Hulswit, Menno. 1998. A Guess at the Riddle of Semeiotic Causation. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 34: 641–88. [Google Scholar]
- Hulswit, Menno. 2001a. Peirce on Causality and Causation. In The Commens Encyclopedia: The Digital Encyclopedia of Peirce Studies. New Edition. Pub. 120809-1715a. Edited by M. Bergman and J. Queiroz. Available online: http://www.commens.org/encyclopedia/article/hulswit-menno-peirce-causality-and-causation (accessed on 10 January 2025).
- Hulswit, Menno. 2001b. Semeiotic and the Cement of the Universe: A Peircean Process Approach to Causation. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 37: 339–63. [Google Scholar]
- Hulswit, Menno. 2002. From Cause to Causation: A Peircean Perspective. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Huntington, C. W., Jr. 1989. The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Indian Mādhyamika. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. [Google Scholar]
- Huntington, C. W., Jr. 2007. The nature of the Mādhyamika trick. Journal of Indian Philosophy 35: 103–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kalupahana, David. 1991. Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant). Edited by Paul Guyer. Translated by Paul Guyer, and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kauffman, Stuart. 1969. Homeostasis and differentiation in random genetic control networks. Nature 224: 177–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kauffman, Stuart. 1971. Differentiation of malignant to benign cells. Journal of Theoretical Biology 31: 429–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kauffman, Stuart. 1993. The Origins of Order. New York: Oxford Univ. Press. [Google Scholar]
- La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, ed. 1901–1914. Bodhicaryāvatārapañjikā: Prajñākaramati’s Commentary to the Bodhicaryāvatāra of Śāntideva. Bibliotheca Indica Series; Calcutta: Asiatic Society of Bengal. [Google Scholar]
- La Vallée Poussin, Louis de, ed. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās (Mādhyamikasūtras) de Nāgārjuna, avec la Prasannapadā Commentaire de Candrakīrti. Reprint. Osnabrück: Biblio Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Lettner, A.T. 2021. Peirce’s Semiotic Pragmaticism and Buddhist Soteriology: Steps Towards Modelling “Thought Forms” of Siglessness. In Pragmatism, Spirituality and Society. Edited by Ananta Kumar Giri. Singapore: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Misak, Cheryl. 2013. The American Pragmatists, 1st ed. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Odin, Steve. 1982. Process Metaphysics and Hua-Yen Buddhism: A Critical Study of Cumulative Penetration vs. Interpenetration. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oetke, Claus. 1991. Remarks on the interpretation of Nāgārjuna’s philosophy. Journal of Indian Philosophy 19: 315–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oetke, Claus. 1996. Nihilist and non-nihilist interpretation of Madhyamaka. Acta Orientalia 57: 57–104. [Google Scholar]
- Pandeya, Ragunatha. 1988–1989. Madhyamakaśāstram. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- Pape, Helmut. 1993. Final Causality in Peirce’s Semiotics and His Classification of the Sciences. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 29: 581–607. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, Charles S. 1931/1968. The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. [CP] Volumes I–VI, edited by Hartshorne and Weiss. Volumes VII–VIII, edited by Burks. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, Charles S. 1967. The Unpublished Manuscripts of Peirce in Richard S. Robin. In Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, Charles S. 1998. The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings. [EP] Volume I, 1867–61. Volume II, 1893–1913. Edited by Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1976. The New Elements of Mathematics. [NEM] 4 volumes in 5 books. Edited by Carolyn Eisele. The Hague: Mouton. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1992. Reasoning and the Logic of Things. [RLT] Edited by Kenneth Laine Ketner. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ronkin, Noa. 2005. Early Buddhist Metaphysics: The Making of a Philosophical Tradition. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenthal, Sandra B. 1968. The ’Would-Be’ Present of C. S. Peirce. Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society 4: 155–62. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, Bertrand. 1992. William James’s conception of truth. In William James: Pragmatism, in Focus. Edited by William James and Doris Olin. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Short, T. L. 1981. Peirce’s Concept of Final Causation. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 17: 369–82. [Google Scholar]
- Siderits, Mark. 2007. Buddhism as Philosophy: An Introduction. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co. [Google Scholar]
- Siderits, Mark, and Jay L. Garfield. 2013. Defending the Semantic Interpretation: A Reply to Ferraro. Journal of Indian Philosophy 41: 655–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smith, Peter. 1998. Explaining Chaos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Steinkellner, Ernst. 2022. Dharmakīrti’s Sambandhaparīkṣā and Devendrabuddhi’s Sambandhaparīkṣāvṛtti. Sanskrit Texts from the Tibetan Autonomous Region. Vienna: Austrian Academy of Science. [Google Scholar]
- Taber, John A. 1998. On Nāgārjuna’s So-Called Fallacies: A Comparative Approach. Indo-Iranian Journal 41: 213–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tola, Fernando, and Carmen Dragonetti. 1995. On Voidness. A study on Buddhist Nihilism. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- Varela, Francisco J., Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch. 2017. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge: The MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Henry. 2005. Rethinking the Validity and Significance of Final Causation: From the Aristotelian to the Peircean Teleology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41: 603–25. [Google Scholar]
- Westerhoff, Jan. 2009. Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction. New York: Oxford Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Westerhoff, Jan. 2016. On the Nihilist Interpretation of Madhyamaka. Journal of Indian Philosophy 44: 337–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Westerhoff, Jan. 2017. Nāgārjuna on Emptiness. A Comprehensive Critique of Foundationalism. In The Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy. Edited by Jonardon Ganeri. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 94–109. [Google Scholar]
- Westerhoff, Jan. 2021. Does Reality Have a Ground? Madhyamaka and Nonfoundationalism. In Philosophy’s Big Questions: Comparing Buddhist and Western Approaches. Edited by Steven M. Emmanuel. New York, Chichester and West Sussex: Columbia University Press, pp. 79–96. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Thomas E. 1994. Nāgārjunian Disputations. A Philosophical Journey Through an Indian Looking-Glass. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Berger, J.R.A. Can Madhyamaka Support Final Causation? ‘Groundless Teleology’ in Mahāyāna Buddhism, C.S. Peirce, and Chaos Theory. Religions 2025, 16, 144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020144
Berger JRA. Can Madhyamaka Support Final Causation? ‘Groundless Teleology’ in Mahāyāna Buddhism, C.S. Peirce, and Chaos Theory. Religions. 2025; 16(2):144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020144
Chicago/Turabian StyleBerger, Jesse R. A. 2025. "Can Madhyamaka Support Final Causation? ‘Groundless Teleology’ in Mahāyāna Buddhism, C.S. Peirce, and Chaos Theory" Religions 16, no. 2: 144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020144
APA StyleBerger, J. R. A. (2025). Can Madhyamaka Support Final Causation? ‘Groundless Teleology’ in Mahāyāna Buddhism, C.S. Peirce, and Chaos Theory. Religions, 16(2), 144. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020144