Normative Reasons, Epistemic Autonomy, and Accountability to God
Abstract
:1. Introduction
The AOT Dilemma: If the AOT defender adopts anti-realism about normative reasons (subjectivism and constructivism), AOT loses its force. But, if the AOT defender adopts moral realism, they face the same problem as the theist, as normative fact constrains autonomy.
The AOT Dilemma, if correct, poses a serious problem, especially for those AOT defenders who adopt moral realism. So why think the AOT Dilemma is defensible?I accept moral realism yet I believe that God does not exist. I also find it unsatisfying, perhaps even “lame” as Mackie would have it, to posit mysterious, quasi-mystical cognitive faculties that are somehow able to make contact with causally inert moral features of the world and provide us with knowledge of them. The central goal of this book is to defend the plausibility of a robust brand of moral realism without appealing to God or any weird cognitive faculties.
2. Autonomy Objections to Theism
2.1. Divine Command Theory
The fact that any action, φ, is morally wrong is grounded in facts about φ being contrary to facts about God and God’s commands. The obligation and wrongdoing statements of DCT are compatible with, if not consequent of, each other. If one has an obligation to φ, then bringing about φ is morally right or good, while failing to φ is morally wrong.Divine Command Theory (DCT): At least some normative facts—facts about moral obligation—are grounded in facts about God and God’s commands.4
2.2. Two Versions of the Autonomy Objection to Theism
2.2.1. The Infantilizing Argument
2.2.2. The Worship Argument
2.2.3. The Nature of Autonomy in AOT
The truly moral agent is one who wishes to be his own master, not the instrument of some other power, and not to trust the deliverances of some supposed authority, but to work out for themselves the rightness of certain kinds of behavior.
The autonomy objector might agree that the features of personal autonomy are necessary conditions for human autonomy in general, yet insufficient for the infantilizing and worship arguments. A child in Piaget’s second developmental stage can act intentionally, undetermined, and with understanding, for example, that her parent knows more than she does. So, if one is infantilized, it is not for a mere lack of personal autonomy.Personal Autonomy: An agent S has personal autonomy, iff, S’s actions are performed intentionally, with understanding, and without conditions that determine S’s actions.
Epistemic Autonomy: An agent S has epistemic autonomy, iff, S is able to form S’s beliefs by S’s cognitive resources, and S’s actions are performed intentionally, with understanding, and without conditions that determine S’s actions.
2.3. Epistemic Autonomy and Normative Reasons
Accordingly, the explanation of what one ought to do at t supervenes on one’s reasons for and against the available courses of action at t. To seek out an explanation for why one should obey God is to seek out one’s normative reasons for obeying God. When free to do so, one has the following kind of autonomy:Normative Reason: An agent S has a normative reason to φ at time t, iff, some fact about φ (concerning S’s situation at t) plays a particular role in explaining what S ought to do at t.
Accordingly, one is autonomous with respect to obeying God just in case one decides to obey God in light of one’s normative reasons for doing so. One comes to know those reasons through one’s cognitive resources intentionally, with understanding and without determining conditions.Normative Reasons Autonomy: An agent S has normative reason autonomy with respect to φ at time t, iff, S decides to φ at t because S has a normative reason to φ at t, and S comes to know S’s normative reason with Epistemic Autonomy.
Is it really hubris or arrogance or sin on our part to wish for a life where we make our own decisions, where we follow the rules we do because we see the point of them and where we need not crucify our intellects by believing in some transcendent purpose whose very intelligibility is seriously in question? Perhaps by saying this I am only exhibiting my own hubris, my own corruption of soul, but I cannot believe that to ask this question is to exhibit such arrogance.
3. Anti-Realist Models of Normative Reason and Varieties of AOT
3.1. Subjectivism about Normative Reasons Autonomy
Normative Reasons Subjectivism: The fact that an agent S has a normative reason to φ at time t is grounded in facts about S’s desires.
Consequently, one is autonomously accountable to God just in case one decides to obey God because one is in the mental <desiring to obey God>. On SNR-Autonomy, what one ought to do at t supervenes on one’s desire(s) at t. Therefore, one’s normative autonomy can go only where one’s desires allow it.Subjectivist Normative Reasons Autonomy (SNR-Autonomy): An agent S is autonomous with respect to φ at time t, iff, the fact that S has a normative reason to φ at time t is grounded in facts about S’s desires.
A Problem for Subjectivist Normative Reasons Autonomy
3.2. Constructivism about Normative Reasons Autonomy
The constructivist model grounds facts about normative reasons in facts about the rational responses of one or more human beings. In this way, the standards of normative reasons are procedurally self-authenticating.Normative Reasons Constructivism: The fact that an agent S has a normative reason to φ at time t is grounded in facts about the rational evaluation of the attitudes and activities of S or S’s community toward φ at time t.
On CNR-Autonomy, what one ought to do at t supervenes on the rational evaluation of one’s attitudes or those of one’s community at t. This includes whether or not one ought to pursue Epistemic Autonomy.Constructivist Normative Reasons Autonomy: (CNR-Autonomy): An agent S is autonomous with respect to φ at time t, iff, the fact that S has a normative reason to φ at time t is grounded in facts about the rational evaluation of the attitudes and activities of S or S’s community toward φ at time t.
Problems for Constructivist Normative Reasons Autonomy
Therefore, normative reason is constructed. Facts about normative reason are grounded in facts about the value of humanity, and facts about the value of humanity are grounded in facts about our assignment of value regarding our individual sense of identity. However, this makes morality subjective since people have wildly different senses of identity. Think, for example, of the differences between the white nationalist and the individual whose life is rooted in opposition to racism.But part of the normative force of those reasons springs from the value we place on ourselves as human beings who need such identities. In this way, all value depends on the value of humanity; other forms of practical identity matter in part because humanity requires them. Moral identity and the obligations it carries with it are therefore inescapable and pervasive.
Normative truth, according to the constructivist, does not outrun what follows from within the evaluative standpoint, but rather consists in whatever is entailed from within it.
4. The Real Issue: Realism about Normative Reasons
4.1. Moral Realism
Normative Reason Realism: Facts about S’s normative reason to φ at t are (a) grounded in objective, mind-independent facts and (b) apply universally (to rational beings).
Normative reasons, on a realist view, are grounded in normative facts, while on an anti-realist view, they are grounded in procedural facts (constructivism) or desire facts (subjectivism).Normative Reason Anti-Realism: Facts about S’s normative reason to φ at t are not (a) grounded in objective, mind-independent facts and (b) do not apply universally (to rational beings).
4.2. Why Moral Realism Is the Actual Problem
4.2.1. Virtual Reality, the Simulation Hypothesis, and Accountability to God
Setting aside the claim that no qualities can make a being worthy of worship, I will focus on the metaethical theories working behind the scenes in Chalmers’s reasoning.Even if the Abrahamic God exists, with all those godlike qualities of perfection, I will respect, admire, and even be in awe of him, but I won’t feel bound to worship him… I don’t think any qualities can make a being worthy of worship. As a result, we never have good reason to worship any being. No possible being is worthy of worship.
4.2.2. Realism and Normative Constraints, and Normative Reasons Autonomy
5. Conclusions: The Real Dilemma
In explaining the objectivity of morality (moral realism), Walter Sinnott-Armstrong writes:The laws of logic and rationality are normative. They tell us what we ought to do. But no one invented them. If you have excellent evidence for one claim, and this entails a second claim, then you ought to believe that second claim. If you are faced with contradictory propositions, and know that one of them is false, then you must accept the other… If you are an atheist, you’ll deny that God made up such principles. If any principals are objective, these are. So we have here objective, authorless, normative laws.
Consider also how David Enoch explains one’s epistemic access to the correlation between normative truths and normative judgments from a moral realist view:If what makes an aggressive war morally wrong is that it hurts innocent people, then whether it is wrong does not depend on my desires, such as whether I want to harm those people. It also does not depend on my beliefs, such as whether I believe that the war will hurt those people…Thus, atheists and agnostics can hold not only that there are moral facts but also that these moral facts are objective rather than subjective.
Clearly, at least some atheists embrace moral realism.17I argue that the correlation that needs to be explained is not as striking as it seems, and that whatever by way of correlation does need explaining can be explained consistently with Robust Realism, by a godless (and so speculative evolutionary) pre-established harmony kind of explanation.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | It is often overlooked that elsewhere Kant affirms that all moral laws are divine commands. See, Kant ([1788] 2015, p. 129); Hare (2000); and Hare (1992, p. 30). |
2 | To be clear, by ‘autonomy objection,’ some mean debates about treating religious views as irrelevant to issues in moral philosophy. See (MacIntyre 1959, pp. 103–9). Others have in mind the debate about any conflict between the normative value of autonomy and religious ethics, especially divine command theory. I have in mind only the latter. |
3 | |
4 | Adams states DCT with respect to wrongdoing rather than obligation: “[A]n act is wrong if and only if it is contrary to God’s will or commands (assuming God loves us)” (Adams 1987, p. 121). Adams also endorses the stronger modal thesis: necessarily, for any action, a; if a is ethically wrong, then a is contrary to the commands of a loving God. (Ibid., p. 132). For my purposes, I do not need the stronger modal thesis. |
5 | However, the parent/child relationship is not clearly analogous to the God/human relationship. While the parent/child relationship is one of degree where the child develops into an adult and, in some cases, into a parent. The same is not true of the God/human relationship. Although humans mature, they do not develop into anything close to God. Part of what motivates the autonomy argument is the intuition that as children mature into adulthood, they not only search for themselves, but become selves in a way that dissolves the accountability relationship between parent and child. However, if God has legitimate permanent authority, the same is not true of the God/human relationship, and our accountability to God never dissolves. |
6 | It is not clear that Kant is chastising the worship of God, but only the veneration of idols. Still, some take Kant to hold that worshiping God is at odds with human autonomy. |
7 | Notice that Rachel’s objection is not stated in terms of DCT. However, we can understand the normative requirement of worshiping God as a divine command grounded in God’s nature or being. Moreover, as many divine command theorists hold that divine commands are grounded in God’s nature or being, Rachels’s worship argument is a species of the autonomy objection against DCT. |
8 | Nomy Arpaly, for example, untangles eight distinct notions of autonomy commonly conflated in recent contemporary work. See Arpaly (2003, pp. 117–48). |
9 | This is an adaptation of Ralph Wedgwood’s notion of a reason for action. See (Wedgwood 2009). |
10 | Mark Schroeder is the primary subjectivist who rejects this thesis. See (Schroeder 2007). For a subjectivist response to Schroder, see (Sobel 2017, chp. 15). |
11 | This is one reason why social constructivists, such as Copp, hold that normative reasons are morally neutral and “self-grounded” in facts about a society’s nature that is constructed by that society. See (Copp 1995, p. 173). |
12 | This argument is similar to Hegel’s objection that Kant’s notion of autonomous will removes the normative content of practical/normative reason. See (Hegel [1820] 2011, scts. 133–37). |
13 | |
14 | For a brilliant treatment of moral knowledge, see Dallas Willard (2018). |
15 | See also, Shafer-Landau (2003). |
16 | See also, Enoch (2014, pp. 208–21). |
17 | For another example, see FitzPatrick (2008). |
References
- Adams, Robert. 1987. The Virtue of Faith and Other Essays in Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Robert. 1999. Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Arnold, Matthew. 1902. Essays in Criticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. First published 1865. [Google Scholar]
- Arpaly, Nomy. 2003. Unprincipled Virtue: An Inquiry into Moral Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baier, Kurt. 2008. The Meaning of Life. In The Meaning of Life. Edited by Elmer Daniel Klemke and Steven M. Cahn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. First published 1957. [Google Scholar]
- Chalmers, David. 2022. Reality+. New York: W. W. Norton. [Google Scholar]
- Copp, David. 1995. Morality, Normativity, and Society. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dworkin, Gerald. 1988. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Enoch, David. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Enoch, David. 2014. Why I am an Objectivist about Ethics (and Why You Are, Too). In The Ethical Life, 4th ed. Edited by Russ Shafer Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 208–21. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C. Stephen. 2013. God and Moral Obligation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C. Stephen. 2022. Could a Divine-Command Theory of Moral Obligations Justify Horrible Acts? Some Kierkegaardian Reflections. The Monist 105: 388–407. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Evans, C. Stephen. 2023. Living Accountably: Accountability as a Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C. Stephen, and Brandon Rickabaugh. 2022. Living Accountably: Accountability as a Virtue. International Philosophical Quarterly 62: 41–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- FitzPatrick, William Joseph. 2008. Robust Ethical Realism, Non-Naturalism, and Normativity. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 3: 159–205. [Google Scholar]
- Frankfurt, Harry. 1971. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fricker, Elizabeth. 2006. Testimony and Epistemic Autonomy. In The Epistemology of Testimony. Edited by Jenifer Lackey and Ernest Sosa. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 225–50. [Google Scholar]
- Hare, John. 2000. Kant on Recognizing our Duties as God’s Commands. Faith and Philosophy 17: 459–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hare, Richard Mervyn. 1992. The Simple Believer. In Essays on Religion and Education. Reprinted in Richard Mervyn Hare. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2011. Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Translated by H. B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1820. [Google Scholar]
- Huemer, Michael. 2013. An Ontological Proof of Moral Realism. Social Philosophy and Policy 30: 259–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Huemer, Michael. 2021. Groundless Morals. In A Debate on God and Morality. Edited by Adam Lloyd Johnson, William Lane Craig and Erik J. Wielenberg. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1967. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L. A. Shelby-Bigge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. First published 1739. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1996. The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and Edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1797. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1785. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 2015. Critique of Practical Reason. revised edition translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1788. [Google Scholar]
- Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996a. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996b. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kraay, Klaas J., and Chris Dragos. 2013. On Preferring God’s Non-Existence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43: 157–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Le Poidevin, Robin. 1996. Arguing for Atheism: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1959. Difficulties in Christian Belief. London: SCM Press. [Google Scholar]
- Markovits, Julia. 2014. Moral Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Markovits, Julia, and Kenneth Walden. 2021. Kantian Constructivism. In The Routledge Handbook of Practical Reason. Edited by Ruth Chang and Kurt Sylvan. New York: Routledge, pp. 318–35. [Google Scholar]
- Murphy, Mark C. 2001. Natural Law and Practical Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nielson, Kai. 1991. God and the Grounding of Morality. Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nowell-Smith, Patrick. 1999. Morality: Religious and Secular. In Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions. Edited by Eleonore Stump and Michael J. Murray. Malden: Blackwell, pp. 403–11. First published 1961 in The Rationalist Annual. [Google Scholar]
- Penner, Myron. 2015. Personal Anti-Theism and the Meaningful Life Argument. Faith and Philosophy 32: 336–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Piaget, Jean. 1965. The Moral Judgement of the Child. Translated by Marjorie Gabain. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rachels, James. 1971. God and Human Attitudes. Religious Studies 7: 325–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2007. Existentialism Is a Humanism. Translated by Carol Macomber. New Haven: Yale University Press. First published 1946. [Google Scholar]
- Schroeder, Mark. 2007. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2004. What Ever Happened to Good and Evil? Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sidgwick, Henry. 1981. The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. Indianapolis: Hackett. First published 1907. [Google Scholar]
- Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2009. Morality without God? Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sobel, David. 2017. From Valuing to Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sobel, David. 2021. How to Be a Subjectivist. In The Routledge Handbook of Practical Reason. Edited by Ruth Chang and Kurt Sylvan. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Street, Sharon. 2008. Constructivism about Reasons. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics. Edited by Russ Shafer-Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. 3. [Google Scholar]
- Street, Sharon. 2009. In Defense of Future Tuesday Indifference: Ideally Coherent Eccentrics and the Contingency of What Matters. Philosophical Issues 19: 273–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Street, Sharon. 2010. What is Constructivism in Ethics and Metaethics? Philosophy Compass 5: 363–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Street, Sharon. 2016. Objectivity and Truth: You’d Better Rethink It. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics. Edited by Russ Shafer-Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press, vol. 11. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 1991. The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wedgwood, Ralph. 2002. Practical Reasoning as Figuring Out What is Best: Against Constructivism. Topoi 21: 139–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wedgwood, Ralph. 2009. Intrinsic Values and Reasons for Action. Philosophical Issues 19: 321–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wielenberg, Erik J. 2005. Value and Virtue in a Godless Universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University. [Google Scholar]
- Wielenberg, Erik J. 2009. In Defense of Non-Natural, Non-Theistic Moral Realism. Faith and Philosophy 26: 23–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wielenberg, Erik J. 2014. Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Willard, Dallas. 2018. The Disappearance of Moral Knowledge. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Rickabaugh, B. Normative Reasons, Epistemic Autonomy, and Accountability to God. Religions 2023, 14, 662. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14050662
Rickabaugh B. Normative Reasons, Epistemic Autonomy, and Accountability to God. Religions. 2023; 14(5):662. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14050662
Chicago/Turabian StyleRickabaugh, Brandon. 2023. "Normative Reasons, Epistemic Autonomy, and Accountability to God" Religions 14, no. 5: 662. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14050662
APA StyleRickabaugh, B. (2023). Normative Reasons, Epistemic Autonomy, and Accountability to God. Religions, 14(5), 662. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14050662