The Secular Moral Project and the Moral Argument for God: A Brief Synopsis History
Abstract
:1. The Moral Argument for God: A Brief Synopsis
2. The Cultural Processes of Secularization
The Historical Opening for Secular Ethics
… all present issues around secularism and belief are affected by a double historicity, a two-tiered perfecttensedness. On one hand, unbelief and exclusive humanism defined itself in relation to earlier modes of belief, both orthodox theism and enchanted understandings of the world; and this definition remains inseparable from unbelief today. On the other hand, later-arising forms of unbelief, as well as all attempts to redefine and recover belief, define themselves in relation to this first path-breaking humanism of freedom, discipline, and order.(ibid., p. 269)
3. Mill, Sidgwick and Moore
4. John Stuart Mill
5. Henry Sidgwick
It was not until Sidgwick’s Methods, which tried to reconcile these two schools (intuitionism and utilitarianism), that all the characteristics of a modern treatment of ethics were fully and deliberately brought together in a single work. Sidgwick is often described as the last of the classical utilitarian’s. He may with as much accuracy be viewed as the first of the modern moralists.(1997, p. 122)
I do not mean that if we gave up the hope of attaining a practical solution of this fundamental contradiction, through any legitimately obtained conclusion or postulate as to the moral order of the world, it would become reasonable for us to abandon morality altogether: but it would seem necessary to abandon the idea of rationalizing it completely…. If then the reconciliation of duty and self-interest is to be regarded as a hypothesis logically necessary to avoid a fundamental contradiction in one chief department of our thought, it remains to ask how far this necessity constitutes a sufficient reason for accepting this hypothesis. This, however, is a profoundly difficult and controverted question, the discussion of which belongs rather to a treatise on General Philosophy than to a work on the Methods of Ethics: as it could not be satisfactorily answered, without a general examination of the criteria of true and false beliefs.59
6. G.E. Moore
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | (Baggett and Walls 2019, pp. 8–19) Baggett and Walls point out the contributions to moral thinking from Augustine (354–430), Aquinas (1225–1244), Descartes (1596–1650), Pascal (1632–1662), Locke (1632–1704) and Reid (1710–1796) prior to Kant. They summarize the moral arguments for God that Kant put forward in this way. Better than anyone, Kant recognized the power and authority of the moral law. On that foundation he constructed two variants of the moral argument. 1. His argument from grace pertains to whether or not the moral life is possible. Morality requires us to achieve a stand too demanding to meet on our own. Divine assistance is needed to close the resulting gap. So rationality dictates that we postulate God’s existence. 2. Kant’s argument from providence pertains to the aforementioned rational need for happiness and virtue to cohere. Full rational commitment to morality requires that morality is a rationally stable enterprise, which entails the ultimate correspondence between virtue and (both individual and corporate) fulfillment. Without God’s existence there is no particularly good reason to think such correspondence obtains. So rationality dictates the postulation of God’s existence (ibid., p. 33). |
2 | Baggett and Walls, ibid., pp. 66–71. The focus of Balfour’s argument was against ethical naturalism and its inadequacies as contrasted with Theism. C.S. Lewis noted in 1962 that Balfour’s Theism and Humanism strongly influenced him; see the excellent work, Arthur James Balfour and Michael W. Perry, Theism and Humanism: The Book That Influenced C.S. Lewis, New, Enhanced edition. (Balfour and Perry 2000). |
3 | Sorley’s very early critique of the ethics of naturalism is notable. Of the later work of Sorley’s, Baggett and Walls comment that it is “…perhaps the most sophisticated development of the moral argument for God’s existence before the present time”. Ibid., p. 74. |
4 | De Burgh deploys a cumulative case in which he combines the cosmological and teleological argument with the moral argument for God’s existence. See Baggett and Walls. Ibid., p. 133. See also (Sessions 1985). Sessions provides good historical context and analysis for De Burgh’s moral argument. |
5 | Lewis has been the most widely read and influential writer of the moral argument in the 20th and 21st centuries. Mere Christianity continues to gain in popularity. It has sold over 3.5 million copies since the early 2000s. |
6 | Breitenbach is correct in judging the impact of Kant’s moral argument. He observes that “Kant’s argument made an impact on the landscape of moral philosophy by forcing those who came after him to consider what implications atheism would have for the rationality of following the moral law”. Zachary Breitenbach (2021), “Evaluating the Theistic Implications of the Kantian Moral Argument that Postulating God Is Essential to Moral Rationality”, Studies in Christian Ethics 34, no. 2: 149. |
7 | See (Dougherty et al. 2018, p. 447) In this interview Alvin Plantinga states that he thinks the moral argument for God’s existence to be “the most compelling”. |
8 | As Alastair MacIntyre puts the matter, “To be a theist is to understand every particular as, by reason of its finitude and its contingency, pointing towards God….It is to believe that, if we try to understand finite particulars independently of their relationship to God, we are bound to misunderstand them” (MacIntyre 2011, p. 23). |
9 | This author has recently completed a PhD dissertation (2023) entitled A Theistic Critique of Secular Moral Nonnaturalism © that fully critiques the secular moral Platonism of David Enoch, Russ Shafer-Landau, Eric Wielenberg, Michael Huemer and Christopher Kulp. The dissertation also develops a distinctive version of the moral argument for the existence of God. |
10 | For that matter, it could also be polytheistic, or pantheistic, to point out some other options. As Dallas Willard rightly points out, “nonnaturalism has been the rule and not the exception in ethical theory”. (Willard 2018, p. 114). |
11 | Many of the books of these thinkers grew out of a presentation of the Gifford lectures. The Gifford Lectures were established in 1887 to focus on issues related to natural theology. God and the moral order has been a central theme in natural theology. |
12 | The first order moral, ethical and the normative are taken to be roughly equivalent throughout this article. |
13 | (Taylor 2007, p. 25) Taylor takes almost 900 pages to work out this question. |
14 | Taylor also notes the move to atheism by the intermediary stage of deism, ibid., p. 293. |
15 | I am using this as a socio-cultural concept and not a metaphysical possible worlds concept. |
16 | As Taylor describes this, “(the) buffered self is the agent that no longer fears demons, spirits, magic forces”. Ibid., p. 135. See also his discussion on pp. 300–1. |
17 | This “frame” is part of what he terms “secularity 3”, which is “not ususally, or even mainly a set of beliefs which we entertain about our predicament”, but instead “the sensed context in which we develop our beliefs”. p. 549 (emphasis original). |
18 | Taylor refers to this as “one of the great achievements of our civilization, and the charter of modern unbelief”, p. 257. |
19 | Here, Taylor (p. 256) speaks of the “ontic placement” of this moral vision in human nature itself. For his notion of “fullness: see pp. 600–1. |
20 | Taylor summarizes this on p. 305. MacIntyre similarly emphasizes this in his last chapter entitled “Contested Justices, Contested Rationalities” in (MacIntyre 1998). |
21 | Here, Parfit points out that the secular moral project is in its infancy and that Theism has been the natural home of ethics. As Parfit puts things, “Belief in God, or in many gods, prevented the free development of moral reasoning. Disbelief in God, openly admitted by a majority, is a recent event, not yet completed. Because this event is so recent, Non-Religious Ethics is at a very early stage”. Ibid., p. 456. |
22 | All of Mill’s writing can be accessed in 33 volumes; see Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, in 33 vols. | Online Library of Liberty (libertyfund.org, accessed 7 May 2017). |
23 | I have relied heavily in this section on David O. Brink’s thorough work on Mill as well as the excellent work by J.B. Schneewind on Mill and Sidgwick. See David O. Brink, “Mill’s Moral and Political Philosophy”, ed. Edward N. Zalta, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Stanford, CA, Fall 2022) John Stuart Mill, The Basic Writings of John Stuart Mill: On Liberty, The Subjection of Women, and Utilitarianism (NY: Random House, Modern Library, 2002); J.B. Schneewind, Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977). For excellent overviews and analysis, see the two chapters in (Irwin 2011). |
24 | (Brink 2018, p. 3) The three most famous proponents of philosophical radicalism are Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832), John Austin (1790–1859) and Mill’s father, James Mill (1773–1836). |
25 | (Mill 2002). |
26 | |
27 | Linda C. Raeder, John Stuart Mill and the Religion of Humanity (Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press, 2002); see also her summary Linda C. Raeder, “Mill’s Religion of Humanity: Consequences and Implications”, Humanitas 14, no. 2 (Mill 2001), pp. 4–34. Mill describes this religion of humanity as “the sense of unity with mankind, and a deep feeling for the general good, may be cultivated into a sentiment and a principle capable of fulfilling every important function of religion and itself justly entitled to the name” (Mill [1874] 1998, p. 109). |
28 | William Paley, Natural Theology (Miami: HardPress, 2017 [1802]). It should be noted that Paley was not a deist, he was clearly a Theist. |
29 | Mill, Three Essays on Religion, pp. 167, 174. Here Mill critiques and accepts Paley’s argument from design. He argues that knowledge of design is only derived from things we already know as designed. Since we already possess experience of specific designed things, by induction they do serve as evidence for God as a designing intelligence. Schneewind, Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy, p. 151 points out that beyond 1830 or so Paley’s influence begins to wane. |
30 | (Schneewind 1977, p. 177) Schneewind’s summary of Paley is quite useful, ibid, pp. 122–29. As Schneewind points out, Paley’s work was published in 1785 and was used as a textbook and reprinted many times. Bentham’s work on utilitarianism was published in 1789 and William Godwin also published a work in 1793. Neither of these works was as popular as Paley’s, Ibid., p. 127. See a more detailed discussion of this in (Rosen 2005, pp. 131–43). Rosen shows that in England there were many religious or theological utilitarians prior to Paley. |
31 | See a discussion of this in the section entitled, “William Paley as a Utilitarian”, in (Rosen 2005, pp. 131–43). Paley was a hedonist of sorts, but as a theist he placed emphasis on God rather than a strictly natural knowledge of right, wrong, good and evil and consequential good. |
32 | Aileen Fyfe, “The Reception of William Paley’s “Natural Theology” in the University of Cambridge”, The British Journal for the History of Science 30, no. 3 (September 1997): 321–35. Even Darwin was influenced by Paley, see (Thorvaldsen and Øhrstrøm 2013). |
33 | |
34 | Quoted in (Schneewind 1977, p. 178). |
35 | The religious side of Mill is thoroughly documented in Timothy Larsen (2018), John Stuart Mill: A Secular Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press); see also Mill, Three Essays on Religion [Reprint] London, 1874, Prometheus Books, Amherst, NY, 1998. Mill rejected a providential, benevolent deism, p. 242. The only argument that Mill found inductively convincing for God was the argument from design, ibid, p. 174. But God according to Mill was finite as shown by the existence of evil in the world and the constraints of design, pp. 38–39, 177–83. Mill also rejected the notion of miracles, accepting Hume’s argument of unalterable natural law as conclusive, but did hold open the possibility that God could creatively intervene in the world, pp. 233, 244. Hence Mill was a Theist of sorts. |
36 | Frederick Rosen, Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill, p. 131. Rosen lists six thinkers cited by (Crimmins 1998). |
37 | John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. George Sher, 2nd ed. (IN: Hackett, 2001), p. 35. For a careful reconstruction of Mill’s argument and solid criticism of it, see (Brink 2018, pp. 34–39). MacIntyre simply calls Mill’s proof “unimpressive”. He thinks that it flounders on a haziness of the central concept. Alasdair C. MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century, 2nd ed. (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998), pp. 238–40. |
38 | Brink, Ibid., p. 1. |
39 | This work will quote only from the 7th edition of the Methods, unless otherwise noted, as is common among interpreters of Sidgwick’s work. Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. [1907] (London: Macmillan & Co, 1962). The work went through five printings and revisions in Sidgwick’s lifetime. The last two versions were posthumous. This 7th edition also includes all of the prefaces from editions 1–7. This is very helpful for tracing the changes in Sidgwick’s work and thinking. |
40 | (Harrison 1996) This is an excellent review of Sidgwick’s reformist efforts in helping to found a first women’s college near Cambridge, and other practical institutional reform efforts he was involved with. For these things, Harrison says of Sidgwick, “But if conventional answers were insufficient, he needed some kind of different and more theoretical guidance. He needed a theory of the “ought”. He needed a Method of ethics”. p. 427. Harris further describes Sidgwick not only as a reformer but also as a highly scrupulous “resigner”, p. 437. |
41 | Ibid., p. 422. |
42 | |
43 | Note that at this time psychology and sociology are also newly forming disciplines. |
44 | Parfit says of Sidgwick’s Methods that it is the “best book on ethics ever written…. Sidgwick’s book contains the largest number of true and important claims”. On What Matters, vol. 1:xxxiii. |
45 | Hence the plural Methods of Ethics and not the singular Method of Ethics. |
46 | (Sidgwick 1962) As Sidgwick puts it describing his intellectual journey away from Mill’s utilitarianism toward his own formulation of utilitarianism, “I was then a Utilitarian again, but on an Intuitional basis”. Preface to the 6th edition, xx. |
47 | (Sidgwick 1962) See chapter XI entitled “Review of Common Sense”. See especially the conclusion pp. 360–61. |
48 | Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (1988a), “Introduction: The Many Moral Realisms”, in Essays on Moral Realism, ed. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, (Ithaca: Cornell University Press), pp. 1–23. |
49 | See also (Sidgwick et al. 1892; Sidgwick 1879). |
50 | Phillips, Sidgwickian Ethics, pp. 14–15; Crisp, The Cosmos of Duty: Henry Sidgwick’s Methods of Ethics, p. 11, note 18. |
51 | For background to this period and the development of Sidgwick’s view on religion see (Schneewind 1977, pp. 17–40). See also (Tribe 2017). Tribe provides additional useful context and background. The 39 Articles requirement was dropped as an academic requirement in 1871. See also (Medema 2008). |
52 | (Tribe 2017, p. 916) Tribe comments, “The Problem then is that Sidgwick’s ‘crises of faith’ has been assimilated to a narrative of secularization created by intellectuals themselves skeptical of religious faith of any kind; which was certainly not Sidgwick’s own position”. |
53 | I disagree with Parfit who too quickly classes Sidgwick as an atheist, Reasons and Persons, p. 453). |
54 | (Sidgwick and Sidgwick 1906, p. 560) See also Sidgwick’s discussion of freedom and what he terms “the moral government of the world”. (Sidgwick 1962, p. 69). |
55 | (Anthony Skelton 2010) Skelton argues convincingly that Sidgwick’s moral epistemology is intuitionist foundationalism. |
56 | (Sidgwick 1962, p. 498) Sidgwick defines happiness as “desirable consciousness” and universal happiness as “…desirable consciousness or feeling for the innumerable multitude of sentient beings, present and to come”. (Sidgwick 1962, p. 404). |
57 | (Sidgwick 1962, p. 508) Sidgwick repeats this notion of “fundamental contradiction”. |
58 | |
59 | |
60 | In this first edition of the Methods, Sidgwick concludes, “But the Cosmos of Duty is thus really reduced to a Chaos: and the prolonged effort of the human intellect to frame a perfect ideal of rational conduct is seen to have been foredoomed to inevitable failure”. M1, p. 473. See also “Sidgwick’s Pessimism”, Philosophical Quarterly 26, no. 105 (Mackie 1976): pp. 317–27. This passage is quoted in full by Mackie and thoroughly discussed. In some respects Mackie finds in Sidgwick an ally to his own error theory. For a full account see (Mackie 1990). |
61 | I note that a reviewer questioned this assessment that Sidgwick’s requirement of “logical necessity” is taken to be to strong. Indeed, this is the case. The footnote that follows documents this to be case for modern interpreters of Sidgwick. |
62 | |
63 | Baggett and Walls, The Moral Argument: A History; pp. 58–59; Baggett and Walls, God and Cosmos, pp. 243–69. In the first citation see the entire section on Sidgwick; in the second citation see chapter 8 entitled “Moral Rationality” that deals with C.S. Lewis, Sidgwick and Kant. |
64 | (Baggett and Walls 2016, p. 269) In this vein, Bart Schultz (2004) says of Sidgwick that he could not bear the idea that we lived in a universe where “…the wages of virtue might ‘be dust’”. Henry Sidgwick, Eye of the Universe: An Intellectual Biography (New York: Cambridge University Press), p. 15. |
65 | Breitenbach, “Evaluating the Theistic Implications of the Kantian Moral Argument that Postulating God Is Essential to Moral Rationality”, p. 151. |
66 | C.D. Broad describes the Methods as “the best treatise on moral philosophy that has ever been written”. C.D. Broad, Five Types of Ethical Theory (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Tubner, 1930), p. 143; Parfit echoes this stating that the Methods is “the best book on ethics ever written”. Parfit, On What Matters, vol. 1, pxxxiii. Both, however, register the common complaint about its lack of conciseness. |
67 | The words that Sidgwick wanted to have said over his grave were, “Let us commend to the love of God with silent prayer the soul of a sinful man who partly tried to do his duty. It is by his wish that I say over his grave these words and no more”. (Sidgwick and Sidgwick 1906, pp. 598–99). He was instead given the traditional Anglican funeral with all its ritual and pronouncements. Bertrand Russell and others referred to Sidgwick as “old Sidg” and regarded him as a product of a bygone era. They regarded themselves as initiating a new era in thought and ideas. |
68 | Of course, we have the advantage of hindsight in evaluating Sidgwick’s thinking. We can see better where things go, where things end up and from where new things start. I think there are at least two important take aways from Sidgwick’s Methods. First, if moral/ethical debate occurs at the level of what we might call the middle range, the strictly practical range, applied ethics, there will be a great deal of consensus on matters, unless our practicality is informed by radically different metaphysics. Secondly, at some point, all practicality must link up with and be informed by a larger, even Ultimate metaphysics; that is, how all things Ultimately hang together in relation to fundamental ethical principles. It is here where the most substantive and difficult, but also, the most important. debates will be carried out. This is also the level of metaethics. It is here where the “why” and “how” of the moral/ethical is fundamentally grounded and worked out. |
69 | I will be quoting only from this edition of Principia unless otherwise noted. (Moore [1903] 1993) This is the standard work with additional notes and commentary. |
70 | (Baldwin 2003, p. 4) Much of this seems to be due to the detailed discussion of Moore in the works of W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good, ed. Philip Stratton-Lake, New edition. (Oxford, New York: Clarendon Press, 1930); see also W. D. Ross, Foundations of Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1939). |
71 | (Moore 1903) Baldwin also points out the importance of this early article of Moore’s, see Baldwin, ibid. See also Thomas Baldwin’s excellent account of Moore’s early dissertation work and the developmet of his ideas in “George Edward Moore”. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, pp. 1–16. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Summer 2010. |
72 | The Principia cites Sidgwick’s Methods more than any other work. |
73 | Even Rashdall complains in a footnote on the nature of the good. He details the fact that Moore’s way of seeing things is not at all new. In particular he references Plato. See Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil a Treatise on Moral Philosophy, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, Britian, 1907), vol. 1: 135–36. |
74 | Hurka’s exposition of the history and thinking shows many, if not most, of the ideas that Moore develops were put in place by earlier thinkers; especially Sidgwick (Hurka 2003). |
75 | (Eddy 2004) This rhetorical style harkens back to an earlier style of Newton, as opposed to Hume’s or Sidgwick’s style. This style Alasdair MacIntyre refers to as Moore’s “…method of calm assertion”. He continues, “More unwarranted and unwarrantable assertions are perhaps made in Principia Ethica than in any other single book of moral philosophy, but they are made with such well-mannered, although slightly browbeating certitude, that it seems almost gross to disagree. But what then is Moore’s case?” MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century, p. 250. |
76 | The beginnings of analytic philosophy are generally attributed to Gottlieb Frege (1848–1925), Bertrand Russell (1872–1970), G.E. Moore (1873–1958) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). Early on, Moore and Russell were collaboraters but there seems to have been little to no interaction between Frege and Moore, although Moore acknowledged the influence of Wittgenstein; see Moore’s autobiography in (Schlipp 1968a, vol. 1, pp. 33–34). |
77 | It should be noted that Moore does include a discussion of ethical ideals that touches on the concpt of good as an ethical ideal in the final chapter of the Principia. Moore and Baldwin, Principia Ethica, pp. 232–73. |
78 | As Moore states things, he says that “(t)he most important sense of ‘definition’ is that in which a definition states what are the parts which invariably compose a certain whole; and in this sense ‘good’ has no definition because it is simple and has no parts”. (Moore [1903] 1993, p. 61). Given this, it is widely recognized that Moore deploys a highly peculiar notion of the term definition throughout the Principia but also that this strategy of analyzing parts and wholes, today known as mereology, is really the strategy that Moore deploys throughout his work to analyze the concept of good. |
79 | Much more discussion on the subject of moral supervenience can be found in this author’s dissertation (Kratt 2023). |
80 | Willard, I think correctly and succinctly, identifies what Moore meant by the naturalistic fallacy, namely, the mistake of identifying one property with a property that is not identical to it. The open question argument specifies that all correct definitions of good do not create open questions, or a remaining question about goodness not specified in associated non-moral properties. For example, is pleasure good? This is an open question. If pleasure is good, then the question reduces to this—is good (pleasure) good? This open question shows that good is something other than pleasure. Good and pleasure are then not identical. Hence, Moore argued, “Good” is a distinguishable, intrinsic and non-natural property. |
81 | |
82 | For a book length treatment on various aspects of the naturalistic fallacy, see (Sinclair 2019) The issue is still of some philosophical interest. |
83 | (Horgan and Timmons 2006, p. 7) Horgan notes that toward “…the end of the twentieth century, we find that the open question argument is alive and well”. For example, he points to its use in T.M. Scanlon’s “buck passing” account of value. See (Scanlon 1998, pp. 95–100) Susana Nuccetelli and Gary Seay, “What’s Right About the Open Question Argument”, in Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics, ed. Susana Nuccetelli and Gary Seay (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 261–82. (Nuccetelli and Seay 2008). |
84 | (Darwall et al. 1992; Baldwin 2003) For an excellent overview and analysis of Moore, see the section on Moore in Dallas Willard’s, The Disappearance of Moral Knowledge. See also (Soames 2005; Irwin 2011) See also the relevant sections in Alexander Miller, Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, Second edition. (Malden: Polity Press, 2013); Mary Warnock, Ethics Since 1900 (Mount Jackson, VA: Axios Press: Distributed by National Book Network, 2007). |
85 | See also this author’s critical analysis of all these thinkers A Theistic Critique of Secular Moral Nonnaturalism © (2023) PhD dissertation, Liberty University. |
86 | The open question argument is still appealed to as refuting naturalistic forms of reductionism; see for example (Huemer 2008, pp. 67–72) Shafer-Landau defends the open question argument as “relevant”. See also (Shafer-Landau 2005, pp. 57–58). |
87 | See also Nicholas L. Sturgeon (2016) “Naturalism in Ethics”, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (London: Routledge). For a useful exposition of how Moore uses the notion of the naturalistic fallacy see (Gauthier 1967). |
88 | (Irwin 2011, p. 633) Here Irwin makes an important point as it relates to Moore’s open question argument. He observes, “… if the appeal to an open question is legitimate, it shows that Good is not only indefinable, but also inexplicable”. This leaves us effectively with no moral knowledge. See Irwin’s excellent entire discussion. |
89 | The many debates spinning off from Moore’s work can be sampled in (Horgan and Timmons 2006). |
90 | (Warnock 2007). |
91 | (Irwin 2011, pp. 639–41) See also (Moore 1962, p. 98). |
92 | (Moore [1903] 1993, p. 2). Moore stated in the same preface that a rewrite of the entire book was needed but that he was not able to undertake such a task. |
93 | (Schlipp 1968b, 2:582) See both volumes in this series for many well-known critical essays on Moore’s ethics. |
94 | |
95 | Soames provides the most technical and detailed criticism of Moore’s thinking. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century. 1: The Dawn of Analysis: 3–90. |
96 | (Willard 2018, p. 159) Emphasis original. |
97 | (Moore [1903] 1993, p. 199) Emphasis mine. This view is also reaffirmed in Moore’s summary of his views on right conduct, ibid, pp. 229–31. Moore later states, “… an action ought to be done or is our duty, only where it produces more pleasure than any which we could have done instead”. (Moore 2005, p. 15) Emphasis is the author’s. The problems with this again seem obvious. See also ibid, p. 120 for a version of Sidgwick’s dualism of practical reason juggernaut. |
98 | Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil a Treatise on Moral Philosophy, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, Britain, 1907) vii. (Sorley 1918). |
99 | |
100 | |
101 | Ayer (1936), Language, Truth and Logic (New York: Dover Publications) 107. Ayer represents the movement known as logical positivism. Theological propositions are “meaningless” according to Ayer. The term emotivism is used by C.L. Stevenson (1937). By this term, Stevenson meant that ethical propositions expressed emotional attitudes that involved personal influence directed towards ethical matters. C.L. Stevenson (1944), “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms”, Mind 46, no. 181 (1937): 14–31; C.L. Stevenson, Ethics and Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Emotivism is part of a larger turn in ethics that occurred after Moore and is referred to as ethical non-cognitivism. For a good introduction to this, see (Schroeder 2010). |
102 | Stuart Hampshire, “Fallacies in Moral Philosophy”, Mind, 58, no. 232 (October 1949): 466-82; (Firth 1952; Anscombe and Margaret 1958; Hampshire 1949). |
References
- Adam, Lloyd Johnson. 2023. Divine Love Theory: How the Trinity Is the Source and Foundation of Morality. Grand Rapids: Kregel Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Anscombe, Gertude, and Elizabeth Margaret. 1958. Modern Moral Philosophy. The Journal of the Royal Institute of Philosophy 33: 1–19. [Google Scholar]
- Ayer, A. J. 1936. Language, Truth and Logic. New York: Dover Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Baggett, David. 2018. Moral Arguments (Actually R1 to Rn): An Abductive Moral Argument for God. In Two Dozen (or so) Arguments for God: The Plantinga Project. Edited by Trent Dougherty, Jerry L. Walls and Alvin Plantinga. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baggett, David, and Jerry L. Walls. 2011. Good God: The Theistic Foundations of Morality. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baggett, David, and Jerry L. Walls. 2016. God and Cosmos: Moral Truth and Human Meaning. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baggett, David, and Jerry L. Walls. 2019. The Moral Argument: A History. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baggett, David, Gary R. Habermas, and Jerry L. Walls, eds. 2008. C.S. Lewis as Philosopher: Truth, Goodness and Beauty. Downers Grove: IVP Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Baldwin, Thomas. 2003. A Hundred Years of Principia Ethica: Interview with Thomas Baldwin. Florianopolis 2: 3–13. [Google Scholar]
- Baldwin, Thomas. 2010. George Edward Moore. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab., pp. 1–16. [Google Scholar]
- Balfour, Arthur. 1915. Theism and Humanism. London: Hodder and Stoughton. [Google Scholar]
- Balfour, Arthur. 1923. Theism and Thought. London: Hodder and Stoughton. [Google Scholar]
- Balfour, Arthur James, and Michael W. Perry. 2000. Theism and Humanism: The Book That Influenced C.S. Lewis. Seattle: Inkling Books. [Google Scholar]
- Bourget, David, and David J. Chalmers. 2014. What Do Philosophers Believe? Philosophical Studies 170: 465–500. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Breitenbach, Zachary. 2021. Evaluating the Theistic Implications of the Kantian Moral Argument That Postulating God Is Essential to Moral Rationality. Studies in Christian Ethics 34: 143–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brink, David O. 1994. Common Sense and First Principles in Sidgwick’s Methods. Social Philosophy and Policy 11: 179–201. [Google Scholar]
- Brink, David O. 2018. Mill’s Moral and Political Philosophy. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab., pp. 1–55. [Google Scholar]
- Broad, C. D. 1930. Five Types of Ethical Theory. New York: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group. [Google Scholar]
- Carr, Robert. 1962. The Religious Thought of John Stuart Mill: A Study in Reluctant Scepticism. Journal of the History of Ideas 23: 495. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane. 2008. Reasonable Faith: Christian Truth and Apologetics, 3rd ed. Wheaton: Crossway Books. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane, Erik J. Wielenberg, Adam Lloyd Johnson, and J. P. Moreland. 2020. A Debate on God and Morality: What Is the Best Account of Objective Moral Values and Duties? New York: Routledge, pp. 93–114. [Google Scholar]
- Crimmins, J. 1998. Utilitarian’s and Religion. Bristol: Thoemmes Press. [Google Scholar]
- Crisp, Roger. 2015. The Cosmos of Duty: Henry Sidgwick’s Methods of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Darwall, Stephen, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton. 1992. Toward Fin de Siecle Ethics: Some Trends. The Philosophical Review 101: 115. [Google Scholar]
- De Burgh, W. G. 1970. From Morality to Religion. Gifford Lectures 1938. New York: Kennikat Press. First published 1938. [Google Scholar]
- Devigne, Robert. 2006. Reforming Reformed Religion: J. S. Mill’s Critique of the Enlightenment’s Natural Religion. American Political Science Review 100: 15–27. [Google Scholar]
- Dougherty, Trent, Jerry L. Walls, and Alvin Plantinga, eds. 2018. Two Dozen (or So) Arguments for God: The Plantinga Project. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Eddy, M. D. 2004. The Rhetoric and Science of William Paley’s Natural Theology. Literature and Theology 18: 1–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Enoch, David. 2013. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C. Stephen. 2010. Natural Signs and Knowledge of God: A New Look at Theistic Arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C. Stephen. 2014. God and Moral Obligation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, C. Stephen, and Trinity O’Neill. 2021. The Moral Argument. In Contemporary Arguments in Natural Theology: God and Rational Belief. Edited by C. P. Ruloff and Peter Horban. New York: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Ewing, A. C. 1973. Values and Reality: The Philosophical Case for Theism. Hyattsville: Alphaville Books. [Google Scholar]
- Firth, Roderick. 1952. Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12: 317. [Google Scholar]
- Frankena, William K. 1950. Some Arguments for Non-Naturalism About Intrinsic Value. Philosophical Studies 1: 56–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fyfe, Aileen. 1997. The Reception of William Paley’s ‘Natural Theology’ in the University of Cambridge. The British Journal for the History of Science 30: 321–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Gauthier, David P. 1967. Moore’s Naturalistic Fallacy. American Philosophical Quarterly 4: 315–20. [Google Scholar]
- Geach, P. T. 1956. Good and Evil. Analysis 17: 33–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hampshire, Stuart. 1949. Fallacies in Moral Philosophy. Mind 58: 466–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harrison, Ross. 1996. Cambridge Philosophers VI: Henry Sidgwick. Philosophy 71: 423–38. [Google Scholar]
- Holley, David M. 2002. Sidgwick’s Problem. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5: 45–65. [Google Scholar]
- Horgan, Terry, and Mark Timmons, eds. 2006. Metaethics after Moore. New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Huemer, Michael. 2008. Ethical Intuitionism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1984. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Ernest C. Mossner. New York: Penguin Books. First published 1739. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 1998. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, the Posthumous Essays, of the Immortality of the Soul, and of Suicide, from an Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding of Miracles, 2nd ed. Edited by Richard H. Popkin. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. First published 1779. [Google Scholar]
- Hurka, Thomas. 2003. Moore in the Middle. Ethics 113: 599–628. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Irwin, Terence. 2011. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study. Vol. 3: From Kant to Rawls. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jakobsen, Martin. 2020. Moral Realism and the Existence of God: Improving Parfit’s Metaethics. Leuven and Paris: Peeters. [Google Scholar]
- Jordan, Matthew Carey. 2011. Some Metaethical Desiderata and the Conceptual Resources of Theism. Sophia 50: 39–55. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 2012. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Revised ed. Edited by Jens Timmermann. Translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1785. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 2015. Critique of Practical Reason, Revised ed. Translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1788. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 2017. The Metaphysics of Morals, 2nd ed. Edited by Denis Lara. Translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1797. [Google Scholar]
- Kratt, Dale E. 2023. A Theistic Critique of Secular Moral Nonnaturalism. Ph.D. dissertation, Liberty University, Lynchburg, VA, USA. [Google Scholar]
- Kulp, Christopher B. 2017. Knowing Moral Truth: A Theory of Metaethics and Moral Knowledge. New York: Lexington Books. [Google Scholar]
- Kulp, Christopher B. 2019. Metaphysics of Morality. Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Larsen, Timothy. 2018. John Stuart Mill: A Secular Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, C. S. 1978. The Abolition of Man. New York: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, C. S. 2001. Mere Christianity: A Revised and Amplified Edition, with a New Introduction. San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco. [Google Scholar]
- Linville, Mark D. 2012. The Moral Argument. In The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Edited by William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 391–448. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair C. 1998. A Short History of Ethics: A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the Twentieth Century, 2nd ed. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair C. 2011. On Being A Theistic Philosopher in a Secularized Culture. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 84: 23–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mackie, J. L. 1976. Sidgwick’s Pessimism. Philosophical Quarterly 26: 317–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mackie, J. L. 1990. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Matthews, W. R. 1947. God in Christian Thought and Experience. London: James Nisbet. [Google Scholar]
- Medema, Steven G. 2008. ‘Losing My Religion’: Sidgwick, Theism, and the Struggle for Utilitarian Ethics in Economic Analysis. History of Political Economy, Annual Supplement 40: 189–211. [Google Scholar]
- Miller, Alexander. 2013. Contemporary Metaethics: An Introduction, 2nd ed. Malden: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, John Stuart. 1998. Three Essays on Religion. Amherst: Prometheus Books. First published 1874. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, John Stuart. 2001. Utilitarianism, 2nd ed.Edited by George Sher. Chandigarh: Hackett. [Google Scholar]
- Mill, John Stuart. 2002. The Basic Writings of John Stuart Mill: On Liberty, The Subjection of Women, and Utilitarianism. New York: Random House, Modern Library. [Google Scholar]
- Mitchell, Basil. 1967. Law, Morality, and Religion in a Secular Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mitchell, Basil. 2000. Morality, Religious and Secular: The Dilemma of the Traditional Conscience. New York: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moore, G. E. 1903. The Refutation of Idealism. Mind 12: 433–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Moore, G. E. 1962. Is Goodness a Quality? In Philosophical Papers. New York: Collier Books, pp. 89–100. [Google Scholar]
- Moore, G. E. 1993. Principia Ethica, Rev. ed. with Pref. to the 2nd ed. and Other Papers. Edited by Thomas Baldwin. New York: Cambridge University Press. First published 1903. [Google Scholar]
- Moore, G. E. 2005. Ethics: The Nature of Moral Philosophy. Edited by William H. Shaw. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, James Porter, and Scott B. Rae. 2000. Body & Soul: Human Nature & the Crisis in Ethics. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moreland, J. P. 2009. The Recalcitrant Imago Dei: Human Persons and the Failure of Naturalism. London: SCM Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nuccetelli, Susana, and Gary Seay. 2008. What’s Right About the Open Question Argument. In Themes from G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics. Edited by Susana Nuccetelli and Gary Seay. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 261–82. [Google Scholar]
- Owen, H. P. 1965. The Moral Argument for Christian Theism. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Paley, William. 2017. Natural Theology. Miami: HardPress. First published 1802. [Google Scholar]
- Paley, William. 2017. Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy. Miami: HardPress. First published 1785. [Google Scholar]
- Parfit, Derek. 1987. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Parfit, Derek. 2011. On What Matters. 3 vols. The Berkeley Tanner Lectures. New York: Oxford University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Parrish, Stephen E. 2019. Atheism?: A Critical Analysis. Eugene: Wipf & Stock. [Google Scholar]
- Parrish, Stephen. The Nature of Moral Necessity, forthcoming.
- Phillips, David. 2011. Sidgwickian Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Prichard, H. A. 1912. Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake? Mind, New Series 21: 21–37. [Google Scholar]
- Raeder, Linda C. 2001. Mill’s Religion of Humanity: Consequences and Implications. Humanitas 14: 4–34. [Google Scholar]
- Raeder, Linda C. 2002. John Stuart Mill and the Religion of Humanity. Columbia: University of Missouri Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rashdall, Hastings. 1907. The Theory of Good and Evil: A Treatise on Moral Philosophy. vols. 1 and 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Regan, Donald H. 2003. How to Be a Moorean. Ethics 113: 651–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ritchie, Angus. 2012. From Morality to Metaphysics: The Theistic Implications of Our Ethical Commitments. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rosen, Frederick. 2005. Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good, New edition. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake. Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, W. D. 1939. Foundations of Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. 1988a. Introduction: The Many Moral Realisms. In Essays on Moral Realism. Edited by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 1–23. [Google Scholar]
- Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey, ed. 1988b. Essays on Moral Realism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schlipp, Paul Arthur. 1968a. The Philosophy of G.E. Moore, 3rd ed. The Library of Living Philosophers. London: Cambridge University Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Schlipp, Paul Arthur. 1968b. The Philosophy of G.E. Moore, 3rd ed. The Library of Living Philosophers. London: Cambridge University Press, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Schneewind, J. B. 1977. Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schroeder, Mark Andrew. 2010. Noncognitivism in Ethics. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Schultz, Bart. 2004. Henry Sidgwick, Eye of the Universe: An Intellectual Biography. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sennett, James F., and Douglas R. Groothuis, eds. 2005. In Defense of Natural Theology: A Post-Humean Assessment. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sessions, William Lad. 1985. A New Look at Moral Arguments for Theism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 18: 51–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Settanni, Harry. 1991. The Probabilist Theism of John Stuart Mill. New York: Peter Lang Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2005. Moral Realism: A Defense. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sidgwick, E. M, and A. Sidgwick. 1906. Henry Sidgwick: A Memoir. London: Macmillan & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Sidgwick, Henry. 1879. The Establishment of Ethical First Principles. Mind 13: 106–11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sidgwick, Henry. 1962. The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. London: Macmillan & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Sidgwick, Henry, J. H. Muirhead, G. F. Stout, and S. Alexander. 1892. Symposium: Is the Distinction between ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’ Ultimate and Irreducible? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 2: 88–107. [Google Scholar]
- Sinclair, Neil, ed. 2019. The Naturalistic Fallacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Skelton, Anthony. 2010. Henry Sidgwick’s Moral Epistemology. Journal of the History of Philosophy 48: 491–519. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Soames, Scott. 2005. Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century. 1: The Dawn of Analysis. Princeton Paperbacks. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sorley, W. R. 1904. On The Ethics of Naturalism. Shaw Fellowship Lectures 1884. London: William Blackwood and Sons. [Google Scholar]
- Sorley, W. R. 1918. Moral Values and the Idea of God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sorley, William. 1905. The Method of a Metaphysic of Ethics. The Philosophical Review 14: 521–634. [Google Scholar]
- Sorley, W. R. 2015. On The Ethics of Naturalism, Shaw Fellowship Lectures. London: William Blackwood and Sons. First published 1884. [Google Scholar]
- Stevenson, Charles Leslie. 1937. The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms. Mind 46: 14–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stevenson, C. L. 1944. Ethics and Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sturgeon, Nicholas L. 2003. Moore on Ethical Naturalism. Ethics 113: 528–56. [Google Scholar]
- Sturgeon, Nicholas L. 2016. Naturalism in Ethics. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, A. E. 1930. The Faith of a Moralist. London: Macmillan & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 2007. A Secular Age. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Thorvaldsen, Steinar, and Peter Øhrstrøm. 2013. Darwin’s Perplexing Paradox: Intelligent Design in Nature. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 56: 78–98. [Google Scholar] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Tribe, Keith. 2017. Henry Sidgwick, Moral Order, and Utilitarianism. The European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 24: 907–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tucker, Miles. 2018. Simply Good: A Defence of the Principia. Utilitas 30: 253–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Warnock, Mary. 2007. Ethics Since 1900. Mount Jackson: Axios Press, Distributed by National Book Network. [Google Scholar]
- Webb, Clement C. J. 1918. God and Personality. New York: Macmillan & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Wielenberg, Erik J. 2014. Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Willard, Dallas. 2011. Naturalism’s Incapacity to Capture the Good Will. In The Nature of Nature: Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science. Edited by Bruce Gordon and William A. Dembski. Wilmington: ISI Books, pp. 865–78. [Google Scholar]
- Willard, Dallas. 2018. The Disappearance of Moral Knowledge. Edited by Gregg Ten Elshof, Steven L. Porter and Aaron Preston. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kratt, D.E. The Secular Moral Project and the Moral Argument for God: A Brief Synopsis History. Religions 2023, 14, 982. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14080982
Kratt DE. The Secular Moral Project and the Moral Argument for God: A Brief Synopsis History. Religions. 2023; 14(8):982. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14080982
Chicago/Turabian StyleKratt, Dale Eugene. 2023. "The Secular Moral Project and the Moral Argument for God: A Brief Synopsis History" Religions 14, no. 8: 982. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14080982
APA StyleKratt, D. E. (2023). The Secular Moral Project and the Moral Argument for God: A Brief Synopsis History. Religions, 14(8), 982. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14080982