Next Article in Journal
Porous Secularity: Religious Modernity and the Vertical Religious Diversity in Cold War South Korea
Next Article in Special Issue
Freedom by Coercion: Augustine’s Limitation of Coercion by the State
Previous Article in Journal
Adab al-Qāḍi: Shared Juridical Virtues of Judaic and Islamic Leadership
Previous Article in Special Issue
The State, Religion, and Violence in Colonial and Postcolonial Malawi
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Aristotle Meets Augustine in Fourteenth-Century Liège: Religious Violence in the Chronicon of Jean Hocsem

Department of English, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ 08544, USA
Religions 2024, 15(8), 892; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080892
Submission received: 4 June 2024 / Revised: 17 July 2024 / Accepted: 22 July 2024 / Published: 24 July 2024
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Religions and Violence: Dialogue and Dialectic)

Abstract

:
As William Cavanaugh has remarked, the scholarly notion of religion “should often be surrounded by scare quotes. Its flexibility and occasional nebulousness make evaluating its role in conceiving of, effecting, and justifying violence even more difficult. At the same time, it sticks around and remains a vital category of contemporary analysis. What if getting behind the Wars of Religion—the period to which Cavanaugh traces the emergence of his “myth of religious violence”—could plant the seeds for a new paradigm in understanding the relationship between religion and violence? In this article, I analyze the Chronicon of Jean Hocsem, a fourteenth-century canon from Liège. Untranslated into English and rarely written about, Hocsem’s text offers an unexpectedly political perspective on this question. Combining insights from Augustine’s City of God as well as Aristotle’s Politics and basing his ideas on his own experience of nearly constant conflict, Hocsem develops the idea that class antagonisms and human frailty make violence—especially political violence—inevitable. He takes this approach within a polity ruled by a prince-bishop, though one he would not have thought of as “religious”. Hocsem’s solutions are thus avowedly political. His pessimism about such questions leads to an emphasis on mitigating violence through the institution of proper socio-political structures. This reading of Hocsem and his politicizing of the question of violence opens new possibilities for scholars, further calling into question any easy relationship between the modern categories of “religion” and violence.

1. Introduction

If scholars of religion can agree on one point, it is that “religion” is still a contested, even nebulous, term. It remains a concept that, as William Cavanaugh has put it, “should often be surrounded by scare quotes”.1 To make sense of “religion and violence” in any essential way is always to reduce one or the other. Escaping this trap requires some specific hermeneutic—sociological, evolutionary, genealogical, or otherwise.2 Moreover, in every case, such heuristics necessitate adopting a contemporary lens in making historical sense of the relationship between religion and violence.
In what follows, I test William Cavanaugh’s “myth of religious violence”. Put broadly, Cavanaugh contends that the modern scholarly and popular notion that religion is a unique or special source for violent behavior is incorrect.3 He traces this “myth” back to historiography on the European Wars of Religion, which are supposed to have been the first European outbreaks of truly “religious” violence on a grand scale. In carefully dissecting and exposing this historiographic genealogy, Cavanaugh critiques the efficacy of the scholarly notion of “religion” and suggests that scholars examine pre- or non-modern interactions between human spirituality and violence to develop a more holistic understanding.
With this in mind, rather than entering a discursive quagmire and investigating what kinds of violence “religion” does and does not authorize in an absolute sense, this article concerns a medieval jurist named Jean Hocsem, who is religious in modern eyes and utterly secular (that is to say, not a monastic) in those of his own time. In this way, I hope to get behind or undercut some of the assumptions that often come with evaluating the relationship between religion and violence. In this way, I show how Hocsem’s life and work reveal the soundness of Cavanaugh’s thesis and offer us a glimpse of Aristotelian and Augustinian traditions of political philosophy and theology that may advance a more holistic understanding of the relationship between religion and violence.
A canon of St. Lambert’s Cathedral in fourteenth century Liège, Jean Hocsem fell on the “secular,” which is to say non-monastic or mendicant, side of clerical life.4 He occupied positions of political importance and even includes some of his letters to popes, bishops, and the king of France in his Chronicon,5 a chronicle of Liégeois history, especially during his own lifetime. Put otherwise, he was both a secular priest and a major political player and observer. Through this lifetime of service, he developed a theory of political change and violence rooted in a pragmatical Augustinianism.6 For Hocsem—himself a man of faith—violence was inevitable, a product of fallen humanity. Authorities, “religious” and otherwise, exist to contain, funnel, and structurally inhibit the development of that violence. When these fail, faithful people can even rise up—indeed ineluctably will rise up—against the authorities, even religious ones with secular mandates, like the bishop of Liège. In other words, by examining his Chronicon, modern scholars have an opportunity to understand how a medieval cleric theorized the role of violence within his own tradition, including against ecclesiastical potentates.

2. Canonical Life and Times

The central point in understanding Hocsem’s political theory is the city to which he devoted much of his adult life—Liège. The city was founded on a myth of religious violence all its own. In 1612, for instance, John of Chapeaville wrote of the martyrdom of St. Lambert, who “spilled his blood for truth and justice”.7 Lambert was a bishop of Maastricht in the late seventh and early eighth centuries, who died as a result of a disagreement with political authorities as the Merovingian dynasty gave way to its Carolingian successor. Once the next bishop transferred Lambert’s relics to Liège, his name became nearly synonymous with the city, such that its cathedral—the one to which Hocsem was attached—would bear his name. Lambert’s uncle and predecessor in Maastricht, Theodard, similarly enjoyed the title of martyr, and each was commemorated annually for their faithful sacrifice.8 In later centuries, the people of the city also venerated Lambert’s successor, Hubert, as a lawgiver.9 Political and ecclesiastical matters were deeply intertwined in Liège, where, by Hocsem’s day, the prime worldly authority was also the bishop of the diocese and thus the successor of Hubert and the martyrs. The city predicated its very identity on political violence, specifically that which arose from the contending of ecclesiastical and lay forces. In itself, this laid the groundwork for future protest against the prince-bishops.
Hocsem’s Chronicon bears witness to nigh constant conflict among the bishop, the clergy, the notables of the city, other lords, and urban residents between 1247–1348. After studying law in Orleans from 1305–1308,10 Hocsem shows up at a meeting between the bishop and the duke of Brabant in 1315.11 Not long after, he would have to flee the city due to a conflict breaking out between the city’s notables and Adolphe de la Marck, the prince-bishop.12 Despite their return, Hocsem and the chapter would end up exiled from Liège again in 1325 when the city notables took umbrage at Bishop de la Marck.13 During this exile, Hocsem would visit Avignon and ingratiate himself with the papal court, earning him further trust and putting him in a position to draft a variety of letters to foreign dignitaries on behalf of the prince-bishop.14 Upon his return in 1330, Hocsem participated in further negotiations with the duke of Brabant, most likely in his capacity as a lawyer.15 In 1346, near the end of Hocsem’s life, Adolphe’s nephew and successor, Englebert, demanded the chapter’s removal from the city once again.16 Hocsem refused, angered by the two times he had already been forced to flee and, condemning the bishop and defending the chapter, lived just long enough to witness the arrival of the Black Death in 1348.17
Taken as a whole, Hocsem’s life traces the lineaments of existence in late medieval Liège. Conflict was a near constant and violence came with it, as Hocsem himself testifies in reporting the burning of Miremort, the killing of 120 people, and his own experience as a survivor.18 As we shall see below, Hocsem’s views on violence are deeply informed by the consistency of such displays of human cruelty. To his mind, cities and other polities were inevitably loci for violence. Practically, he taught law at the chapter school, advised the bishop, and wrote letters to various secular and ecclesiastical lords. In broader terms, however, he sought to imagine how the inevitability of such violence might be channeled or reduced. How, in other words, might others not have to face the same level of horror that he did?

3. Aristotle, Augustine, Liège

Among the first events Hocsem narrates are the violent outbursts caused by class upheaval in the mid thirteenth century. Chapter III of Book I, for instance, carries the subtitle: De variis dissentionibus et tumultibus qui initio episcopatus Henrici in civitate Leodiensi acciderunt (On the various dissensions and tumults that befell the city of Liège and began during the episcopate of Henry).19 At the center of these disturbances are the conflicting demands of the groups that make up the city. Hocsem calls them by slightly different names throughout his account of this turmoil; in broad terms, however, they match the three estates of medieval political theory.20 He develops these larger categories along specific lines, mentioning the canonicos (canons)21 as their own group (indeed the one to which he belonged). He also specifies that the populares (common people),22 insignes (aristocrats),23 dives (rich),24 burgenses (burghers),25 and scabini (aldermen)26 played distinct roles in the conflict, even if some overlap may exist between the classifications. There was, according to Hocsem, the hope that the rich and poor alike could share the city (in unam simul dives et pauper possint convivere civitatem).27 This wish, itself revealing of the tensions always apparent in Liège, inheres in one of the oldest slogans associated with urban protest there: Que le pauvre puisse demeurer en paix delez le riche (that the poor may dwell in peace alongside the rich).28 Even from the earliest part of this chronicle, Hocsem shows a clear emphasis on the genere et causis (kind and causes)29 of conflict in the principality. In every case, he comes back to the diverse and complicated class composition of the city—it seems, to his mind, to portend and even require constant adjudication of differences.
He reveals the inevitability of such conflict just as he apologizes to the reader for turning from history to political theory. Telling his readers to skip this section if they prefer the narration of historical events, Hocsem expresses his interest in understanding the causae of the conflict inter insignes et populum (between the aristocrats and the people).30 To accomplish this, he turns to Aristotle and the model polities adumbrated in his Politics. Accepting that government can be by the few, the many, or by one and may be aimed at the good of all or simply the ruler(s), Hocsem argues that democratia (democracy)31 is better than oligarcia (oligarchy)32 because, while the insignes plot against the populares and themselves, the people only plot against those above them in the social order (et sic orta ceditione frequenter, si vincant, ad tempus divicie principantur, donec nova ceditione vincantur).33 In a word, democracy means less violence.
Here, Hocsem reveals his assumptions about conflict. By its very nature, the city is doomed to struggle between its constituent groups. In this way, he betrays a species of Augustinian pessimism about worldly governance, a fact that should not be surprising given that he quotes Augustine’s City of God in the Chronicon.34 At the beginning of Book II, for example, he cites Aristotle,35 Boethius,36 and Ovid37 to argue for the enduring reign of fortune over the just and the unjust. In his eyes, equanimity in the face of consistent misfortune and strife is the fruit of virtue, the mark of a saintly existence. He adds Augustine to this chorus, citing liberally from De Civitate Dei’s Book V.38 In this passage, Augustine (and by extension Hocsem) argues that a Christian ruler is not called happy because of a long reign, an easy succession, or wealth but because of his hope and faith. Hocsem uses this aside to comment that, while he must continue to narrate deeds related to war, victory in conflict is an effect of fortune, not a question of true divine happiness (Et quia gesta et fortia facta principum bellica a fortuna plerumque procedunt, conscripta consideratione predicta non debent quoad vixerint publicari, juxta illud).39 Augustine, in other words, offers the canon an authority through whom to comment on the inevitability of human conflict and violence, even as he holds out hope for Christian magnanimity in times of trial.
For Hocsem, then, the fallibility of human beings as glimpsed through Augustine combines with their necessarily opposed class interests (an insight he gleans from Aristotle) to make the city a microcosmic vale of tears. Violence is baked into the very idea of inhabiting a common space; it is unavoidable, a product of original sin and the limits of human sociality. This is the ultimate causa of the internecine violence he bore witness to throughout his active, politically savvy life.

4. Religio Leodiensis

As noted above, the term “religious violence” would not have had meaning for Hocsem. He was one of the canonicos, not a professed monk and certainly not “religious” in a way that could be neatly separated from his role as a legal theorist, a diplomat, and a defender of the privileges of his particular social group. His living in Liège, however, allows us to glimpse a particular role (or non-role) for “religion” in his theory of violence. Liège was a city ruled by an ecclesiastical official who exerted both spiritual and secular authority over his subjects. Indeed, the beginning of his chronicle insistently mentions both the threat and reality of interdiction,40 a powerful and coercive weapon available to the prince-bishop, one unavailable to his lay-aristocratic equivalents. Hocsem’s own cathedral chapter, which sided with the guilds against the bishop in 1302–1303,41 was an avowedly Christian organization, one composed of priests who cared both for souls and for their own material privileges.42 In this context, all conflict was religious insofar as it almost always involved institutionally religious actors. And this is not even to mention that even those from outside the First Estate would have belonged to religious confraternities and parishes and found themselves opposing believers from within their own tradition. Each of these groups justified the soundness of their position in religious terms. All violence in medieval Liège was thus “religious” in some sense or another.
This ambivalent view of “religious violence” is nowhere clearer than in Hocsem’s introduction to the episcopate of Adolphe de la Marck, with whom he worked closely. Citing Augustine once more (this time in his praise of Josephus—again from the City of God), Hocsem tells the reader that he has esteem for the ancients and their mode of historical writing, drawing an implicit comparison between Bishop Adolphe and leaders of old. He underscores the point by declaring in re militari nullus compar ponteficum (in military matters, no one compared to the pontiff).43 According to Hocsem, Adolphe is like an ancient hero; he did not, as was customary in his own time, rely on others to do his fighting but instead faced down his enemies with bravery and mettle: non enim per duces belli suffectos, ut assolet, belligerare consuevit, sed quociens dimicandi necessitas incumbebat nunquam retrospiciens consertis manibus reportavit semper ab hoste triumphum (For he did not tend to wage war through military leaders, as is customary, but as often as the need to fight arose, he never looked back with his hands folded but always won back victory from the enemy).44 Here, the bishop—undeniably a religious leader according to any modern sensibility—is memorialized in the vein of a Caesar or an Alexander. His reign is a list of gesta (deeds),45 the standard way of summarizing the content of a chronicle in the Middle Ages—whether the subject was clerical or lay. His title may be episcopus (bishop) but what defines him is his role in the historical tapestry (ut latiorem ad texendum telam historie ordiamur).46
In this sense, Hocsem’s perspective on violence’s religious quality parallels his view of its regularity. Just as strife comes for rulers whether Christian or pagan, just or unjust, so violence results from all ideological configurations, whether “religious” in a modern scholarly sense or not. The canons of the city were not religious in their own terms, but they are by any definition that accords with contemporary usage. The guilds of the city, with whom the canons occasionally sided against the bishop, had patron saints but saw no conflict in revolting against their heavenly and earthly prince. It should not surprise us, then, that what mostly concerns Hocsem throughout the Chronicon are discord (discordia)47 and concord (concordia)48 in the prince-bishopric of Liège and their relationship to the gesta of particular leaders and other figures of repute. Where violence is a given, and where its character is natural rather than cultivated by particular forms of spiritual ideology, the question is how to contain and how to theorize and control it, above all else.

5. Hocsem and the Myth of Religious Violence

Hocsem’s views on internecine strife and the inevitability of violence accord with William Cavanaugh’s famous thesis on the myth of religious violence (Cavanaugh 2009). Predating the Wars of Religion, Hocsem seeks to determine the nature and causes of violence in specific situations understood with no reference to “religion” as scholars now use the term. He simply stands outside of the norms of that discourse. By taking this approach, Hocsem’s focus is on political questions, because, where violence is inevitable, the only thing to be done is to examine strategies for mitigation. For this reason, he follows Aristotle in advocating a mixed, “democratic” form of government for cities like Liège. In this way, Hocsem also proves himself a staunch Augustinian, providing a gloss on the fundamental position proffered by Augustine that “Christians ought to hate all war and desire peace but resign themselves to the fact that real peace cannot be achieved on earth”.49 He anticipates something like contemporary realism (or even liberalism) and asks scholars to better investigate how political theory can be a vital conversation partner in the questions that surround religion and violence. He seems to ask: which structures impede violence? Which structures encourage it? By doing so, he casts light on a more holistic approach of the sort preferred by Cavanaugh. Peace, he suggests, is always inter (between),50 a respite to be cultivated, a product of hope, rather than a consistent state to be expected, a baseline that simply exists when not impinged upon by especially violent forms of religion.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Notes

1
William Cavanaugh, The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 7.
2
For a brief and incisive introduction to the sociological paradigm, see (Juergensmeyer 2017, pp. 20–34). For the evolutionary approach, see (Alcorta and Sosis 2022). Cavanaugh, The Myth is a classic example of the genealogical vantage point. For an overview of various approaches, see (Arcamone 2016, pp. 12–42).
3
This is, of course, not to say that religious traditions cannot foster or exacerbate violence. Cavanaugh openly admits that they can. Such traditions should be studied for their role in cultivating violent behavior. Many of the early modern thinkers interested in religion and violence came to this connection because these concepts were so obivously linked in their time and place. Cavanaugh’s point, however, is that religion is not a special or even definable source of violence, especially not trans-historically. Indeed, it can and has been a peacemaking force. It represents a diverse set of perspectives (Cavanaugh suggests that the term itself has little meaning outside scholarly analysis, where even then it remains problematic, necessary only because no other concept is available. Religion writ large, for him, is no more pro-violence than terms like “way of life” or “being”). Taking this idea up, this article will not examine specific instances of historical or contemporary religious extremism (e.g., American Christian nationalism or Salafist Islam) but rather seeks to examine the conceptual-historical relationship between the concepts “religion” and “violence” through the example of Jean Hocsem.
4
The only biographical sketch of Hocsem available in English is extremely brief. See (Lützelschwab 2010, S. 933).
5
Hocsem’s Chronicon remains untranslated and is only available in the edition prepared by Godefroid Kurth: (Hocsem 1927). I will always cite this text as Chronique, though I may reference it independent of a particular citation by its Latin title, Chronicon. We know Hocsem to be responsible for another text, this one about canon law called Digitus florum utriusque iuris. This work has not been commented upon in English to my knowledge. An article, however, exists in French, exploring the text’s relationship to Hocsem as a canonist: (Feenstra 1963, pp. 486–520).
6
William E. Connolly’s ambiguous relationship to Augustine is of interest here. In William E. Connolly (1993, pp. xvii–xxiv), the author relates his desire to meet Augustine’s conception of the moral-political order with a post-Nietzschean rejoinder. Connolly himself admits some indebtedness to Augustine, though he expresses some reservation that his readers will believe him (Connolly, The Augustinian Imperative, xviii). As we shall see below, Hocsem’s Augustinian agonism takes for granted the vital pluralism (at least of class) that Connolly sees threatened by Augustine. Hocsem, then, meets Connolly with a rejoinder of his own, agreeing with him on the inevitability and usefulness of conflict in politics but in a way that sees Augustine’s theoretical influence (even if implicitly) in a more positive light.
7
Quoted in (Saucier 2014, p. 11).
8
9
10
11
12
See note 10.
13
14
See (Kurth 1927, pp. xviii–xxii) for a full list of the letters.
15
16
17
18
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, XXXIV, 357, ll. 16–20.
19
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 11, ll. 10-11. All translations from the Chronicon are mine.
20
For a helpful analysis of the three estates in a neighboring polity, see (Boffa 2004, pp. 113–20). While Brabant differed in being ruled by a duke, its close relationship to Liège, including in terms of economic prosperity and consistency of revolt, makes it a worthwhile point of comparison.
21
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 11, l. 14.
22
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 11, l. 14.
23
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 12, l. 1.
24
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 13, l. 9.
25
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 13, l. 14.
26
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 12, l. 3.
27
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 13, l. 9.
28
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III, 13, l. 9, n. 4. Kurth also gives an early fifteenth century Latin equivalent: Quia volo quad pauper in pace queat stare cum divite (Hocsem, Chronique, I, III, 13, l. 9, n. 4).
29
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, IV, 15, l. 7.
30
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, IV, 15, ll. 10–11.
31
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, IV, 19, l. 25.
32
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, IV, 19, l. 25.
33
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, IV, 20, ll. 4–6.
34
For example, at Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, ED, 140, l. 32
35
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, ED, 140, l. 6–7.
36
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, ED, 140, l. 11.
37
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, ED, 139, ll. 7–10.
38
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, ED, 140–141, ll. 32–24.
39
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, ED, 141, ll. 25–27.
40
See, for instance, Hocsem (1927), Chronique, I, III 12, l. 5.
41
Black (1996, p. 107). On the rebellion generally, see (Kurth 1907). While the Low Countries in this period were notorious for the ubiquity of rebellion and discontent among the urban population, the chapter’s justification of revolt against the prince-bishop remains an odd occurrence. Black, in fact, contends that Hocsem is the only northern European to engage in this way with these Aristo-republican ideals otherwise found only in the Italian humanists. While Black does not go into detail, we might see Hocsem’s interest in Boethius and fortuna as further parallels.
42
On secular canons, see the recent volume (Berg and Otto 2023).
43
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, I, 143, ll. 22–23.
44
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, I, 143-144, ll. 23–24.
45
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, I, 142, l. 8.
46
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, I, 144, ll. 5–6.
47
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, IV, 153, l. 7.
48
Hocsem (1927), Chronique, II, IV, 156, l. 2.
49
50
Hocsem, for example, speaks of pace inter domum de Awans et de Waroux mirabili modo inita, (peace between the house of Awans and Waroux, which began recently and in a miraculous way) (Hocsem 1927, Chronique, II, XXI, 246, l. 20-21). Here, his usage is not temporal, but his emphasis on the miraculous nature of the peace testifies to his pessimism about its endurance.

References

  1. Alcorta, Candace, and Richard Sosis. 2022. Evolutionary Perspectives and Religion and Violence. Cambridge: University of Cambridge Press. [Google Scholar]
  2. Arcamone, Dominic. 2016. Religion and Violence: A Dialectical Engagement through the Insights of Bernard Lonergan. Cambridge: James Clarke & Co., pp. 12–42. [Google Scholar]
  3. Berg, Sigrun Høgetveit, and Arnold Otto, eds. 2023. Secular Canons in Medieval Europe: Diversity under Common Canon Law. Berlin: De Gruyter. [Google Scholar]
  4. Black, Antony. 1996. The Commune in Political Theory in the Late Middle Ages. In Theorien kommunaler Ordnung in Europa. Edited by Peter Blickle and Elisabeth Müller-Luckner. München: R. Oldenbourg Verlag, pp. 99–112. [Google Scholar]
  5. Boffa, Mario. 2004. Warfare in Medieval Brabant, 1356–1406. Rochester: Boydell & Brewer. [Google Scholar]
  6. Cavanaugh, William. 2009. The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  7. Connolly, William E. 1993. The Augustinian Imperative: Reflections on the Politics of Morality. Newbury Park: Sage Publications. [Google Scholar]
  8. Feenstra, Robert. 1963. Flores Utriusque Iuris de Jean de Hocsem et Leur Edition au XVe Siecle. Tijdschrift voor Rechtsgeschiedenis 31: 486–520. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Gorry, Jonathan. 2011. Ploughshares into Swords? St. Augustine’s Ethics of Political Violence. Religion Compass 15: 753–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Hocsem, Jean. 1927. La Chronique de Jean de Hocsem. Edited by Godefroid Kurth. Bruxelles: Commission Royale d’Histoire. [Google Scholar]
  11. Juergensmeyer, Mark. 2017. Thinking Sociologically about Religion and Violence: The Case of ISIS. Sociology of Religion 79: 20–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Kurth, Godefroid. 1907. L’entrée du parti populaire au conseil communal de Liége en 1303. Liège: Herni Poncelet. [Google Scholar]
  13. Kurth, Godefroid. 1927. Introduction to La Chronique de Jean de Hocsem. Edited by Godefroid Kurth. Bruxelles: Commission Royale d’Histoire, pp. ix–ixxv. [Google Scholar]
  14. Lützelschwab, Ralf. 2010. “John of Hocsem” in the Dictionary of the Medieval Chronicle. Edited by Graeme Dumphy and Cristian Bratu. Leiden: Brill, vol. 2, s. 933. [Google Scholar]
  15. Saucier, Catherine. 2014. A Paradise of Priests: Singing the Civic and Episcopal Hagiography of Medieval Liège. Rochester: University of Rochester Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Padusniak, C. Aristotle Meets Augustine in Fourteenth-Century Liège: Religious Violence in the Chronicon of Jean Hocsem. Religions 2024, 15, 892. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080892

AMA Style

Padusniak C. Aristotle Meets Augustine in Fourteenth-Century Liège: Religious Violence in the Chronicon of Jean Hocsem. Religions. 2024; 15(8):892. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080892

Chicago/Turabian Style

Padusniak, Chase. 2024. "Aristotle Meets Augustine in Fourteenth-Century Liège: Religious Violence in the Chronicon of Jean Hocsem" Religions 15, no. 8: 892. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080892

APA Style

Padusniak, C. (2024). Aristotle Meets Augustine in Fourteenth-Century Liège: Religious Violence in the Chronicon of Jean Hocsem. Religions, 15(8), 892. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15080892

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop