Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing 性
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Guo Xiang Scholarship Today
What is self-so? Guo Xiang says, “Self-so means not to act deliberately, but to be thus and so of itself, spontaneously. […] But the self-so is merely the self-so, the spontaneous being such, of things themselves”. This means that self-so refers to having no intention to make or be or act [in any specific way]. Who is it that has no intention to do this? Things themselves have no intention to do this, things are spontaneously what they are. Thus, the subject of this predicate “self-so” is still things themselves; the cause of the creation of the traces of sages still lies in the sage himself, but the sage has no intention to make these traces; they are merely [part of] what he is spontaneously. It is obvious then that “that which leaves the traces” refers to the being-self-so of things themselves….(Wang in Ziporyn 2003, p. 42; translation modified)
3. Xing 性
Emphasizing the notion of “self” Meng makes it clear that Guo’s idea of xing is centered on the individual thing in question. Understanding xing accordingly, it becomes clear that “lone-transformation” and “self-so”, two issues often regarded as representing the heart of Guo’s thoughts, are based on xing. Cao Runqing 曹潤青 argues that xing is foundational in Guo’s philosophy, and “on a basic level there are two extremes that compose the notion of xing, one is the allotment of xing (xing fen 性分) and the other is self-so” (Cao 2016, p. 37).23 Accordingly, any accurate appreciation of either lone-transformation or self-so can only be made after first understanding xing.The relevant content of the theory of self-xing is that each thing makes itself itself. The so-called “lone-transformation” is just “self-contented”, “self-spontaneous”, “self-itself”, and “self-so” there is no external cause or basis “causing something to be as it is”. This thing is just “this thing”, there is nothing else to it. Each thing is its own self-xing, every person is their own personal self-xing, there is not general/universal or absolute xing. [As Guo Xiang himself writes] “each thing is its own xing, each xing has its own limitations.22
Here, Guo references dao to make his point as obvious and strong as possible. While some thinkers might associate dao with a more primordial “being” or as a source or ideal of human action, Guo vehemently rejects this—an issue we will come to again below. He places the focus fully on a thing itself, or a xing, as the source of what it is and how it acts. Xing is the metaphysical anchor for all being and actions. Thus, Guo adds more nuance to readings of earlier texts such as the Laozi and Zhuangzi which say the goal is to become “self-so” by incorporating the idea of xing. On Guo’s account simply giving free reign and resting in one’s own xing is enough to constitute self-so.The Dao itself has no capability [neng]. To say here that they achieved [de] it from the Dao is just a way of elucidating that they achieved it spontaneously [zide]. They just achieved it spontaneously, and that is all there was to it. The Dao can’t make one achieve anything, and what I myself am not up to achieving I can’t make myself achieve either. That being so, whatever can be achieved [de], externally does not depend on the Dao and internally does not depend on the self [ji]. Vacuously one but achieves it spontaneously [zide] and in so doing undergoes lone-transformation [duhua]. As difficult as it is to have existence [sheng], nevertheless through lone-transformation such existence is spontaneously realized [zide]. Once one has achieved existence, why should one any longer worry that it is impossible for such existence to be had through selfconscious effort [wei]! Therefore, making selfconscious effort to exist, as one might expect, is an ineffective way to keep one’s existence whole and safe because existence is not the result of self effort [jiwei], and if one works selfconsciously at it, this will harm one’s genuine existence.(Lynn 2022, p. 139; translation modified)
4. Xing 性, Self-So, and ming 冥 “Vanishing”
In fact, the allotment of xing indicates a bottom-up path from phenomena themselves to dao, “self-so” indicates a top-down path, it is the way dao becomes realized in the world. According to Guo Xiang’s view, self-so demonstrates the essential characteristics of a particular xing, since each xing is ceaselessly expanding, a process of realizing its potential as provided by contingencies (ming 命), and since each thing encounters different things, ultimately, the realization of possibilities is presented as the realization of different possibilities, and the phenomenal manifestation of the realization of possibilities is that all things have their own absolute limits of xing, which are expressed as different, unsearchable “traces”.31
Just as wuwei does not mean “not acting” or just lying down and letting the world pass one by, giving free rein to xing or allowing something to go by its own natural dispositions does not mean that no saddles can be used and no training can be carried out. Rather, the saddles used and training conducted must be in accord with each individual xing; a universal training plan is not tenable. Likewise, one can have goals, produce steps to take toward those goals, and even learn from others, but this has to be compatible with one’s xing.32 This involves a shift in focus—rather than having the xing accord to a general principle, the principle is just something kept in mind while the xing does what it does.He who is good at riding horses does so by letting them completely realize [jin 盡] their capability, and such complete realization of potential consists in letting [ren 任] them act to suit themselves [zi 自]. However, if when horses would walk they are forced to gallop fast, this tries to exceed the use for which they are capable, which is why it happens that, unable to bear it, many of them die. But, if horses, whether nag or great steed, were allowed to employ [ren 任] their strengths accordingly and suit their allotted capacities for speed, although their hoof prints might stretch out to beyond the eight ends of the earth, the natural disposition [xing 性] of each and every horse would surely be kept whole and safe. Nevertheless, the deluded, when they hear about horses being allowed to suit their own natures [ren xing 任性], take this to mean that they should be freed and no longer ridden. When they hear talk of wuwei, they are wont to say that this means it is better to lie down and rest than to get up and act. And how they do go on and on without ever turning back! But this is surely to miss completely what Master Zhuang means by far!(Lynn 2022, pp. 191–92; translation modified)
Here, we find that the notion of ming neatly ties together Guo’s major metaphysical concerns and has important practical repercussions as well. He may well be overly optimistic in his assessment of xing and ming—which borders on mysticism—and he may also generally hold this metaphysical framework in too high regard, but, this is a topic that can only be elucidated with a firm understanding of the key concepts in Guo’s metaphysics, which this paper intends to outline.When one draws lines on the ground and makes others follow them, these are traces that cannot be hidden again. If one possesses a self (you ji 有己) and faces objects [with it], one cannot vanish (into) things. Thus the great man does not brighten (ming 明) himself so as to shed light on others; rather, he lets the other’s own light illuminate themselves. He does not confront others [displaying] his own virtues, but gives it over to them to attain their own virtues. Thus he can thread one unity through the ten thousand things and obliquely unify (xuantong 玄同) other and self, obliteratingly (minran 泯然) becoming one with all under heaven and joining inner and outer into one felicity.
5. Wuwei 無為 “Not Acting-For” and Ji 跡 “Traces”
What names pick up on, which as we saw above stops at actualities, is only that which has been left over by actualities. Unfortunately, this is all that humans can cognize, traces of the self-so and wuwei activities of specific xing. The conditions in which the specific xing operated in, and that xing itself, are always distinct from later cognitions of it. If one tries to imitate others, even exemplars such as Yao or Shun, they only end up imitating their traces, which moves them away from what Yao and Shun were actually like, which is being self-so or wuwei.“Yao” and “Shun”, the names of the emperors, are merely their traces; the self lodges in these traces, but the traces are not the self. Thus the terror [of the world] comes from the world itself, [not from the sages]; the more terrified the world is, the coarser [the sages’] traces will be. The coarseness or excellence [of the traces merely depends on how flat or steep the road is; how could it be that the traveler has changed his feet? Thus the sage is one, but there is the difference between Yao, Shun, Tang, and Wu. [We must] understand that this difference is merely in the names given by changing times; these are not sufficient to name the actuality of the sage. Thus how could Yao and Shun have been merely “Yao” and “Shun”? Hence, although they may have the appearance of care and worry, and the traces of humaneness and duty, still that which leaves the traces is ever whole.(Ziporyn 1993, p. 514; translation modified)
Being self-so or wuwei involves responding uniquely to different situations based on what one is (xing 性), and how one fits well with everything else (all other xing). As discussed below, this is a matter of allowing one’s xing to merge, or “vanish” (ming) into the situation and all other things. Attempts to cognize traces become in the way of “vanishing” and of being self-so or wuwei. Traces are examples of situations that differ from the present situation in countless ways, and from actors that differ from anyone else. No two situations are the same, and neither are any two people. Additionally, the ways situations and people mesh are incredibly complex, so even when a person finds themselves in a similar situation, and with a somewhat similar disposition as someone else, that does not mean they can follow footprints. Interactions can vary hugely based on minute factors. Moreover, any attempt to model someone else necessarily gets in the way of one’s own self-so or wuwei merging with the situation. Ziporyn writes:Human cognition can only cognize the traces of things, that is, cognize the traces left behind by the activity of other things; they cannot cognize the self-xing (自性) of other things which leaves these traces. If we don’t distinguish between the two [and the limits of names in regard to actualities], we would have to hold that we can cognize the self-xing of other things, and that other things [i.e., other xing] were the real objects of our cognition. But Guo Xiang believes that each thing is an absolute and independent existence, which cannot be the object of cognition.(Tang in Ziporyn 2003, p. 38; translation modified)
Thus, being self-so or wuwei is largely a matter of not following traces. Once one forgets about models and does not try to imitate the way others have performed things, they are already open to operating more spontaneously. Not cognizing how one should or should not do things, especially in an overly abstract or principle-based manner, gets one in a place of operating in line with one’s own dispositions (xing), which allows them to match effectively and harmoniously with the dispositions of all other things comprising a situation. Guo connects this to a purity of virtue, which may just be another way of referencing being clear about one’s own xing. He writes “To be unclear about self-so leads to ‘acting for,’ ‘acting for’ one’s virtue is no longer pure” (Guo 1997, p. 101).36 This view is built upon a metaphysical understanding of a world comprised of various ever-transforming and constantly vanishing xing. Exactly what this means for knowledge, or cognizing, and desires and other human intentions (or “acting for”) will be explored in the next section.[T]races are not simply ineffectual for producing spontaneity [self-so and wuwei] and hence superfluous; they are positively dangerous, for they cause beings to neglect their own inner necessity in favor of something attractive outside themselves…. By cognizing attractive external traces of another being’s spontaneity, these beings lose their own spontaneity.
6. Wu Yu 無欲 “No Desires” and Wu Zhi 無知 “No Knowledge”
Here Guo is suggesting that humans are naturally (or “human nature”) just fine—what Fu Peirong means by “good”—in the sense that things will be okay, or orderly and go well-enough, as long as xing is not interfered with. As long as people can self-so and wuwei, which requires others around them to be similar to this (or do similar to this) also, then the limitations of their own xing will not be pushed. Enhancing “likings” and “desires” is one of the ways to mess up the inherent simple and straightforwardness of human xing. Knowledge is another.Human life is inherently simple and straightforward [zhi 直], so if nothing tries to lead it astray, one won’t attempt to exceed one’s natural endowment [xingming 性命], and natural desires and aversions won’t be distorted. If those in authority don’t practice wuwei, actions taken by them will result in everyone conforming to them. This is why having been seduced into liking and desiring things people are wont to exceed the limits of their natural endowment [xing 性]. Therefore, what is valued in the sage king is not his ability to put things in order but the fact that by practicing wuwei, he allows people [ren wu 任物] to behave spontaneously [ziwei 自為].(Lynn 2022, p. 208; translation modified)
In some texts, learning about the legendary sage-ruler Yao is promoted as a way of influencing people to become better. Here, knowledge is good because it gives people a model of excellence. According to Guo, however, this knowledge conflicts with people’s “self-realization” (zide 自得).40 So while it is fine to learn about Yao, or the negative example of Jie, they should be forgotten when one formulates one’s own actions. Rather, one should approach knowledge, the footprints of others, and their own desires with an attitude of you 宥 (a different character from you 有 in the wu–you pair), which Richard John Lynn understands as “letting things be”. Guo writes:Even though [the legendary sage-ruler] Yao let the world freely be, the footprints he left behind came to mean “order”. Although the order of [Yao] and the disorder of [the legendary tyrant Jie] certainly differed, it is just that the two were the same, in that they both inflicted loss of happiness on later ages and in the way they both denied self-realization to people, who either competed to esteem the one or were filled with fear and revulsion for the other. Therefore, instead of praising Yao and condemning Jie, it would be better just to forget about both of them.
Accordingly, Guo summarizes the best type of person as “not bothered by knowledge or desires” (不煩乎知欲也; Guo 1997, p. 337), and he often says that tyrants are those who become caught up in desire41 and that excessive focus on knowledge can lead one astray.42 As highlighted above, Guo is not advocating the cessation of all knowledge or desires. He is speaking very plainly of the attitude one takes towards them. Knowledge and desires are part of the human experience, and there is no attempt to eliminate them or even significantly downsize them in Guo. As long as people do not become too attached to them, and do not let them bother them, then they can continue to be self-so and wuwei or “rest in” (an 安) and “give free reign to” (ren 任) to their xing. We thus once again see major ideas in Guo as founded upon xing. Next, we will consider wu 無 and dao 道.Letting it be [you 宥] allows it to exist freely on its own [zizai 自在], which results in order, but if one tries to put it in order, disorder [luan 亂] results. […] With non-rule [wuzhi 無治], people neither exceed nor stray [from their xing].(Lynn 2022, p. 207; translation modified)
7. Wu 無 “Nothing” and Dao 道 “Way”
Confucius goes on to say that we cannot, for example, speak of a time before there were sons and grandsons. Seen in relation to Wang Bi, the rejection of wu is perhaps the most radical aspect of Guo’s work.48 Guo is not necessarily criticizing a more ontic understanding of wu in Laozi 11, but he is overtly rejecting any Wang Bi–inspired thinking of wu as the root of all things and yet an ontological nothing.It is not only that wu (nothing) cannot transform and become you (something), but also you (something) cannot transform and become wu (nothing). Accordingly, even though you (something) can become things and affairs, and although it changes and transforms in thousands of ways, not even once will it become wu (nothing). Not even once becoming wu (nothing), thus, from long ago there has never been a time without you (something), it has constantly existed.
Here we move from the rejection of the ontological wu that is nothingness as having any relation to the world to an even more radical rejection of dao. Readers of the Laozi and Zhuangzi well know that dao is a major concept. Guo undermines the concept, or, as we will see later, perhaps repurposes it:What could possibly exist prior to things! I might have it that yin and yang were prior to them, but yin and yang themselves are just what we may call things. So what was there even prior to yin and yang? I might have it that self-so was prior to them,50 but self-so means just things functioning spontaneously on their own. I might have it that the perfect Dao was there prior to it, but the perfect Dao consists of just perfect emptiness [zhiwu]. As such, it has no existence, so what could have been more prior to that? This being so, what then could have possibly existed prior to things! However, since things still come into existence without ever ending, it is clear that they just happen self-so and not because something makes them happen [非有使然也].(Lynn 2022, p. 398; translation modified)
Ziporyn reiterates by saying that in Guo we find “insistence that Dao is and does exactly nothing, that there is no Dao outside of things in their multiplicity” (Ziporyn 2003, p. 45). In fact, dao has no place in Guo’s thoughts. It is at best a marker or way of saying things were just self-so, self-right, self-attained, and the like. Rather than actually being something, or asking people to align themselves with it, or having any influence on the world, dao helps us realize that there is nothing that has this role, and things are what they are in and of themselves, and that is best.The Dao has no power. When the text says, “They attained it from the Dao”, this is merely to show that they spontaneously attained it. It is simply spontaneously auto-attained; the Dao cannot make them attain it. What I have not attained, I cannot make myself attain. Thus whatever is attained [i.e., whatever qualities one has] externally does not depend on the Dao, internally does not come from my self; it is simply abruptly auto-attained and self-right (zide 自得) and lone-transformation (duhua 独化).
8. Conclusions
There might be more to the picture here; Guo might have other ideas that contribute to this statement. Otherwise, what he writes here seems potentially overly expectant. Describing this and other sections, Ziporyn writes,Therefore, arcanely [mingran] take whatever one encounters as fated yet never engage in it with one’s mind [xin 心]—one is thus so perfectly identified with it [minran] that he becomes one with what is perfectly appropriate [zhidang] and stays free from joy or sorrow while this happens. Therefore, although one might serve some ordinary fellow, he shall always act with perfect appropriateness whatever he sets out to do—so how much more likely will he succeed when it comes to ruler or parents!
This is not only difficult to swallow, but hard to imagine. What exactly does it look similar to “thoroughly merge” or “vanish” into the “cacophony” of all things, and will that really lead to perfect appropriateness?The same applies to the ideal man and the things he encounters; he follows them, lets them be what they are, but does not imitate or esteem any particular ones, nor does he attempt to make any of them other than they are, forcing one to be like another or himself to be like any one of them, or any of them like him. For in Guo’s ideal, there is no particular “him” for them to be like. The mind of the sage is nonexistent, like the Dao, and this is the great virtue of both. The perfect self-rightness of all things lies in this peculiar type of nonaction [wuwei] and silence, which is at the same time, by virtue of its very inaction and silence, the action and cacophony of all it encounters. By thoroughly merging [ming] with this cacophony, by becoming it, one fits it, vanishing (into) it [ming], and thereby forgets it.
With character perfectly realized and natural endowment completely fulfilled, Heaven and Earth are suffused with joy. Since nothing happens to impede such joy, this means he is utterly disengaged.
When one complies with the joy of Heaven, ample shall be his joy.
Again, what Guo writes here “flies in the face of common sense” and deserves further exploration. The work in this paper provides a starting point to further explore such claims.Once no mindfulness of joy exists, joy becomes completely ample.
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Guo Xiang, like many of his contemporaries, believed that the Zhuangzi was written by a historical person, Zhuangzi or Zhuang Zhou, and likewise with the Laozi. Translations of these titles into English follow from these views. |
2 | |
3 | Understanding Guo Xiang’s thought as a coherent and systematic philosophy is by no means an uncontroversial issue. Many scholars have disputed this characterization. In their respective works Tang Junyi 唐君毅 (d. 1978), Lao Siguang 勞思光 (d. 2012) (Lao 2003), and Fang Dongmei 方東美 (d. 1977) have all made this argument. They do have differing reasons for contesting the idea that Guo’s commentary can be understood as a philosophical system. But this is outside the scope of this article. |
4 | Whereas wu often indicates a “lack” or even “fleeing”, bu is more of a direct negation or denial, something like “not” or “no” or even “that is not the case”. The implications of using bu wei rather than wuwei are worth noting, but outside the scope of the current project. |
5 | Huang Shengping 黄圣平 provides an extremely detailed study of xing in Guo’s philosophy (Huang 2007). |
6 | Christine Tan wrote her PhD thesis (in English) on Guo Xiang and is turning it into a monograph scheduled for publication in 2024 or 2025. |
7 | Tang Yijie deals with many of the same issues discussed in this paper. Much of his work is also dedicated to du 獨 or “lone” and its various formations in Guo’s work, such as duhua 獨化 or “lone transformation” (see Tang 2009; Lo 2020). Du is undoubtably a significant concept, but falls outside the scope of this paper. |
8 | Feng Youlan published several histories of philosophy (Feng 1934, 1986; Fung 1948) which include sections devoted to Xuanxue. Feng also translated the Zhuangzi with selections of Guo Xiang’s commentary (1931). However, for many interest in Xuanxue in modern China was “rebooted” with Tang ([1957] 2009). For concise introductions to Xuanxue see Li (2006); Chan (2014); D’Ambrosio (2016b). |
9 | Previously the most significant access in English to a translation of Guo’s commentary was some partial translations in Brook Ziporyn’s translation of the Zhuangzi (Ziporyn 2009). |
10 | In a recent paper, titled “Metaphysics and Agency in Guo Xiang’s Commentary on the Zhuangzi”, Chris Fraser (2020) takes up themes similar to those discussed in this paper. In particular Fraser reads Guo as positing a “metaphysical view of dao” and hones in on ming (vanishing) as important for a “normative stance” on agency. Traditional scholarship on Guo demonstrates that dao is not a concept Guo utilized, and that most of his mentions of this term are either negating it, or speaking of a particular notion of dao. This will be greatly expanded upon below. In terms of normativity, this is also a place where Chinese scholarship on Guo widely agrees that there is no “normative” argument in Guo’s work. It is outside the scope of this paper to delve more into this issue. However, readers familiar with Western philosophy will likely find Fraser’s paper very insightful. |
11 | Ye writes “根本上来说,事物之所以‘自然’,乃是以其内有的‘性分’为依据。” |
12 | |
13 | Tang does not reject change, in fact he focuses on “lone-transformation” in much of his work, but he understands xing as being stable. Xing itself does not change, each xing constantly disappears and is replaced by another. |
14 | In some sense Ziporyn follows Tang very closely on this point. |
15 | These are the most common terms, but there are others. For example, He Yan’s 何晏 (d. 249) “commentary” on the Lunyu is called a “ji jie 集解”, which could be literally translated as “collected explanations”. |
16 | For a further discussion of this, as well as a lengthy treatment of the idea that Xuanxue “merges” Confucian and Daoist ideas, see D’Ambrosio (2016b). |
17 | Feng Youlan expressed a concern nearly 100 years ago with undervaluing commentators and misunderstanding them based on modern philosophical assumptions writing: “When [later Chinese thinkers] had ideas, instead of expressing those ideas directly in their own names, they would read them into the sayings of some ancient authority as if they had found them already there. Their writings, therefore, were usually in the form of commentaries. But commentators of this kind were really philosophers; commentaries of this kind were really philosophical works, having intrinsic value in themselves. To this class of commentators and commentaries belonged Kuo Hsiang [Guo Xiang] and his work, ‘Commentaries on the Chuang-tzu [Zhuangzi]’. If we realize that Kuo Hsiang was an independent philosopher just as Chuang Tzu had been…” (Fung 1931, p. 57). |
18 | This is not to say that other thinkers did not also come up with more individualized notions. For some discussions of this see, for example, (Munro 1985). For a discussion of how Guo’s notion of xing relates to other conceptions, see Liu (2022). |
19 | |
20 | Relatedly discussion can be found in a number of other scholars’ work (see Yü 2016; Coles 2019). |
21 | This has been noticed by many scholars, including Tang and Yang themselves. Below we will discuss Cao Runqing’s 曹潤青 work in some detail. His research on Guo Xiang investigates these terms in detail (see Cao 2016). |
22 | The original reads: “自性说的实质就是使各自成为自己。所谓“独化”,就是“自在”、“自尔”、“自己”、“自然”,没有什么外在的原因或根据“使之然”。这一个就是“这一个”,不是别的什么,每一物都有每一物的自性,每个人都有每个人的自性,没有普遍绝对的性。“物各有性,性各有极。” |
23 | The original reads: “郭像對性的基本理解,一個是性分,一個是自然,二者共同構成了性這一概念下的兩端。” |
24 | As mentioned above, there are several ways to understand Guo Xiang’s notion of xing. This description relies on a fairly standard interpretation. |
25 | There is not a lot of research on the philosophical significance of an 安, though some, such as Fei Xiaotong 費孝通 (d. 2005) have argued that it is actually crucial for understanding the Lunyu (see Fei 1948). A study of Guo’s unique use of an, especially in comparison with that of the Lunyu, would be interesting, but falls outside the scope of this paper. |
26 | Guo writes, for example, “Rest in one’s self-so, and that is enough (ren qi ziran er yi 任其自然而已)” (Guo 1997, p. 388). |
27 | In the in the “Wen xue” 文學 (“Letters and Scholarship”) chapter of the Shishuo Xinyu 世說新語 (“A New Account of the Tales of the World”) Liu Xiaobiao 劉孝標 (d. 521) expresses Zhi Dun 支遁 (d. 366 CE) hesitation over this general theme in Guo’s philosophy: 夫逍遙者,明至人之心也。莊生建言大道,而寄指鵬[鷃]。鵬以營生之路曠,故失適於體外;鷃以在近而笑遠,有矜伐於心內。至人乘天正而高興,遊無窮於放浪,物物而不物於物,則遙然不我得;玄感不為,不疾而速,則逍然靡不適,此所以為逍遙也。若夫有欲當其所足,足於所足,快然有似天真,猶飢者一飽,渴者一盈豈忘烝嘗於糗糧,絕觴爵於醪醴哉?苟非至足,豈所以逍遙乎? (Zhu and Shen 2011, p. 68) One who is “free and easy” clarifies the heart-mind of the utmost person. When Zhuangzi talked about the great dao, he used the analogy of the Peng bird and the quail. Because the Peng bird’s way of life is untrammeled, it loses all particular direction in the realm beyond the body. But because the quail, on the other hand, lives in the near and scoffs at the far, there is a certain complacency in the realm within its heart-mind. The utmost person, riding upon the correctness of the heavens, soars aloft, wandering without bounds in unfettered freedom. Since he treats objects as objects, without being treated as an object by other objects, therefore in his roaming he is not self-satisfied. Being mystically in communion with the cosmos, he does not act purposefully (bu wei). He is not hurried, yet he moves swiftly. Therefore in his freedom he goes everywhere. This is how it becomes “free roaming”. But if, on the other hand, one has a desire to fulfill one’s own contentment, and to be content with one’s own contentment, such a person in his happiness has something like natural simplicity, like a hungry man once he is satiated, or a thirsty man once his thirst is quenched. But would such a man forthwith forget all about cooking and eating in the presence of grains and cereals, or put an end to all further toasting and pledging in the presence of wines and liquors? Unless it is perfect contentment, how can it be a means to free roaming? (Mather 2017, p. 116; translation modified). |
28 | In his comments to Guo’s work Cheng Xuanying writes “an and ren mean the same thing (an, ren ye 安,任也)” (Guo 1997, p. 471). |
29 | We often say things like “Oh that’s so Mom” or “Of course Ashley would say that/do that”. While this is not exactly what Guo is describing, it does provide a starting place for understanding his notion of xing. |
30 | For example, see the Xing Zi Ming Chu 性自命出. |
31 | The original reads: “實上,性分顯示的是從現象通向道的由下而上的路徑,自然則是從道落實於現象的由上而下的路徑。在郭像看來,自然呈現了性的本質特徵,即性是不斷展開著的、實現命賦予它的可能性的過程,每一個個體由於所遇到的際遇不同,最終呈現為不同可能性的實現,可能性的實現在現像上的表現則是萬物各有其絕對的性分之限,表現為各自不同的、無法求取的’跡’。” |
32 | Discussing self-cultivation and naturalism in Guo Xiang’s work, Benjamin Coles delves much further into this issue (see Coles 2019). Unfortunately this theme is outside the scope of this paper, but it is very important for understanding the significance of xing. |
33 | References to the Laozi, Lunyu, and Zhuangzi are made in accordance with ctext.org, which follows the Harvard-Yenching Institute Sinological Index Series concordance. Translations not otherwise indicated are the author’s own. |
34 | This discussion evolves somewhat in Xuanxue to become “teaching of names” versus “self-so”. It is a helpful framework, but one which is outside the scope of this article. For insightful treatments see Tang ([1957] 2009); Lü (1999); Chan (2014); D’Ambrosio (2016b). |
35 | The original reads “名止於實,故無為;實各自為,故無不為。” |
36 | The original reads “不明自然則有為,有為而德不純也”. |
37 | By this Fu does not mean that human nature is “good” in a moral sense or in a sense that is necessarily compatible with, for example, what we find in the Mengzi. The idea is rather that texts like the Laozi and Zhuangzi—and here we are extending this to Guo’s thought as well—advocate going along with what is natural in humans. Doing this, interpersonal relationships and even political affairs will go well. This point will be discussed further below. |
38 | |
39 | For fuller discussions of knowledge as well as the relationship between knowledge and traces see Ziporyn (1993); D’Ambrosio (2016a). In a later article of Ziporyn’s (2015) he describes this relationship in more detail, and discusses at length the discourse surrounding this debate. Richard John Lynn has explored knowing in the context of Guo’s work on the Lunyu, see Lynn (2020). |
40 | One way to think of “self-realization” is as a form of freedom. Many people throughout history, especially artists, literati, and scholars, have found the Zhuangzi and Guo as resources inspiring notions of freedom. Christine Tan argues that Guo’s thought in particular offers a unique alternative to the way freedom is often construed in contemporary (western) philosophical thought. Rather than the familiar “freedom to” or “freedom from”, Tan argues, Guo and the notion of zide reflect on “freedom in” (see Tan 2023; see also Tan 2021). |
41 | See, for example, Guo’s comments to chapter 4 of the Zhuangzi. |
42 | This will be discussed in more detail below. |
43 | For a fuller discussion of this see D’Ambrosio (2020). |
44 | Scholars often write as if the Laozi is obviously speaking of metaphysics or ontology when discussing dao (e.g., Gao 2022), however, this is clearly not the case. Chen Guying 陳鼓應 (b. 1935) has done a wonderful job demonstrating that there are multiple possible readings, and assuming dao has metaphysical and ontological implications only becomes wide spread after Wang Bi’s influence (Chen 2020). |
45 | This has been a consistent reading of Guo Xiang for almost two thousand years. Feng Youlan, Tang Yijie, Tang Yongtong, Brook Ziporyn, and Paul D’Ambrosio (see works cited above and in the references) all agree with this reading as well. However, recently some scholars have challenged that there might be other ways to look at this issue. A growing number of papers have questioned the traditional reading of Guo’s rejection of dao. For example, see Yu (2004), Wang (2006), and Liu (2022). Gao (2022) provides a useful summary of this debate in English. In this paper I agree with the traditional reading, and do not have the space to go too far into this debate. However, I would note that there are very obvious rejections of dao in Guo’s work, and that the attempts to revitalize this concept perform a decent amount of theoretical acrobatics—which cannot be sufficiently explored in this short section. |
46 | In this he is not unlike Pei Wei 裴頠 (d. 300), who wrote a treatise titled “Extolling you 有” (Chongyou lun 崇有論). |
47 | We might even go so far as to say “anti-metaphysical” although, as noted above, this has recently become a highly contested issue. |
48 | This comment may be off. Clearly it was very popular for scholars and literati to follow Wang Bi in taking wu to be the root. But in addition to Guo Xiang, Pei Wei also rejects this idea, and it is not easy to gauge just how “radical” this position was. |
49 | Another way to put this, is that while Guo does talk a lot about the origins of the cosmos, it is almost always negative—i.e., saying what it is not. He does not have a theory of how things came about. According to Guo, everything is self-generated. |
50 | Scholars who think Guo does provide a robust notion of dao sometimes refer to self-so as primordial (see Gao 2022). |
51 | In his first comment on the opening lines of chapter 16 of the Zhuangzi, Guo writes: “Having already regulated their original natures with conventional wisdom, such people now desire to recover the essence of their natural endowments by studying that conventional wisdom, but in seeking it in this way, they are ever more estranged from the Dao”. (Lynn 2022, p. 300) Guo does not reject the use of a notion of dao. Rather, focusing on the conceptualization of dao is problematic. This discussion of dao in Guo’s thought is far from comprehensive, but it does provide an inroad for understanding his unique metaphysical appreciation of dao. |
References
- Cao, Runqing 曹潤青. 2016. Xingfen yu Ziran: Guo Xiang Zhuangzi Zhu Zhong “Xing” de Gainian 性分與自然:郭象《莊子注》中“性”的概念 [The Allotment of Xing and Self-So: On the Concept of Xing in Guo Xiang’s Commentary to the Zhuangzi]. Journal of Pingdingshan University 平頂山學院學報 31: 23–37. [Google Scholar]
- Chan, Alan. 2014. ‘Neo-Daoism.’ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Online Edition. Available online: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/neo-daoism/index.html (accessed on 7 June 2023).
- Chen, Guying. 2020. The Annotated Critical Laozi: With Contemporary Explication and Traditional Commentary. Translated by Paul J. D’Ambrosio, and Ouyang Xiao. Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Coles, Benjamin. 2019. Guo Xiang and the Problem of Self-Cultivation in Daoist Naturalism. Religions 10: 388. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul J. 2016a. Guo Xiang on Self-So Knowledge. Asian Philosophy 26: 119–32. [Google Scholar]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul J. 2016b. Wei-Jin Period Xuanxue (Neo-Daoism): Reworking the Relationship between Confucian and Daoist Themes. Philosophy Compass 11: 621–31. [Google Scholar]
- D’Ambrosio, Paul. 2020. He Yan’s ‘On Dao’ (dao lun 道論) and ‘On the Nameless’ (wuming lun 無名論). In Dao Companion to Xuanxue 玄學 (Neo-Daoism). Edited by David Chai. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 167–84. [Google Scholar]
- Dai, Liangchang 戴璉璋. 1995. Guo Xiang de Zisheng Shuo yu Xuanming Lun 郭象的自生說與玄冥論 [Guo Xiang’s Theory of Self-Generation and Discussions of Darkness]. Researches on Chinese Literature and Philosophy 中國文哲研究集刊 7: 39–78. [Google Scholar]
- Fei, Xiaotong 費孝通. 1948. Xiangtu Zhongguo 鄉土中國 [From the Soil: The Foundations of Chinese Society]. Beijing: SDX Joint Publishing Company 三聯書店. [Google Scholar]
- Feng, Youlan 馮友蘭. 1934. Zhongguo Zhexue Shi shang xi ace 中國哲學史上下冊 [A History of Chinese Philosophy, volumes 1 and 2.]. Beijing: People’s Press 人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Feng, Youlan 馮友蘭. 1986. Zhongguo Zhexue Shi Xinbian 中國哲學史新編 [A New History of Chinese Philosophy]. Beijing: People’s Press 人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Fraser, Chris. 2020. Metaphysics and Agency in Guo Xiang’s Commentary on the Zhuangzi. In Dao Companion to Xuanxue 玄學 (Neo-Daoism). Edited by David Chai. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 343–66. [Google Scholar]
- Fu, Peirong 傅佩荣. 2006. Laozi Fu Peirong yi jie 老子傅佩榮譯解 [Fu Peirong’s Interpretation and Explanation of the Laozi]. Beijing: Oriental Publishing Center. [Google Scholar]
- Fung, Yu-Lan [Feng Youlan 馮友蘭]. 1931. Chuang-Tzu: A New Selected Translation with an Exposition of the Philosophy of Kuo Hsiang. New York: Gordan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fung, Yu-Lan [Feng Youlan 馮友蘭]. 1948. A Short History of Chinese Philosophy. Translated by Derk Bodde. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gao, Yuhan. 2022. Rethinking Guo Xiang’s Concept of “Nothing” in the Perspective of His Reception of Laozi and Zhuangzi. Religions 13: 593. [Google Scholar]
- Guo, Qingfan 郭慶藩. 1997. Zhuangzi jishi 莊子集釋 [Collected Explanations of Master Zhuang]. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Huang, Shengping 黄圣平. 2007. Guo Xiang Xuanxue Yanjiu: Yanzhe Benxinglun de Lilu 郭象玄学研究:沿着本性论的理路 [A Study of Guo Xiang and Xuanxue: Following the Path of Theories on Natural Dispositions]. Beijing: Hualing Press 华龄出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Knaul, Livia. 1985. Kuo Hsiang and the Chuang Tzu. Journal of Chinese Philosophy 12: 429–47. [Google Scholar]
- Lao, Siguang. 2003. Wen hua zhe xue yan jiang lu 文化哲學演講錄 [Lectures on Philosophy of Culture]. Hong Kong: The Chinese University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Zehou 李澤厚. 2006. Zhongguo Gudai Sixiang Shilun 中國古代思想史論 [A Treatise on the History Classical Chinese Thought]. Beijing: SDX Joint Publishing Company 新知三聯書店. [Google Scholar]
- Lin, Xiyi 林希逸. 2015. Laozi yanzhai kouyi 老子鬳齋口義 [Interpretation of the Laozi in Everyday Language]. Shanghai: East China Normal University Press 華東師範大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Guomin 劉國民. 2022. Guo Xiang Zisheng, Duhua Shuo Xinshi 郭象自生、獨化說新釋 [New Interpretations of Guo Xiang’s Theories of Self-Generation and Lone-Transformation]. Hubei University Journal 湖北大學學報 2022: 221–39. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xiaogan. 2008. Two Orientations in Hermeneutic Writing: Wang Bi’s Commentary on the Lao Zi and Guo Xiang’s Commentary on the Zhuang Zi. Contemporary Chinese Thought 20: 23–45. [Google Scholar]
- Lo, Yuet Keung. 2020. Lone-Transformation and Intergrowth: Philosophy and Self-Justification in Guo Xiang’s Commentary on the Zhuangzi. In Dao Companion to Xuanxue 玄學 (Neo-Daoism). Edited by David Chai. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 367–92. [Google Scholar]
- Lü, Xichen 呂錫琛. 1999. Guo Xiang Renwei ‘Mingjiao’ ji ‘Ziran’ ma? 郭象認為“名教”即“自然”嗎? [Does Guo Xiang Think the ‘Teaching of Names’ is ‘Self-so’?]. Philosophical Researches 哲學研究 1999: 84–103. [Google Scholar]
- Lynn, Richard J. 2020. Guo Xiang’s Theory of Sagely Knowledge as Seen in His “Essentials of the Analects”. In Dao Companion to Xuanxue 玄學 (Neo-Daoism). Edited by David Chai. Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 393–410. [Google Scholar]
- Lynn, Richard John. 2022. Zhuangzi: A New Translation of the Sayings of Master Zhuang as Interpreted by Guo Xiang. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mather, Richard, trans. 2017. Shih-shuo Hsin-yu: A New Account of Tales of the World. Ann-Arbor: University of Michigan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Meng, Peiyuan 蒙培元. 2021. Meng Pieyuan Quanji 蒙培元全集 [The Collected Works of Meng Peiyuan]. Sichuan: Sichuan People’s Press 四川人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Munro, Donald. 1985. Individualism and Holism: Studies in Confucian and Taoist Values. Ann Arbor: U of M Center for Chinese Studies Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Shang, Jianfei 尚建飛. 2013. Wei-Jin Xuanxue Daode Zhexue Yanjiu 魏晉玄學道德哲學研究 [A Study of Wei-Jin Xuanxue Moral Philosophy]. Beijing: Renmin Chubanshe 人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Tan, Christine. 2021. Guo Xiang’s Ontology of Zide. Self-Realisation Beyond the Binary Self. Monumenta Serica 69: 1–17. [Google Scholar]
- Tan, Christine. 2023. ‘Freedom In’: A Daoist Response to Isaiah Berlin. Dao 22: 255–75. [Google Scholar]
- Tang, Yijie 湯一介. 2009. Guo Xiang yu Weijin Xuanxue 郭象與魏晉玄學 [Guo Xiang and Wei-Jin Period Xuanxue]. Beijing: Beijing Daxue Chubanshe 北京大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Tang, Yongtong 湯用彤. 2009. Weijin Xuanxue Lungao 魏晉玄學論稿 [Essays on Wei-Jin Period Xuanxue]. Beijing: SDX Joint Publishing Company 三聯書店. First published 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Deyou 王德有. 2010. Wei-jin Xuanxue: Gao Daoyi de Xianshi Rensheng 魏晉玄學:高蹈逸的閒適人生 [Wei-Jin Xuanxue: Leisurely Living Hermits]. Shanghai: Oriental Publishing Center. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Xiaoyi 王曉毅. 2006. Guo Xiang Pingzhuan 郭象評傳 [A Review of Guo Xiang]. Nanjing: Nanjing University Press 南京大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Zhongjiang 王中江. 2015. Daojia Xueshuo de Guannian Shi Yanjiu 道家学说的观念史研究 [Research on the Conceptual History of Daoist Theories]. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Xu, Kangsheng 許抗生. 2008. Lue tan Wei Jin xuanxue de ziranzhuyi sixiang 略談魏晉玄學的自然主義思想. In Wei Jin xuanxue yanjiu 魏晉玄學研究. Edited by Yijie Tang 湯一介 and Zhongping Hu 胡仲平. Wuhan: Hubei Education Press, pp. 444–59. [Google Scholar]
- Yang, Lihua 楊立華. 2010. Guo Xiang Zhuangzi Zhu Yanjiu 郭象《庄子注》研究 [A Study of Guo Xiang’s Commentary to the Zhuangzi]. Beijing: Beijing Daxue Chubanshe 北京大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Ye, Shuxun 葉樹勳. 2018. Guo Xiang “Ziran” Guannian de Neihan jiqi xiangguan Wenti 郭象“自然”观念的内涵及其相关问题 [The Meaning of Guo Xiang’s Notion of “Self-So” and Related Issues]. Contemporary Philosophy 现代哲学 5: 124–39. [Google Scholar]
- Yu, Dunkang 余敦康. 2004. Weijin Xuanxue Shi 魏晉玄學史 [The History of Wei-Jin Xuanxue]. Beijing: Beijing Daxue Chubanshe 北京大學出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Yü, Ying-shih. 2016. Individualism and the Neo-Daoist Movement in Wei-Jin China. In Chinese History and Culture: Sixth Century B.C.E. to Seventeenth Century. Edited by Michael S. Duke and Josephine Chiu-Duke. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 134–65. [Google Scholar]
- Zhu, Bilian 朱碧蓮, and Haibo Shen 瀋海波, eds. 2011. A New Account of the Tales of the World 世說新語. Beijing: Zhonghua Shuju 中華書局. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook. 1993. Self-so and its Traces in the Thought of Guo Xiang. Philosophy East and West 43: 511–39. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook. 2003. The Penumbra Unbound: The Neo-Taoist Philosophy of Guo Xiang. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook. 2009. Zhuangzi: The Essential Writings with Selections from Traditional Commentaries. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Ziporyn, Brook. 2015. Guo Xiang: The Self-So and the Repudiation-Cum-Reaffirmation of Deliberate Action and Knowledge. In Dao Companion to Daoist Philosophy. Edited by Xiaogan Liu. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 397–423. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
D’Ambrosio, P.J. Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing 性. Religions 2023, 14, 879. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070879
D’Ambrosio PJ. Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing 性. Religions. 2023; 14(7):879. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070879
Chicago/Turabian StyleD’Ambrosio, Paul Joseph. 2023. "Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing 性" Religions 14, no. 7: 879. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070879
APA StyleD’Ambrosio, P. J. (2023). Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing 性. Religions, 14(7), 879. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070879