Religious Dimensions of Confucius’ Teachings on Ren and Li in the Analects
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Li as Culture
I once spent all day thinking without taking food and all night thinking without going to bed, but I found that I gained nothing from it. It would have been better for me to have spent the time in learning.
2.1. Li 禮
2.2. Ren 仁
To return to the observance of the rites through overcoming the self constitutes benevolence [ke ji fu li wei ren克己復禮爲仁].
[P]rior to Confucius, Chinese tradition did not have a general, universal virtue under which all particular virtues could be subsumed. Confucius, in developing ren as this comprehensive virtue, established a ground that provided classical Chinese ethical theory with unity, consistency, and coherence.
2.3. Relationship between Ren and Li
3. Li as Cult
Jing 敬, the Spirit of Li
Characteristic of Confucius’ teaching is the use of the language and imagery of li as a medium within which to talk about the entire body of the mores, or more precisely, of the authentic tradition and reasonable conventions of society…. Confucius thus does two things here: he calls our attention to the entire body of tradition and convention, and he calls upon us to see all this by means of a metaphor, through the imagery of sacred ceremony, holy rite.
Rite brings out forcefully not only the harmony and beauty of social forms, the inherent and ultimate dignity of human intercourse; it brings out also the moral perfection implicit in achieving one’s ends by dealing with others as beings of equal dignity, as free coparticipants in li. Furthermore, to act by ceremony is to be completely open to the other; for ceremony is public, shared, transparent; to act otherwise is to be secret, obscure and devious, or merely tyrannically coercive. It is in this beautiful and dignified, shared and open participation with others who are ultimately like oneself that man realizes himself. Thus perfect community of men…becomes an inextricably part, the chief aspect, of Divine worship….
“Authoritative” entails the “authority” that a person comes to represent in community by becoming ren embodying in oneself the values and customs of one’s tradition through the observance of ritual propriety (li).
Tzu-yu asked about being filial. The Master said, ‘Nowadays for a man to be filial means no more than that he is able to provide his parents with food. Even hounds and horses are, in some way, provided with food. If a man shows no reverence, where is the difference?
4. Confucius: Humanistic or Religious?
4.1. Enchanted Worldview
The character li 禮 has the radical shi 示 as a component element, meaning, “show”, “sign”, “indicate”. Because these ritual displays were originally enacted in a religious context to make human intentions known to the spirits, shi as a constituent radical in a character is usually indicative of religious affairs. The “ritual vase” (li 豊) component of ritual action(li) further associates ritual with the sacred and sacrificial.
Confucius approved of the li of mourning and sacrifices largely because of his adoption of the Zhou tradition as an ethical guide to communal intercourse, not because of the specific associated religious beliefs about the existence of ghosts and spirits…. Notably, Confucius seems to have an “as if” attitude toward the existence of the dead as objects of sacrifice (Analects 3:12)….
The pragmatic teacher is constantly expounding what he considers to be truths about the correctness or incorrectness of modes of behavior in terms of the assumed ends of behavior. The ends themselves presuppose a certain vision of the world in which they are pursued.
The Master said, ‘If a man is able to govern a state by observing the rites and showing deference, what difficulties will he have in public life? If he is unable to govern a state by observing the rites and showing deference, what good are the rites to him?’
The Master said, ‘If there was a ruler who achieved order without taking any action, it was, perhaps, Shun. There was nothing for him to do but to hold himself in a respectful posture and to face due south.’.
A highly problematic aspect of the world “humanism” is, of course, its strong association with the whole trend of what has been called humanism in the post-Cartesian West. The notion of a radical breach and even antagonism between a human world centered on the human subject as the sole source of meaning and an indifferent, “valueless” or even hostile universe does not seem to be suggested anywhere in the Analects.
4.2. Heaven
The Master said, ‘I am thinking of giving up speech.’ Tzu-kung said, ‘If you did not speak, what would there be for us, your disciples, to transmit?’ The Master said, ‘What does Heaven ever say? Yet there are the four seasons going round and there are the hundred things coming into being. What does Heaven ever say?’.
The Master said, ‘There is no one who understands me.’ Tzu-kung said, ‘How is it that there is no one who understands you?’ The Master said, ‘I do not complain against Heaven, nor do I blame Man. In my studies, I start from below and get through to what is up above. If I am understood at all, it is, perhaps, by Heaven.’
…it is entirely possible to believe that the same Heaven which silently manifests itself in the course of the four seasons also knows Confucius and endows him with a historic mission. When one glances briefly ahead over the long history of Confucian thought, one finds that while the specifically “theistic” component of this view of Heaven often recedes, the rigid antithesis between Heaven as “order of nature” and Heaven as cosmic consciousness never does become firmly established.
5. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | In this essay, the romanization of Chinese characters follows the Pinyin system, even when quoting the works of other scholars. |
2 | Unless otherwise noted, all quotations from the Analects are from the Lau 1970 translation. |
3 | The time Confucius lived (551–479 B.C.E.) was known as the Spring and Autumn period, when the glory of the Western Zhou (周) Dynasty was declining, but still a fresh memory in the minds of the people. The Zhou Dynasty (11th–3th century B.C.E.), which lasted for over five hundred years following the Xia (厦) and Shang (商) Dynasties, was the longest dynasty in Chinese history. While interested in the cultures of the Three Dynasties, the Master drew primarily on the last, the Zhou, the one whose tradition was still available at the time. Indeed, he saw history down to the Zhou not as regress but as progress (Graham 1989, p. 12). Confucius was born in Qufu, a town in the state of Lu in central China. Although Lu was small and militarily inconsequential, it was known as the repository of the traditional ways of the early Zhou court (Peimin Ni 2002, pp. 4–5). |
4 | It is, however, not the case that Confucius did not recognize the importance of “thinking”. Even though Confucius emphasizes personal appropriation of the cultural tradition, he also says “If one learns from others but does not think, one will be bewildered” (Confucius 1979, 2.15). That is, the Master sees the importance of personalizing what is learned and making it appropriate and meaningful in one’s own unique circumstances. Anyhow, it remains true that for Confucius “learning” is to be given priority for the simple reason that without first “learning” something, one cannot make it one’s own. In the saying above, the Master goes on to say “If, on the other hand, one thinks but does not learn from others, one will be in peril”. The interplay between ‘learning’ and ‘thinking’ is a recurring theme in the Analects. |
5 | The significance of this expansive usage of the term by Confucius will be discussed later in the paper. |
6 | They further note that the difficulty in interpreting ren in the Analects is partly due to the fact that in the Analects the term “is at times used in its pre-Confucian “particularistic” sense, and at other times used as general virtue” (Hall and Ames 1987, p. 111). |
7 | Given the status of ren as the ideal virtue in Confucius’ philosophy, to translate it as such English words as “benevolence”, “magnanimity”, or “human-heartedness”, it seems to me runs the risk of reducing it to a virtue, which will fail to do justice to Confucius’ originality as a moral thinker. Whatever rendering we may adopt, I think we should make sure that ren is concerned with the essence of the human project of becoming truly human. |
8 | “Imagine a community in which the only way of getting married is for the partners to perform certain motions, such as exchanging rings, on a ceremonious occasion of a certain kind. Now, within this community, two people’s performing the appropriate motions on the appropriate occasion is both necessary and sufficient for their getting married” (Shun 1993, p. 467). |
9 | Shun admits that there are passages in the Analects where Confucius appears to take li as playing merely an instrumental role with regard to ren. For example, the Master asks, “What can a man do with the rites who is not benevolent?” (Confucius 1979, 3.3). Although the saying does not directly say that li is instrumental to ren, Shun observes that it may be taken to imply that a man’s not being ren is regarded by Confucius as a situation in which li does not perform its function. For the discussions on the textual support for the “instrumentalist” interpretation, see Shun (1993, pp. 463–65). |
10 | In contrast to Shun, Li regards “What can a man do with the rites who is not benevolent?” as implying that one could follow the rules of li without being ren. |
11 | Li acknowledges that his understanding of the relationship between ren and li is “a kind of instrumentalism broadly construed” (Li 2007, p. 323). |
12 | Confucius says “In the case of Yen Yuan, his heart for three months at a time does not go off course from noble (仁). As for the rest of them, they attain it only for a day or a month” (6.7. Graham’s translation). |
13 | Quoted in (Chan 2006, p. 236). Thus, Chan contends that while many scholars have explored the relationship between ren and li, the true understanding of li requires a good grasp of the concept of jing. |
14 | See Hall and Ames (1987, pp. 85–86). The authors observe that in Chinese society li, while its meaning is extended to include the various kinds of formal human conducts, “never lost the sense of sacredness”. |
15 | In his influential anthology, A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy, Wing-Tsit Chan famously attributed “humanism” to Confucius. Chan, in a section titled “The Humanism of Confucius” says “[T]he humanistic tendency had been in evidence long before his time, but it was Confucius who turned in into the strongest force in Chinese philosophy. He did not care to talk about spiritual beings or even about life after death” (Chan 1963, p. 15). |
16 | An anonymous reviewer suggested that I need to clarify my use of the term “humanism” and recommended referring to Tu Weiming’s studies for further insight. Another reviewer pointed out that while philosophers have been hesitant to consider Confucianism as a religion due to their focus on defining what religion means, scholars in religious studies—such as Joseph Adler, Robert Cummings Neville, Vivian-Lee Nyitray, Tu Weiming, and others—observe Confucians acting religiously and focus on practical discussions of lived behavior and expressed ideals, avoiding abstract definitional issues. I would like to thank all of the reviewers for their invaluable assistance in revising this essay. |
17 | Some theorists argue that “magic” and “religion” are to be understood as antithetical. Religion developed in opposition to magic. |
18 | The “disenchantment of the world” (Entzauberung der Welt)—literally meaning “de-magi-fication”—is one of the central terms in Max Weber’s philosophy of history. The term refers to a process through which people no longer explain the world by reference to magical forces, but rely instead on science and rational forms of thinking. In Weber’s own words, “[today] there are no mysterious incalculable forces that come into play, but rather...one can, in principle, master all things by calculation. This means that the world is disenchanted” (Weber 1958, p. 141). |
19 | After studying tian in the Analects, Robert Louden concludes, “Confucius’ moral outlook is religious (though again, not theistic) in the straightforward sense that he holds that moral standards are dependent on something outside of us, something bigger than human nature—or culture—that is much more than a human or even a rational construction” (Louden 2002, p. 81). |
20 | This is Sandra Schneiders’ definition of spirituality (Schneiders 2005, p. 16). |
References
- Ames, Roger T., and Henry Rosemont. 1999. Introduction. In The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation. New York: Ballantine Books, pp. 1–70. [Google Scholar]
- Chan, Sin Yee. 2006. The Confucian Notion of Jing (Respect). Philosophy East and West 56: 229–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chan, Wing-Tsit. 1963. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ching, Julia. 1993. Chinese Religions. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Ching, Julia. 2003. What Is Confucian Spirituality? In Confucian Spirituality. Edited by Weiming Tu and Mary Evelyn Tucker. New York: Crossroad Publishing Company, vol. 1, pp. 81–95. [Google Scholar]
- Confucius. 1979. The Analects (Lun Yü). Translated by Din Cheuk Lau. New York: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Confucius. 1999. The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation. Translated by Roger T. Ames, and Henry Rosemont. Classics of Ancient China. New York: Ballantine Books. [Google Scholar]
- Cua, Antonio S. 2003. The Ethical and the Religious Dimensions of Li. In Confucian Spirituality. Edited by Tu Weiming and Mary Evelyn Tucker. New York: Crossroad Publishing Company, pp. 252–86. [Google Scholar]
- Eno, Robert. 1990. The Confucian Creation of Heaven: Philosophy and the Defense of Ritual Mastery. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fingarette, Herbert. 1972. Confucius—The Secular as Sacred. New York: Harper & Row. [Google Scholar]
- Graham, Angus Charles. 1989. Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China. La Salle: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Hall, David L., and Roger T. Ames. 1987. Thinking through Confucius Suny Series in Systematic Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ivanhoe, Philip J. 2007. Heaven as a Source for Ethnical Warrant in Early Confucianism. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 6: 211–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lau, Din Cheuk. 1979. Introduction. In The Analects (Lun Yü). New York: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Chenyang. 2007. Li as Cultural Grammar: On the Relation between Li and Ren in Confucius’ ‘Analects’. Philosophy East and West 57: 311–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Louden, Robert B. 2002. “What Does Heaven Say?”: Christian Wolff and Western Interpretations of Confucian Ethics. In Confucius and the Analects: New Essays. Edited by Bryan W. Van Norden. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 73–93. [Google Scholar]
- Ni, Peimin. 2002. On Confucius. Wadsworth Philosophers Series; Belmont: Wadsworth. [Google Scholar]
- Schneiders, Sandra M. 2005. Approaches to the Study of Christian Spirituality. In The Blackwell Companion to Christian Spirituality. Edited by Arthur Holder. Oxford and Malden: Blackwell Pub, pp. 15–33. [Google Scholar]
- Schwartz, Benjamin I. 1985. The World of Thought in Ancient China. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shun, Kwong-Loi. 1993. Jen and Li in the ‘Analects’. Philosophy East and West 43: 457–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Waley, Arthur. 1989. Introduction. In The Analects of Confucius. New York: Vintage Books, pp. 13–79. [Google Scholar]
- Weber, Max. 1958. Science as a Vocation. In From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. Edited by Hans Heinrich Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 129–56. [Google Scholar]
- Weiming, Tu. 2024. Spiritual Humanism: Self, Community, Earth, and Heaven. Diogenes 65: 145–61. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Lee, J. Religious Dimensions of Confucius’ Teachings on Ren and Li in the Analects. Religions 2024, 15, 668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060668
Lee J. Religious Dimensions of Confucius’ Teachings on Ren and Li in the Analects. Religions. 2024; 15(6):668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060668
Chicago/Turabian StyleLee, Jongtae. 2024. "Religious Dimensions of Confucius’ Teachings on Ren and Li in the Analects" Religions 15, no. 6: 668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060668
APA StyleLee, J. (2024). Religious Dimensions of Confucius’ Teachings on Ren and Li in the Analects. Religions, 15(6), 668. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15060668