Next Article in Journal
Guo Xiang’s Metaphysics of Being and Action: On the Importance of Xing
Next Article in Special Issue
Relations in Ramon Llull’s Trinitarian Ontology
Previous Article in Journal
Happiness and Being Human: The Tension between Immanence and Transcendence in Religion/Spirituality
Previous Article in Special Issue
Aquinas’s Understanding of Religion
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

The Unknowability and Imagination in Mystical Doctrines of the Late Medieval English Mysticism

by
Lucie Rathouzská
Thomas-Institut, Universität zu Köln, Universitätsstr. 22, D-50923 Cologne, Germany
Religions 2023, 14(7), 878; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070878
Submission received: 10 May 2023 / Revised: 28 June 2023 / Accepted: 4 July 2023 / Published: 6 July 2023
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Religion and Faith in the Reception of the Middle Ages)

Abstract

:
There are three English authors of the fourteenth century we may call “imaginative mystics” because of their use of imagination in spiritual praxis, i.e., Richard Rolle, Walter Hilton, and the unknown author of the Cloud of Unknowing. However, recently, there has been some criticism expressed regarding these doctrines; in particular, there is a question of whether a spiritual praxis, which includes imaginative images, can keep the principle of the unknowability of God. There is also a question of sensual perception. Imaginative images keep some attributes of sensual perception, such as shape, and they always have some spatiality and temporality. There is a question: how can these images depict the spiritual nature of God and spiritual objects themselves? There is even a possibility that imagination darkens contemplative vision and turns the soul’s attention back to the world. In this paper, I will try to show how these three English authors kept the principle of God’s unknowability and what the role of the imagination in their spiritual praxis is.

1. Introduction

Serm. 277, 14 (PL 38): After all, we look with our eyes, we don’t look askance at our eyes. Only don’t let us strive to reduce God to a place, don’t let’s strive to shut God up in a place, don’t let’s strive to spread God out in any kind of bulk through extended space; let us not have the nerve to do that, let’s not even think of it. Let the substance of divinity remain in its own proper dignity.
(Translation by Hill 1994, p. 41)1
In the excerpt from Sermon 277 above, Augustine asks, “How could God be seen if He is a spiritual being and has no physical attributes that we can see with our fleshly sight?”. Augustine warns against understanding God as a fleshly being because of God’s spiritual nature. Seeing God with carnal attributes limits the understanding of his true divinity. Augustine’s question of how “God could be seen,” in the light of this problem with the inadequacy of bodily seeing of spiritual nature, became later a question of spiritual practice. A few centuries later, there were three 14th-century English mystics, Richard Rolle (1300–1349), Walter Hilton (1340–1396), and especially the unknown author of Cloud of Unknowing, who, similarly as Augustine says:
Cloud, ch. 61, p. 88: Take case, therefore, that you do not understand in a bodily sense what is meant spiritually, even though it is expressed in bodily words, such as UP or DOWN, IN or OUT, BEHIND or IN FRONT, ON ONE SIDE or ON THE OTHER SIDE. For however spiritual something may be in itself, yet if it is to be spoken about, given that speech is a bodily activity performed by the tongue, a bodily organ, it must always be spoken in bodily words. But does it follow that it must therefore be received and understood in a bodily sense?—no, not spiritually.
Every expression within a language is connected to corporeality. The author of Cloud of Unknowing stresses that spiritual metaphors have to be interpreted adequately in their spiritual sense because the corporeal sense leads to misinterpretation.
A similar problem is associated with imagination in spiritual practice. There is the question of whether imaginative images can truly represent spiritual objects always associated with corporeality, for every such image carries at least spatiality and temporality. It is not only English authors who often use imagery with various parables and metaphors. A peculiarity of these images lies in their double quality. They carry a spiritual meaning while retaining the characteristics of bodily perception. We can then suppose that the imagination cannot adequately represent God and spiritual objects because the association with corporeality limits our understanding. The fundamental questions are “can God be seen in the imagination?” and “what is the role of the imagination in spiritual practice?” English authors offer specific answers to these questions characterized by their awareness of this problem and their connection to the Christian tradition.
We can doubt the credibility of the imagination and the images it provides. Augustine associates the unreliability of imagery with corporeality for a specific reason. There is no image that was not perceived by the senses before. Imagination needs bodily perception. Augustine shows the fallibility of the imagination in his reply to Nebridius in his Seventh Epistle2 where he answers the question of whether the imagination as the soul’s power is independent of the senses:
Ep. 7, 2, 3 (CSEL 34/I, 14, 26–29): […] images is not, as you write, the mere suggestion or admonition occasioning their formation by the mind within itself, but the actual bringing in to the mind, or, to speak more definitely, impressing upon it of the illusions to which through the senses we are subject.
The images of imagination are not genuine and affect the soul with illusions; our bodily perception is much more truthful. (Ep. 7, 2, 5 (CSEL 44/I, 16, 20).4 Thomas Aquinas follows Aristotle’s treatise on the faculties of the soul from De anima. We can adopt his definition of imagination (imaginatio) as a mental faculty common to humans and animals that preserves images of things not currently experienced by the senses (Com. De anima, 3, 5, 151).5 Imagination participates in knowledge as one of the four inner senses of the soul.6 The question of the role of imagination in gaining knowledge of God is even more challenging. The second article of the sixth question of Thomas’s Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius, “whether divine science must be founded on imagination?” or “whether imagination must be renounced?” offers an answer. Thomas first gives reasons why God can be understood only through imagination. He refers to Aristotle, according to whom we cannot understand anything intellectually without the participation of imagination. (Expos. super librum Boethii De trinitate, 6, 2, 1).7 The opposite position that understanding God does not depend on imagination is supported by Thomas at the beginning of Augustine’s De trinitate. Augustine points out the problem of bringing spiritual things within the limits of bodily perception, as by imagination, only bodily matters could be understood. (Expos. super librum Boethii De trinitate, 6, 2, 2).8 In his reply, Thomas argues that all knowledge consists of a beginning and a goal, i.e., judgment. The origin of all knowledge is sense perception and grasping by imagination. The intellectual understanding then is derived from this imaginative grasp. The origin and goal of knowledge are often in the senses (knowledge of nature) and the imagination (mathematics), but there is also the knowledge that transcends both. Thomas refers here to the knowledge of spiritual things, which may originate from the senses and imagination, but they cannot form a judgment:
Expos. super librum Boethii De trinitate, 6, 2: In the case of divine things, we may use the senses and the imagination as the principles of our reasoning, but not as the ends of it, as if we were to judge that divine things are as things perceived by the senses or the imagination. For to aim at something is to have a goal in it. Therefore, divine science can aim neither at the imagination nor the senses, in mathematics only at the imagination but not at the senses, and in natural science at the senses.
(Translation by LR)9
Our knowledge may begin in the imagination, but it does not complete in the senses or the imagination. Understanding is initiated by the action of the intellect. According to Thomas, if we were to prevent the imagination from acting, we would also prevent the intellect from understanding things, even divine things.10 (Expos. super librumBoethii De trinitate, 6, 2).
In this article, I will focus on how the English mystics of the late Middle Ages dealt with the question of the imagination and what methods they adopted to overcome the problems associated with the imagination. The essential question I ask is whether and how it is possible to see God in the imagination.

2. The Limits of Imagination and the Mutual Discussion between English Authors

In his works, Richard explicitly rejects the participation of imagination in spiritual life, especially in contemplation. His rejection of this mental potency confirms the writing Officium et miracula written in defense of Richard’s canonization, which never took place. According to the Officium, one of the manifestations of contemplation, the song Richard heard in contemplation, did not come from the imagination because it was a genuine spiritual song (Officium, p. 15).11 We can doubt the success of the Officium’s defense when we read the notes of Richard’s contemporaries, the unknown author of Cloud of Unknowing and Walter Hilton:
Scale, II, II, XI, pp. 233–34: In like manner may it be said of other kind of feelings that are like to bodily, as hearing of delectable songs, or feeling of comfortable heat in the body, seeing of light, or sweetness of bodily savour. These are not spiritual feelings; for spiritual feelings are felt in the powers of the soul, principally in the understanding, and in love and little in the imagination. But these feelings are felt in the powers of the body in the imagination and therefore are not spiritual feelings.
In this passage, Hilton mentions “bodily feelings” and condemns them as false expressions of contemplation that have no relationship to true spirituality. The reason why we can assume that this is a condemnation of Richard’s mystical work lies in his particular kind of bodily metaphors. Richard speaks in very colorful language about the three manifestations of contemplation, heat (calor), sweetness (dulcor), and song (canor).12 Further, the passage shows that Hilton believes true spirituality lies in understanding, the rational part of the soul, and love, but not in the imagination, which can only contribute a little (it is just “little in the imagination”). These sensory metaphors lead us to the author of Cloud of Unknowing. In Chapter 46 of the treatise, he says:
Cloud ch. 46, pp. 69–70: For God’s love, therefore, take care in this work of contemplation not to strain your heart in your breast too roughly or immoderately, but work with skill rather than with brute force. For the more skilfully, the more humbly and spiritually; and the more roughly, the more physically and like a beast. So take care, for any beast-like heart that presumes to touch the peak of contemplation will certainly be beaten away with stones.
The statement of the unknown author is less clear than the Hilton’s in the quotation above. However, the unknown author distinguishes between mystical experience as such and its other manifestations (“brute force”), such as bodily experiences. If this deduction is correct, the problem of “brute force” applies only to beginners, not advanced students who have already received grace. The secondary manifestations mean unpreparedness for spiritual progress. Although we see some rejection of bodily manifestations and Richard’s use of sensory metaphors, in fact, neither Hilton nor the author of Cloud of Unknowing directly names Richard, so we have no certainty that these are comments on his mystical teachings.13 Moreover, this is not a criticism or rejection of imagery but just of its specific use when connected with senses. The author of Cloud of Unknowing, however, also offers us an explicit rejection of imagination, which seems to refer to Richard (whom he again does not name):
Cloud, ch. 65: In those who are newly turned from the world to devotion, this disobedience of imagination can be clearly recognized when they are praying. For until the time comes when the imagination is to a great extent controlled by the light of grace in the reason—as it is by continual meditation on spiritual matters, such as their own sinfulness, the Passion, the kindness of our Lord God, and many others similar topics—they are quite unable to set aside the strange and alien thoughts, delusions and images that are supplied and imprinted in their minds by the light and ingenuity of imagination. All this disobedience is the punishment for original sin.14
From this statement, we can see that the problems encountered by beginners are considered by the author of Cloud of Unknowing to be the result of original sin. It is probably a refinement of the problems of beginners in the previous passage. The author discusses a particular form of beginner’s problems. He names meditation on spiritual topics, about our sinfulness, the passion, kindness of God, and so on, which he believes are manifestations of uncontrolled imagination. Richard uses the term sympathy for the very ideas that we can classify among these named spiritual topics:
Med. on the pass., p. 97: Dear lady, because the sorrow which you endured at your son’s suffering ought to have been mine… seeing the precious wounds were my own just desert and that you are considerate, obtain just a single one of them for me, one pang in my heard of the same pain, a drop of that lamentation to accompany him with… I have a craving for pain, to implore my lord for a drop of his blood to make my soul bloody with.
There are elements in Richard’s work that the author of Cloud of Unknowing would later describe as incipient expressions of imagination. Of course, we cannot know if the anonymous is commenting on Richard’s doctrine. However, the author of Cloud of Unknowing presents a way of setting aside imagery and distancing himself from metaphor, a significant feature of his doctrine that differs at first glance from Richard’s mystical doctrine.
Richard has been explicit about the imagination on several occasions; each time he has done so, he excludes it from participation in the true spiritual life, at least, he excludes it from partaking in contemplation. According to Richard, there are examples of people who consider themselves saints, even if their mystical life takes place only in the imagination. It is not the true spiritual life (Fire, 2, p. 71).15 It is clear that Richard had to face objections to his mystical doctrine in his time because he defended himself and claimed that his spirituality did not come from the imagination:
Fire: […] for that I have done is not from feigning simulation, and being taken by imagination, as some say of me; and many therewith are beguiled that ween they have that they never received.16
We might think that Richard excludes imagination from participation in contemplation. The lower degrees, especially the meditative degree,17 consist of most precisely this imagery named by the anonymous author.18 It stems from the definition of the meditative degree that Richard gives us. However, Richard admits a considerable variety of individual spiritual experiences, so these imageries can also be very simple and austere, not as rich as the sympathy with Mary. Richard considers these simpler images even more perfect and more typical for people that are more experienced in spiritual life.19 Even in his early references, Richard rejects imagination, although this is again partly to deflect the criticism of his contemporaries. At the very beginning of the Fire of Love, he says that he felt heat on his chest and immediately dismisses the objection that it happened only in his imagination:
Fire, prol., p. 11: More have I marveled than I showed when, forsooth, I first left my heart wax warm, truly, and not in imagination, but as if were burned with sensible fire.20
Richard further rejects the objection that his mystical experience originated in imagination and desire (fleshy love, concupiscencia).21 Then, perhaps the cause of Richard’s rejection of the imagination in his doctrine is not so much the doctrine itself as it is his association of the imagination with corporeality, as we see in this introduction to his most important work.22 Gregory the Great also rejects imagination. According to Gregory, imagination distracts the soul from prayer and distracts it with bodily images. (Homil in Ezech. 1, 8, 13). Gregory divides the mystical way into three degrees. At the first degree, the soul turns inward (se colligat). At the second degree, the soul knows itself (est collecta), and at the third degree, it devotes itself to contemplation (se contemplat). (Homil. In Ezech. 2, 5, 9). Hilton presents a similar progression in his second book, Scale of Perfection. The soul first penetrates itself to know itself. Then the soul recognizes God. The primary condition at the beginning of the journey, according to Gregory, is the ability to withdraw from the images of objects in the world that “are in the heavens and the sky” and to know oneself without these images:
Homil. in Ezech, 2, 5, 9, 5: But no one can turn inward unless he first learns to suppress heavenly and earthly images with the eyes of reason.23
(Translation by LR)
Similarly, the author of Cloud of Unknowing explains in the passage above that spiritual metaphors cannot be interpreted physically and that “up” does not mean “higher” in the physical sense but in the spiritual sense. In this passage, he advises beginners and explains that they must keep a certain distance from metaphors and that this is a faculty of reason. That is some concession to imagination because, for beginners at least, imagination is a part of their spiritual life, that is, if reason interprets metaphors correctly. Gregory, on the other hand, completely rejects images of imagination because, according to him, they cannot capture spiritual objects at all:
Homil. in Ezech, 2, 5, 18, 5: It is not as with corporeal things that we know by imagination and immaterial light cannot be apprehended because while visible light is thus knowable invisible light is impenetrable.24
(Translation by LR)
Richard’s approach to imagination seems to be similarly dismissive to that of Gregory, and spiritual meanings cannot be brought down from heaven to earth because of the incompatibility of physical and spiritual vision.

3. Attempts to Overcome Imaginative Images in English Mysticism

Because all three English authors were aware of the problems associated with imagination, as we have already seen in their mutual discussion and their specific definitions of imagination as mental faculty, we can suppose they all have some way of overcoming imagery or at least keeping some distance from images.

3.1. Overcoming Imagination and Images in the Cloud of Unknowing

At first glance, the author of Cloud of Unknowing demonstrates the most promising technique of detachment from the images that imagination provides. The anonymous author creates a metaphor of a cloud of forgetting, under which the disciple should hide everything that prevents his will from reaching out freely to God. Thus, under this cloud, all desires, thoughts, and even the activity of the soul, especially senses and rational cognition and the action of the imagination, gradually disappear. In my opinion, one of the most complex themes of the Anonymous author’s works and his demands on the student is the last requirement he imposes on them, i.e., to forget oneself, thus to complete this intentional forgetting in a void he calls humble darkness.
In the first chapters of Cloud of Unknowing, the author introduces two negative metaphors—a cloud of unknowing and a cloud of forgetting. The cloud of unknowing stands between man and God, while the cloud of forgetting stands between man and the world. Man stands between the two clouds, while God is above the cloud of unknowing that hides him from human sight. The cloud of unknowing, according to these early chapters, prevents reason from a direct understanding of God; it also prevents perception and feeling:
Cloud, ch. 3, p. 22: For the first time you do it, you will find only a darkness, and as it were a cloud of unknowing, you do not know what, except that you feel in your will a naked purpose towards God. Whatever you do, this darkness and this cloud are between you and your God, and hold your back from seeing him clearly by the light of understanding in your reason and from experiencing him in the sweetness of love in your feelings. And so prepare to remain in this darkness as long as you can…
The cloud of forgetting does not stand between man and the world naturally, as the cloud of forgetting stands between man and God. The author asks the disciple to place it there of his own free will and to hide everything he knows, and eventually himself, under it:
Cloud, ch. 5, p. 26: I am telling you, then, just as this cloud of unknowing is above you, between you and your God, so you will need to put a cloud of forgetting beneath you, between you and everything that was ever created… they should all be hidden in this way under the cloud of forgetting.25
Cloud of forgetting is a negative method of overcoming imagery. What is mysterious is the form of darkness the author is talking about. Is it darkness without imagery? It is perhaps the most plausible way of interpreting it, to which many scholars lean,26 but we should be intrigued by a certain paradoxicality of such a statement. The question is whether the cloud of forgetting is a means of overcoming imagery. Then it is striking that cloud of forgetting is itself an image coming from imagination. In that case, the author of Cloud of Unknowing overcomes imagination and its images precisely through the imagination itself. This method of overcoming imagery seems to be less convincing.27

3.2. Hilton’s Imaginative Meditation

The fundamental question we must ask addresses the role of imagination in mysticism. It seems to be a means of communication, and it also assists in the expression of individual spiritual experiences. Furthermore, the role of imagination is expressed the most clearly by Hilton in Scale of Perfection, where its role is shown in its relation to affectivity. In Richard’s work, the imagery in the meditative degree manifests itself as sympathy, by which he likens himself to Christ and the Virgin Mary. We see this likening to divinity in a more developed form in Hilton since affective devotion is a necessary part of the progression to divinity (Clark 1984, p. 83). This may be surprising, as we know that Hilton warned against imagery. Nevertheless, Hilton does not support the involvement of imagination during all the stages of mystical progress. He defines it as the second stage, while in the first and second stages, the involvement of the imagination is not desirable.28 Hilton divides the mystical journey into three stages, reading (lectio), meditation (meditatio), and prayer (oratio).29 In Hilton’s teaching, the goal of the mystical journey is a renewal of the soul according to the image of the Trinity.30 The soul is renewed gradually during each stage. First, the memory is recovered in the reading stage, then affectivity is recovered in the stage of meditation, and understanding is recovered in the prayer stage. Prayer connects the affective and cognitive parts of the soul (Clark 2009, pp. 26–27).
The reason is active in the initial degree of reading, but affectivity is not involved.31 This first degree belongs to the active life founded on the faculty that Hilton believes all men possess, namely reason. Therefore, all men can attain this first degree.32 The second part of the progression to contemplation involves the renewal and increase in affectivity, but the understanding (feeling) or intellect is irrelevant at this stage.33 According to Hilton, this second and higher degree of contemplation is granted as a grace of the Holy Spirit and cannot be attained by our own will. It is also the stage of meditation, which means knowing one’s soul, destroying sins, and acquiring virtues, and these stages of soul renovation are done through the imagination in meditation. The third kind of contemplation combines knowledge and affectivity. Hilton refers to the attainment of the perfection of both powers—the achievement of the perfect love of God and the perfect understanding of God. The third kind of contemplation involves “seeing the truth itself,” God, and unification with God, being likened to him, or the restoration into the soul’s original form in the image of the Trinity.34
Hilton’s meditative stage resembles Richard’s notion of sympathy, which the author of Cloud of Unknowing criticized; in particular, when Hilton writes about thinking of what it means to be a human, motivated by a desire to understand the humanity of Christ.35 Meditation has two meanings in Hilton’s work. First, it is associated with affectivity, which grows during this stage and concentrates on God. Meditation is thus a practice that encourages affectivity (Cleve 1989, pp. 23–24). The second meaning of meditation is that it helps the soul to know itself (Cleve 1989, pp. 23–24). This is the theme of the first book, Scale of Perfection.36 Imagination is a kind of exercise that the soul needs to pass through in preparation for contemplation, to increase its love or affectivity directed towards God, and to know itself on this journey. In this process, the soul itself becomes more spiritual. The further it is on the path of renewal, the more it becomes aware of its spiritual nature and feels more similar Christ and God:
Devoute Man, XVI, p. 355: […] yet for all this we are unfit and indisposed for to seek and behold spiritual things that are above us, until our souls thought precedent exercise of the imagination, become to be more subtle, or as it were thin, a somewhat spiritual, and withal he became well mortified and settled in virtues by process of time and increase of grace.
Hilton proceeds to distinguish three ways of knowing God; the second way (meditatio) is less ideal than the third way (oratio) but more idea than the first way (lectio):
Scale, II, XI, p. 229: For thou shalt understand that the love of God is in three manner of ways; all of which are good, but each one is better than other. The first cometh only through Faith, in the lowest degree of clarity; and it is good, for it sufficient to salvation. The second is that which a soul feeleth thought faith and imagination of Jesus in His Manhood. This love is better than the first, when the imagination is stirred by grace, for then the spiritual eye is opened in beholding of our Lord’s humility. The third love that a soul feeleth thorough spiritual sight of the Godhead in the humanity, as it be seen here, is the best and most worthy, and that is perfect love. This love a soul feeleth not, until it be reformed in feeling.
I think there are some reasons to believe that the sensory cognition that dominates at the first degree is overcome by Hilton.37 At this first degree, imagination is associated with senses, but this stage ends with the end of the dominance of senses in the soul. Imagination is then the dominant means of knowledge in the second stage, and it is a dispensed grace. At the third degree, the intellect (feeling) dominates and is the perfect way of knowing or understanding. The imaginative way of knowing, however, is not an inappropriate way of knowing the divine; it is just less ideal than knowledge in the intellect:
Scale, III, I, p. 237: One is had principally in imagination, and little in understanding. This knowing is in chosen souls beginning and profiting in grace, who know God, and love Him humanly (not spiritually) with human affections, and with a corporal image of His Humanity, as I have spoken before.
While it seems clear that Hilton overcomes the senses when he proceeds to the second degree, it is less clear if he overcomes the imagination when he moves to the third degree. The true goal of his endeavor is the perfect knowledge in the intellect. The nature of imagination is peculiar, as its purpose lies in assisting the dominant power, the intellect, on the third degree. Thus, the role of imagination in the attainment of knowledge probably does not end even with the progression to intellectual understanding:
Scale, III, I, p. 237: This knowing is good, and is likened to milk, by which they are tenderly nourished as children until they be able to come to the Father’s table and take from His hand substantial bread. Another knowing is principally felt in the understanding, and little in imagination, for the understanding is the lady, and the imagination is the maid, serving the understanding when need is. This knowing is solid bread meet for perfect souls, and is reforming in feeling.
Hilton does not abandon the imagination as he abandoned sense cognition when he moved to the second degree of knowledge, even when the intellect becomes the dominant mode of cognition.

3.3. Richard and God behind the Dark Column

Surprisingly, we can hardly find a better example of the overcoming of imagination and its images elsewhere than in Richard’s Emendatio vitae, probably criticized by other authors (mentioned before) for its excessive use of imagery. Perhaps not surprisingly, as Richard abandons imagery, he begins to express himself through negative metaphors of light and darkness. He also very convincingly preserves God’s unknowability. After Richard passes through the stages of prayer and meditation, in which he expresses himself mainly through metaphors of love and uses sensory metaphors, he abandons these metaphors at the highest stages of contemplation.
The object of contemplation, according to Richard, is eternal truth, for which he uses the metaphor of light. The spiritual progress in contemplation manifests itself in a sharper vision of this truth, which has been blurry for a long time:
Mending of Life, pp. 86–87: By long ghostly travail we should arise to contemplation of heavenly things; and so the ghostly eye is lifted up into the sight of ghostly things. But this sight is not clear, for the while we live here, we see by our own, faith as by a mirror. Though the eye of understanding busy itself for to profit in ghostly sight, yet it may not see that light as it is; but it hath a feeling thereof, since it keepeth and holdeth the savour and the fervour thereof.38
When Richard describes the nature of God, he points to the inadequacy of reason. An adequate description of God’s nature could provide only a reason, but a reason is incapable of achieving divinity. Thus, the only knowledge of his nature is that he is greater than anything we can think of. God can be only loved:
Mending of Life, p. 76: God is of endless might and goodness: His sweetness may not be told nor thought, nor it may not the comprehended nor all received of a creature.39
Richard also uses the metaphor of light and darkness to express God’s unknowability when he writes that God dwells “in the darkness,” so we cannot know him directly:
Mending of Life, p. 88: As when we stand in mirkness we see nothing, so sometime in contemplation, when a soul is lighted with ghostly light, it seeth no light Holy Writ saith of Christ: “Posuit tenebras iatibulum suum”: “Christ hideth Him to us in mirkness, and “He speaketh to us in a cloud ”; and though that light may not be seen here, yet there is felt a delicious thing in that ghostly sight.40
We also see that Richard abandons sensory metaphors at this highest stage of the mystical journey. He associates “seeing” and “light” with the unknowability of God, that is, with the rational part of the soul. He writes that “there is no visible light” in contemplation. This is not a sensory metaphor. The light that illuminates the soul is intellectual, transcending the senses. Richard emphasizes the unknowability of God, “speaking through the dark pillar” so that he does not manifest himself directly and does not show himself quite clearly.
Because Richard abandons all the metaphors he has used before in higher stages of contemplation and engages metaphors of light and darkness, which he has not used until now, to express God’s unknowability and indescribability, we can assume that he is expressing his distrust of imagination by abandoning imaginative images. In the previous stages of prayer and meditation, he used imagery plentifully. So we may conclude that he excludes imagery from contemplation.

4. How Can the Imagination See God?

Richard answers the question of how the image-making soul can preserve God’s unknowability and indescribability—by giving up imaginative images in contemplation. However, we have not yet learned whether and how the imagination could know the divinity. Hilton, on the other hand, gives us a more confident answer.

4.1. Knowledge of God’s Likeness

We have found that, unlike Richard, Hilton does not abandon imagination even in contemplation, assigning imagination the auxiliary role of a maid to the intellect, which dominates knowledge in contemplation. The role of imagination is essential in the preceding stage of meditation, when the soul has already attained some knowledge of God, only less perfect than in contemplation. Hilton does not believe that knowledge without imagination is better than knowledge that is imaginative, which is perhaps why he does not attempt to abandon imagination and its images. The essential point is that the perfection of knowledge depends on the mental potency that is currently dominant, not on the mental potency that is overcome or does not participate in knowledge. So, the perfection of knowledge in the second stage depends on the quality of knowledge that imagination can provide.
The knowledge provided by imagination brings an understanding of God. It enables the soul to know the likeness of God, just as it allows the soul to know itself, the spiritual nature of the soul. So, if the imaginative way of understanding has any limit, it is the recognition of the nature of God, which is unknowable in the second degree through imagination:
Scale, I, II, I, p. 35: Aspiring upward to Jesus Christ, whom yet thou canst never see bodily as He in His Godhead, nor frame any image or likeness of Him in thy imagination; but thou mayest, though devout and continual beholding of the humility of His precious humanity, feel the goodness and the grace of His godhead.41
God remains unknowable and indescribable, at least his very essence. In contrast, according to Hilton, God’s form, the way he shows himself in the imagination, does not preserve God’s unknowability so much, as can be seen from his comparison of imaginative and intellectual knowledge:
Scale, III, II, p. 241: Not as some manner imagine, that the opening of Heaven is as if a soul could see by imagination through the skies above Firmament, how our Lord Jesus sitteth in His Majesty, in a bodily light, as much as un hundred suns. No, it is not so; no, though he see never so light on this manner, verily he seth not the spiritual Heaven… Nevertheless, this kind of sight is tolerable in simple souls that can seek no better for Him that is invisible.
Thus, even according to Hilton, the imagination shows the soul inadequate images of God, but he still values this knowledge. Hilton’s solution to the problems associated with imagination is to separate the knowledge of God’s image and God’s essence. It leads us to the question, does Hilton believe that the intellect can know the nature of God? If the soul could transcend imagination, the intellect could rise to perfect knowledge. However, I believe that imagination will never be overcome or surmounted. Even though the intellect may dominate understanding, the power of the intellect is not strong enough to raise itself to comprehend supernatural knowledge.

4.2. Knowledge of the Divine Is a Natural Knowledge

From Hilton’s description, we can assume that even at the highest degree of contemplation, the imagination assists the intellect. The author of Cloud of Unknowing presents a way that enables the soul to keep its distance from imagery. The author of Cloud of Unknowing keeps warning us that “within” does not mean within oneself, through one’s mind, and that “above” does not mean in the heavens, for as the author writes:
Cloud, ch. 61, p. 88: How could a soul, which by its nature has nothing physical about it, be turned upright in a bodily sense? No, it cannot be so.
The author is not trying to overcome physical obstacles and reach supernatural knowledge. He does not want a man to overcome the soul’s natural ability to create images. However, he understands well that a metaphor, similar to any idea, cannot fully correspond to an object and that it does not capture it completely. I believe we will always create images and imagery, but we will keep our distance from them, based on understanding their spiritual meaning, not on the mere belief that they are true.
The soul can still use imagery and metaphors, but it must interpret them correctly. In this way, it maintains an intellectual distance from them on the degree of natural language. No matter how close the Cloud of Unknowing has moved toward its target, it still has to contend with misconceptions. The entire treatise accompanies an insistent warning of its author against misunderstanding the metaphors. The author probably does not want us to reject imagination as such; he does not say that we must stop creating images anywhere in his writing. Nevertheless, both Cloud of Unknowing and Epistle of Privy Counselling contain several requests to abandon concrete imagery:
Privy Counselling, ch. 1, p. 172: Empty your mind of everything except a naked intent reaching out to God. Don’t clothe this with thoughts of who God is or what he has created. Just be aware that he is as he is.
Denying the adequacy of imagination does not imply that the author rejects the potency of imagination to help our spiritual progress. The author wants us to understand that the ideas of the world, ourselves, and God can be false and that an idea of anything can be inadequate to its object:
Privy Counselling, ch. 6, p. 187: Give God the blind awareness of your being. Forget your education and everything you know. Push it away for now because you’re much better off if you gain the spiritual wisdom and expertise of contemplation. These riches are even more valuable than the gold and silver we collect on earth. By “gold” and “silver” I mean the physical and spiritual knowledge that we gather by reflecting on the traits of God and on those of all created things below, within, and beside us.
The author does not want to translate our expectations about ourselves and God or the world into knowledge about God, so he asks the reader to keep his distance from them and himself by a continuous awareness of the fact he may be wrong.

5. Conclusions

We can summarize that all three English authors are aware of the problems associated with imagination, especially the limitation of spiritual qualities to sensual qualities. They are equally mindful that imagination in the spiritual life is a subject they should have commented on because of the criticism they may have faced in their own time. As we can see, the English authors are not convinced of the adequacy of the simplest solution, the exclusion of imagination from spiritual life. I believe that the closest to this solution is Richard, who, most likely under the influence of Gregory the Great, excludes imagination from contemplation. On the other hand, it does not restrict it in any way to the level of prayer and meditation, although it explicitly rejects imagination as such. Hilton clarifies Richard’s conviction when he explains that imagination increases affectivity, and thus helps the soul to rise to God. I think the author of Cloud of Unknowing is not trying to overcome imagery. Similar to Hilton, the anonymous author puts imagination in a subordinate role to reason or intellect, as he explains that we must interpret spiritual images and metaphors adequately. For both authors, imagery is acceptable at the initial degree, and for beginners in spiritual life, according to Hilton, imagination even participates in contemplation.
Another question is whether it is possible to “see God” in one’s imagination. Hilton approached the closest to an affirmative answer to this question, and according to him, spiritual things can be viewed through imagination, though not perfectly. The author of Cloud of Unknowing also considers imagination a way of learning about spiritual things, which, at least for beginners, can support the understanding of the spiritual meanings of metaphors. Hilton places imaginative cognition between sensory and intellectual knowledge. However, Hilton already considers the imaginative understanding of the divine as a part of contemplation. It is a kind of imaginative contemplation, which is not so perfect as contemplation in the intellect, but it is still a good way of understanding God’s likeness. Hilton points to the fact that the imagination is a mediator of the intellect’s vision, and therefore he calls it a “maid of the intellect”.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Data Availability Statement

Not applicable.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Notes

1
Serm. 277, 14 (PL 38): Oculis enim videmus, non nostris oculis invidemus. Tantum non conemur Deum perducere ad locum, non conemur Deum includere in loco, non conemur Deum per spatial locorum quasi aliqua mole diffundere; non audeamus hoc, non cogitemus. Maneat substantia divinitatis in sua et propria dignitate.
2
On Augustine’s replies to Nebridius, see (Karfíková 2021, pp. 25–38).
3
Ep. 7, 2, 3 (CSEL 44/I, 14–15, 26–29): […] nihil est aliud illa imaginatio, mi Nebridi, quam plaga inflicta per sensus, quibus non, uttuscribis, commemoration quaedam fit, ut talia formentur in anima, sed ipsa huius falsitatis inlatio siue, ut expressius dicatur, inpressio.
4
Aristotle also points out the unreliability of imaginative images in De anima: Moreover, sensations are always true, but imaginings prove for the most part false. Further, it is not when we direct our energies closely to the sensible object, that we say that this object appears to us to be a man, but rather when we do not distinctly perceive it [then the term true or false is applied]. And, as as we said before, visions present themselves even if we have our eyes closed. (De an. III, 2, 428a12, translation by Hicks 1965, p. 125).
5
Com. De anima, 3, 5, 151: […] Illa autem animalia dicit philosophus phantasiam habere, quibus aliquid secundum phantasia mapparet, etiam dum non actusentitur. English translation: […] speaks of those animals having phantasia to whom something appears in virtue of phantasia, even when not actually sensed. (Translation by Pasnau 1999, p. 331).
6
Sensus communis, imaginatio, vis cogitativa, memoria (see STh. I, q. 78, a. 4).
7
Thomas refers to the first and third books of De an. I, 1, 403a8: A further difficulty arises as to whether all attributes of the soul are also shared by that which contains the soul or question which it is indispensable, and yet by no means easy, to decide. It would appear that in most cases soul neither acts nor is acted upon apart from the body: as, e.g., in anger, confidence, desire and sensation general. Thought, if anything, would seem to be peculiar to the soul. Yet, if thought is a sort of imagination, or not independent of imagination, it will follow that even thought cannot be independent of the body. If, then, there be any of the functions or affections of the soul peculiar to it, it will be possible for the soul to be separated from the body: if, on the other hand, there is nothing of the sort peculiar to it, the soul will not be capable of separate existence. (Translation by Hicks 1965, p. 7).
8
Thomas refers to trin. I, 1 (CSEL50, 27): Quorum nonnulli ea quae de corporalibus rebus siue per sensus corporeos expert notauerunt, siue quae natura humani ingenii et diligentiae uiuacitate uel artis adiutorio perceperunt, ad res incorporeas et spiritales transferre conanturut ex his illas metiri atque opinari uelint. English translation: Now one class of such men endeavor to transfer to things incorporeal and spiritual the ideas they have formed, whether through experience of the bodily senses, or by natural human wit and diligent quickness, or by the aid of art, from things corporeal; so as to seek to measure and conceive of the former by the latter. (Translated by Augustine and Dods 1872, p. 1).
9
Expos. super librum Boethii De trinitate, 6, 2: Va ergo possumus in diuinisctsuisu et ymaginatiine sicut piincipiis nostre considerationis set non sicut terminis, ut sulicet iudicemus talia esse diuina quaiia sunt que sensus uel ymaginatio appreendit; dedua autem ad aiiquid est ad illud terrninari, et ideo in diuinis neque ad ymaginationem neque ad sensum debemus dedua, in mathematicis autem ad ymaginationem et non ad sensum, in naturalibus autem etiam ad sensum.
10
On the importance of imagination in the knowledge of God in Thomas see (Bauerschmidt 2009–2010, pp. 169–84).
11
Officium, p. 15: Bot what þatsange es it may noghte be dyscrynede be no bodylylyknes, for it es gnstely and abowne all manere of ymagynacyone and means resone.
12
For example in the Contra amatores mundi we see conection of heat and sweetness (fervor dulcifluo): Laudabilis utique et amabilis, suavis et delectabilis est divina dilectio, que nos miro sapore letificat, et fervor dulcifluo refectos ab omni terrena carnalique cupidine benigne obumrat. (Contra, 2, 153–157, p. 105).
13
A. Baldwin thinks that Hilton directly criticized Richard Rolle for using imagination and sensual metaphors, based on a lack of negative features he considers Richardson’s mysticism a negative one. On the other hand, he considers Hilton’s mysticism positive. Baldwin thinks that Hilton overcomes imagination and therefore considers his mysticism a negative theology (Baldwin 2015, pp. 124–37). Similarly, D. Turner states that the Cloud author criticized Richard in chapter 65 (quoted here). See (Turner 1995, p. 204).
14
D. Turner regards this passage as an explicit criticism of Richard’s mysticism. See (Turner 1995, p. 204).
15
Fire, p. 71: And yet some others that men trowed had been holy had this heat in imagination only. …quandoquidem et alii qui non inequales illi estimabantur, per imaginacionem tantum habent ardorem. (Incendium, p. 236).
16
Fire, p. 134: […] quia non est ex simulacione aut imaginariis quod fecisus cepcionibus, utquidam de me interprebantur; et quibus multi seducuntur, qui se suscepisse suscipati sunt quod nunquam susceperunt. (Incendium, p. 236).
17
Richard describes the stages of the mystical journey in Emendatio vitae. These are the stages of prayer, meditation, and contemplation (see especially the passages in chapter eight, where Richard describes meditation, he describes prayer in chapter seven, and the higher stages of contemplation are described in chapters eleven and twelve).
18
Emendatio, 8, 20–30: Some men’s meditation is of the joy of holy Angels and holy souls that be with Christ; and this [be-]longeth to contemplation. Comp. latin text: Cum enim iam mundum cor habere ceperit, et nulla corpore rei ymago sibi illudere poterit, tunc certe ad alciora admittitur, vt in amore deitatis uehementer glorietur. Quidam eciam meditantur de gloria bonorum angelorum et sanctarum animarum cum Christo exultancium: et hec meditacio ad contemplacionem pertinet. Comp. Mending of Life, p. 52.
19
Emendatio, 8, 30–35: Other mens meditation is of the wretchedness of mankind, how foul it is; and they dispute in their thought how mad those men be that forget heavenly joy for the vanity of this life. Comp. latin text: Alii meditaciones ita disponent ut nichil nisi laudem et desiderium Conditoris sonet, ut ipsum ut possibile sit viatoribus ament. Ad hanc autem meditacionem nemo perunit nisi qui multum in precedentibus exercitatus est. Comp. Mending of Life, pp. 52–53.
20
Fire, prol., p. 11: Admirabar magis quam enuncio quando siquidem sentivi cor meum primitus incalescere, et vere non imaginarie, quasi sensibile igne estuare. (Incendium, prol. p. 145).
21
Fire, p. 11: But when I knew that it was only kindled inwardly from a ghostly cause, and that this burning was nought of fleshly love or concupiscence, in this I conceived it was the gift of my Maker. Comp. latin text: Cumque congnouissem quod ex interior solummodo efferbuisset, et non esset a carne illud incendium amoris, et concupiscencia, in qua continui, quod donum esset Conditoris. (Incendium, p. 145).
22
A. Albin concludes this is based on his broader analysis of Richard’s work. According to Albin, Richard’s notion of imagination is linked to bodily cognition, because what is in the imagination must have previously been perceived through the senses. Therefore, Richard rejects the connection between spirituality and imagination. (See Albin 2015, pp. 184–55).
23
Homil. in Ezech, 2, 5, 9, 5: Sed se ad se nullo modo colligit, nisi prius didicerit terre narumat que caelestium imaginum phantasmata ab oculo mentis compescere.
24
Homil. in Ezech, 2, 5, 18, 5: Nequeemin cum corporearum rerum imaginibus illa infusion incorporeae lucis capitur, quiadum sola uisibila cogitantur, lumen inuisibile ad mentem non admittitur.
25
D. Turner explains that “unknowing” and “forgetting” are active verbal forms, the author of Cloud of Unknowing that it is an activity and the beginner must be active himself because it is not a matter of simply not knowing and overlooking, but an activity of the soul. (See Turner 1995, pp. 195–96).
26
There is another method to be noted, which also was mentioned by the Cloud author. It is a monosyllabic prayer. In the 37th chapter, the Cloud author states that a monosyllabic word conveys the best the urgency and intention of the spirit. The author likens it to a situation when a frightened person shouts “Fire!”, as also this call shows urge and thrill. However, in case of a prayer, a monosyllabic word indicates an affection of the spirit. There is a power of the word that stands between the unknowability of God and the imperfection of a man, this power could make a connection. (Cloud, ch. 39, p. 62: Prayer itself, to put it exactly, is nothing but a devout intention directed towards God for the attainment of good things and the removal of evils.) Nevertheless, it is not clear if such a prayer is meant to be a negative strategy or author’s voluntarism. For the importance of monosyllabic prayer see (Johnson 2011, pp. 349–55). This study supports the idea of a link between a will anda monosyllabic prayer. According to Johnson, the Cloud author bypassed the difference between temporality and eternity by the monosyllabic prayer, as in the moment of such a prayer the presence and the affection of spirit is the closest to eternity, which does not flow but stays still, as for God eternity means presence and just a one single moment. This is the author ’s base for a spiritual practice.
27
There has been certain criticism regarding the contemporary reflection of the works of Hilton, Richard and the Cloud author, regardless if it was in a form of actual critical comments or random comments on sensory perceptions. Richard Rolle’s work seems to be the most problematic one. It was already D. Knowles who doubted the credibility of Richard’s mysticism, mostly because of reference on heat, sweetness and songs (Knowles 1961, p. 54). Later, Turner also criticized Richard’s imagination images, which evoke affectivity to the detriment of intellect. Contrary to that, according to Turner, the Cloud author dealt with imagination much better (Turner 1995, pp. 186–210). A. Minnis came to a similar conclusion as he states that Richard did not succeed to overcome imagination images. Nevertheless, according to him, Hilton was able to overcome imagination. (Minnis 1983). In general, L. Nelstrop focused on the topic of modern approaches to English mysticism. (Nelstrop et al. 2009). For further information o the contemporary discussion see (Rathouzská 2021, pp. 29–38).
28
A. Minnis focused on Hilton’s imagination. According to him, imagination has the most significant position in Hilton’s mysticism in the penuntilate level before reaching the unity with God. Nevertheless, imagination has to be overcome in the last level. In the penuntilate level, imagination is a meditation on Christ’s humanity. According to Minnis, the Hilton’s doctrine puts intellect higher than imagination or will, as far as the knowability of God. In the final level, imagination is a “maid of intellect”. According to Minnis, it is not important how much a soul loves divinity, because if the concept of God is dependent on the imagination more than on the intellect, the soul has not reached the perfect love and contemplation yet. Nevertheless, the imaginative perspective of answeringdivinity is a given mercy and it is a good way how to answer God, although it is considered a tool for beginners. On the second stage, imagination forms human desire and returns it to the original state when it desired God perfectly, it is a way how soul starts to “remember passion”. (see Minnis 1983, pp. 351–59).
29
In Bonaventure’s De triplici via, the mystical path leads through reading (lectio) and meditation (meditatio), prayer (oratio) and contemplation (contemplatio), where the first two stages are stages of purification (purgatio): Sciendum est igitur, quod triplex est modus exercendi se circa hanc triplicem viam, scilicet legendo et meditando, orando et contemplando. (De triplici via, prologus, p. 94) The journey, as with Hilton, culminates in the completion (perfectio). The title of Hilton’s work may come from that. The “path to perfection” would thus be more a “path to completion” or reaching the goal of the journey rather than becoming perfect. But Hilton most likely takes this division from Hugh´ Didascalicon: Quattuor sunt in quibus nunc exercetur vita iustorum et, quasi per quosdam gradus ad futuram perfectionem sublevatur, videlicet lectio sive doctrina, meditatio, oratio, et operatio. Quinta deinde sequitur, contemplatio, in qua, quasi quodam praecedentium fructu, in hac vita etiamquae sit boni operis merces future praegustatur. (Didascalicon, 5, IX, p. 109).
30
Scale, I, I, IV, p. 4: The first consisteth in knowing God, and of spiritual things gotten by reason and discourse, by teaching of men, and by study in holy Scripture, without spiritual gust, or affection, or inward relish felt by them; for they have it not by the special gift of Holy Ghost, as persons truly spiritual have their knowledge, which, therefore, is very tasteful to them in their interior.
31
J. P. H. Clark argues that Hilton recognizes three ways of living the Christian life. He distinguishes between the active life and the contemplative life. That is a common distinction. Hilton also advocates a “mixed life”. This mixed life is an active way of life that includes elements of regular religious exercise and the perfecting of the soul. Nevertheless, Hilton regards the purely contemplative life as a higher and better way of life. However, he encourages mixed life to people who do not live a genuine contemplative life. (Clark 1979, pp. 265–66).
32
Scale, I, I, V, p. 6: The second part of Contemplation lieth principally in affection, without spiritual light in the understanding or sight of spiritual things…
33
Scale, I, I, VIII, pp. 9–10: The third sort, which is as perfect Contemplation as can be had in this life; consisteth both in knowing and affecting; that is, in knowing and perfect loving of God, which is when a man’s soul is first reformed by perfection of virtues to the image of Jesus, and afterwards, when it pleaseth God to visit him, he is taken in from all earthly and fleashy affections, from vain thoughts and imaginings of all bodily creatures… and then by the grace of the Holy Ghost is enlightened, to see by his understanding Truth itself (which is God) and spiritual things, with a soft, sweet, burning love in God, so perfectly that he becometh ravished with His love, and so the soul for the time is become one with God, and conformed to the image of the Trinity.
34
Scale, I, II, II, p. 48: For a man shall not come to the spiritual light in Contemplation of Christ’s Godhead, unless first he be exercised in imagination with bitterness and compassion, and in steadfast thinking of His humanity.
35
Scale, I, II, III, p. 54: But if thou wilt do well, begin a new game and a new travail, and that is, by meditation, to enter within into thy own soul, for so know what it is, and by the knowing thereof to come to the spiritual knowledge of God.
36
Chapter XII also treats the body, Hilton giving as an example St. Paul in Scale, I, XII, p. 18: And so St Paul would forget all bodily things, and even his own body also, that so he might see spiritual things.
37
Scale, II, I, XI, p. 232: But though that this be true that His love in imagination is good; nevertheless a soul should desire to have spiritual love in understanding of the Godhead.
38
The work was originally written in Latin as Emendatio vitae; the Latin text differs considerably from the English. Comp. this motiv in latin text: …quia dum per fidem currimus, per speculum in enigmate uidemus. Si enim oculus intellectualis nititur in lecem spiritualem, lemen illud ut in se est non uidet, sentit tamen se ibi fuisse, dum saporem et feruorem incircumscripti luminis secum retinet. (Emendatio, 12, 80).
39
Comp. latin text: Deus enim infinite magnitudinis et inexcogitabilis bonitatis, unnumerabilis dulcedinis, omni create nature incomprehensibilis, nuncquam a nobis/ita comprehendi poterit, quemadmodum in se eternus existit. (Emendatio, 11, 145).
40
Comp. latin text: Sicut in tenebris stantes nichil cernimus, ita in contemplacione que inuisibiliter animam illuminat, uisibile lumen non uidemus. Ponit itaque Christus tenebras labtibulum suum, et adhuc in columna nubis ad nos loquitur. Sed valde delectabile est quod sentitur. (Emendatio, 12, 90–95).
41
The intellect sees the Godhead as an unchangeable being: See Scale, III, II, p. 238: […] he seeth Him that He is an unchangeable being…

References

  1. Primary Sources

    (Cloud) Anonymous. 2001. Cloud of Unknowing and Other Works. Edited by Anthony C. Spearing. London: Penguin.
    (Privy Counselling) Anoymous. 2009. The Cloud of Unknowing with the Book of Privy Council. Boston, London: Shambhala Publications.
    (Ep.) Augustinus, Epistulae (CSEL 34/1, 13–18 Goldbacher).
    (Serm.) Augustinus, Sermones (PL 38, 1257–1268 Migne).
    (trin.) Augustinus, De trinitate (CSEL 50 Mountain).
    (Homil. in Ezech, 1) Gregory the Great. 1986. Homiliae in Ezechiel. Edited by Ch. Morel. Paris: Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique.
    (Homil. in Ezech, 2) Gregory the Great. 1990. Homiliae in Ezechiel. Edited by Ch. Morel. Paris: Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique.
    (Didascalicon) Hugh of Saint Victor. 1939. Didascalicon: De Studio Legendi. Washington: The Catholic University Press.
    (Contra) Richard Rolle. 1968. Contra amatores mundi of Richard Rolle of Hampole. Edited by Paul D. Theiner. Berkeley: University of California Press.
    (Fire) Richard Rolle. 1914. The Fire of Love, or, Melody of Love; and the Mending of Life, or, Rule of Living. London: Methuen.
    (Incendium) Richard Rolle. 1915. The Incendium Amoris of Richard Rolles of Hampole. Edited by Margaret M. Frances. London: Machester University Press.
    (Med. on the pass.) Richard Rolle. 1988. Meditations on the Passion. In Richard Rolle. The English Writings. Edited by Rosaline S. Allen. New York: Paulist Press, pp. 90–124.
    (Mending of Life) Richard Rolle. 1913. The Mending of Life. Edited by Dundas Hardford. London: H. R. Allenson.
    (Officium) Perry, George. G. 1966. English Prose Treatise of Richard Rolle de Hampole. London: N. Trübner & Co.
    (Emendatio) Richard Rolle. 1995. Emendatio Vitae: Orationes ad Honorem Nominis Ihesu. Edited by Nicolas Watson. Toronto: Pontifical Institute for Mediaeval Studies.
    (Expos. super librum Boethii De trinitate) Thomas Aquinas. 1959. Expositio Super Librum Boethii de Trinitate. Leiden: Brill.
    (Com. De anima) Thomas Aquinas, De anima. (Opera omnia 24, 151).
    (STh.) Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologica (Opera omnia 1, 490).
    (Scale) Walter Hilton. 1908. Scale (or Ladder) of Perfection. Editer by J. B. Dalgairns. London: Art & Book Company Limited.
    (Devoute Man) Walter Hilton. 1908. Treatise Written to a Devout Man. In Scale (or Ladder) of Perfection. Edited by. J. B. Dalgairns. London: Art & Book Company Limited, pp. 315–55.
  2. Secondary Sources

  3. Albin, Andrew. 2015. Listening for canor in Richard Rolle’s Melos amoris. In Voice and Voicelessness in Medieval Europe. Edited by Ruth I. Kleiman. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 184–86. [Google Scholar]
  4. Bauerschmidt, Frederick Christian. 2009–2010. Imagination and Theology in Thomas Aquinas. Louvain Studies 34: 169–84. [Google Scholar]
  5. Baldwin, Anna. 2015. An Introduction to Medieval English Literature: 1300–1485. New York: Palgave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
  6. Augustine, Saint, and Marcus Dods. 1872. The Works of Aurelius Augustine, Bishop of Hippo: A New Translation. Edinburgh: T.&T. Clark. [Google Scholar]
  7. Clark, James H. 1979. Action and Contemplation in Walter Hilton. Downside Review 97: 265–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Clark, James Patrick H. 1984. Walter Hilton and Stimulus amoris. Downside Review 102: 347–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Clark, Patrick M. 2009. ‘Feeling’ in Walter Hilton’s Scale of Perfection. Downside Review 128: 24–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Cleve, Gunnel. 1989. Basic Mystic Themes in Walter Hilton’s Scale of Perfection: Book I. Salburg: Institut Anglistik und Americanistik Univerzität Salzburg. [Google Scholar]
  11. Hicks, Robert D. 1965. Aristotle De Anima. Amsterdam: Adolf M. Hakkert. [Google Scholar]
  12. Hill, Edmund. 1994. The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st Century, III/8: Sermons 273–305A. New York: New City Press. [Google Scholar]
  13. Johnson, Eleanor. 2011. Feeling Time, Will, and Words: Vernacular Devotion in the Cloud of Unknowing. Journal of medieval and Early Modern Studies 41: 349–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  14. Karfíková, Lenka. 2021. Imagination and Memory in Augustine’s Correspondence with Nebridius. In Héritagesplatoniciens et Aristotéliciensdansl’orient et l’OccidentIIe–XVIe Siècles. Scrinium Friburgense 54. Edited by Tiziana Suarez-Nani and Tamar Tsopurashvili. Wiesbaden: Reichert Verlag, pp. 25–38. [Google Scholar]
  15. Knowles, David. 1961. The English Mystical Tradition. New York: Harper. [Google Scholar]
  16. Minnis, Alastair. 1983. Affection and Imagination in “The Cloud of Unknowing“ and Hilton’s “Scale of Perfection”. Traditio 39: 351–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  17. Nelstrop, Luise, Kevin Magill, and Bladley Onishi. 2009. Christian Mysticism: An Introduction to Contemporary Theoretical Approaches. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Limited. [Google Scholar]
  18. Pasnau, Robert. 1999. A Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima’. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
  19. Rathouzská, Lucie. 2021. Imaginative Contemplation in the 14th Century English Mysticism. In The Figurativeness of the Language of Mystical Experience. Edited by Antonio Barnés and Magda Kučerková. Brno: Masaryk University Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. Turner, Denys. 1995. Darkness of God: Negativity in Christian Mysticism. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Rathouzská, L. The Unknowability and Imagination in Mystical Doctrines of the Late Medieval English Mysticism. Religions 2023, 14, 878. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070878

AMA Style

Rathouzská L. The Unknowability and Imagination in Mystical Doctrines of the Late Medieval English Mysticism. Religions. 2023; 14(7):878. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070878

Chicago/Turabian Style

Rathouzská, Lucie. 2023. "The Unknowability and Imagination in Mystical Doctrines of the Late Medieval English Mysticism" Religions 14, no. 7: 878. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070878

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop