The introjection of literal idolatry is a defining trait of the modern social imaginary, especially given the unnatural demand for hierarchy and its use of religion and violence to curtail imaginative explorations of faith that nonetheless persist in humans.
3.1. The Modern Development of the Social Imaginary
In an ideal world, collective representations provide linguistic portals that empower people to responsibly and creatively speak forth descriptive propositions that articulate their felt awareness of emergent realities. Collective representations would serve as part of the informing echo that shaped mind and nature simultaneously. Such an idealized understanding would follow Bateson’s argument that culture and nature relate through a stochastic process that requires a two-pronged standard to allow change.
Bateson (
2002) found that most cultural institutions rely on this process of flexible, adaptive stability. Recalling his work as an anthropologist, Bateson described an Australian tribe whose social organization and ideas about nature are
abductively related. This means that their ideas about nature support, and are supported by, their ideas about society. Thus, individuals in the tribe live, “as all human beings must, in an enormously complex network of mutually supporting presuppositions” (p. 134). One example of how this works in our contemporary society occurs when someone attempts to justify economic or political inequality by claiming that “survival of the fittest” is “only natural”. So doing appeals to a mistaken conventional interpretation of nature that supports a harmful social order without examining how nature exists as a collaborative balance.
This complex network of presuppositions at the social level corresponds to the unthought character level of “habit” in Ricoeur’s narrative identity at the individual level. A culture has a characteristic set of capacities that it has developed as valuable or desirable. Portions of experience that are less frequently explored become dormant and eventually associated with unknown realities. At a cultural level,
Bateson (
2002) finds that those presuppositions that support conventional values create the conditions of epistemology. These unthought presuppositions determine which sensory experiences are perceptible in consciousness and subsequently imagined as true. Collective representations provide these presuppositions in the account of literal idolatry offered above. They weaken our immediate and intuitive felt sense of reality. When epistemology becomes a cultural language-based substitute for felt experience, it supplants the more accurate dialectic of expression and experience that Gendlin described. It leads to thinking we can know the truth of something through exclusively verbal formulations.
The resulting situation is difficult to change, because altering a cultural epistemology requires “shifting our whole system of abductions”, with the understanding that an abduction is a “double or multiple description of some object or event or sequence” (
Bateson 2002, p. 134). Instead of a thoughtful correction to an abductive system of presuppositions, a society dominated by literal idolatry tends to argue about what things are called. These arguments provide the illusion of change but preserve the system of abductions and presuppositions. Collective representations remain invisible influences, the unknowable foundation of what we call knowledge.
In the West, the most recent epistemological change occurred in the shift to the modern from the medieval system of abductions. Based on his understanding of language and culture,
Barfield (
1988) argued that this transition coincided with an idolatrous mindset. He depicted the transition from the medieval to the modern in terms of a cultural shift from a
participatory into a
perspectival mode of experience. People shifted from
living in to
looking at the world. He wrote, “Before the scientific revolution the world was more like a garment [people] wore about them than a stage on which they moved. In such a world the convention of perspective was unnecessary” (p. 94) because “they felt themselves and the objects around them and the words that expressed those objects, immersed together in something like a clear lake of …meaning” (p. 95). Barfield’s “garment” and immersion in a “clear lake of meaning” invite us to think of a world in which more forms of coherence were always already given, rather than needing to be attained. Using Ricoeur’s terms, the imagination connected language and the senses, while collective representations (such as archetypes) opened a wider range of known realities.
The demand for self-identity and complete coherence becomes comprehensible only after a shift from a
participatory (where these would have been presupposed) to a
perspectival mode of experience. Barfield is not alone in identifying this shift and its consequences with reference to religion. More recently, Charles
Taylor (
2007) described this as a transition from a society “in which it was virtually impossible not to believe in God to one in which faith, even for the staunchest believer, is one human possibility among others” (p. 3). Taylor used the term “disembedding” to describe how the modern world was attained at the expense of the kind of coherence that naturally occurs when immersed in experiences. Instead of cohering, the individual, social, and cosmic worlds began to pull apart (pp. 146–58).
One result of this was gaining a “buffered self” that lets people develop greater “confidence in [their] own moral ordering at the expense of a self that was porous and vulnerable to a world of spirits and powers” (p. 27). In addition to an increased level of psychological or spiritual armoring, buffering led to the disconnection of the self from the world of sensory experience and the creative imagination. A buffered self, shielded from the felt experience of participation, is then primed to inhabit the perspectival mode of experience that Barfield described. The consequence of the armoring not only led to a sense of heightened individual responsibility for moral ordering (including coherence and self-identity), but also to a world in which “subjects” interacted with “objects”. Such a shift also parallels what Bennett would identify as an increasing emphasis on causality instead of a co-emergent world of distributed agency and expansive origins.
Understood as a shift in how narrative identities are constructed, the process of disembedding becomes the way that the ongoing truth of descriptive propositions are exclusively measured by one form of verbal reasoning. Following Gendlin, an over reliance on verbal reasoning leads people to neglect imagined and felt connections to others and the self. Consequently, truth is reduced to the level of flat, unchanging assertions. Following Taylor, this shift in abductive presuppositions was experienced as increasing disconnection. It resulted in a contextual reality that no longer provided an adequate foundation for identity. Bridging this gap was the growing sense of individual causal efficacy, exhibiting an abstract moral determination anchored in the isolating and merely literal world. This generated a provisional, perhaps incoherent, sense of character. More options at a conceptual level without reference to felt experience meant that less was
given at what Ricoeur considered the “lower level” where
idem and
ipse become indistinguishable. Instead, as the options for what was
chosen multiplied, individuals needed to exert far more effort to retain a stable sense of narrative identity. As a result, “often we treat ourselves as objects. Working and social life require this objectification; our very freedom depends on these social regularities which give us a routine existence. And so we create ourselves and in ourselves the conditions of validity of the concepts of modern psychology. These concepts are adapted to the man who adapts himself” (
Ricoeur 1986, p. 101). The objectification of the self is a symptom of the perspectival psychology of the modern social imaginary.
Recall that, for Ricoeur, the imagination synthesized and connected the finite and limited dimension of sensory experience with the infinite and abstract tool of language. This allowed people to undergo, but not to know, a range of ineffable experiences. If cultures can be said to have certain character traits or habits, a set of values and presuppositions perpetuated through ways that language frames experience, then, using an abductive model of reasoning, they would also have a social imaginary. The social imaginary would provide a storehouse of language that would make more or less nuanced experiences available. In the wake of modernity, the social imaginary and the collective representations it housed became a functional substitute for Barfield’s clear lake of meaning. This difference is important because the modern social imaginary largely promotes values inconsistent with natural processes of change. These replaced spontaneous experiences of the imagination that connect words to feelings, leading to experimentation and growth.
Taylor (
2007) uses the term “social imaginary” in this way, and it is telling that his descriptions of the foundation of the social imaginary are neither natural nor numinous, the primary paths toward feeling connections. He ventured that the web of commonalities that comprise a social imaginary includes how people “imagine their social existence, how they fit together with others, how things go on between them and their fellows, the expectations which are normally met, and the deeper normative notions and images which underlie these expectations” (p. 171). The focus of the imagination no longer relates to sensory experiences, but to presumptions about other people’s literal thoughts and judgments. The social imaginary fosters lateral connections and remains disconnected (disembedded) from direct experiences. As its primarily verbal and conceptual forms of identification became increasingly prominent, it offered a widespread alternative to the kinds of natural growth and narrative identity outlined by Bateson and Ricoeur.
The modern Western social imaginary also developed its own process of narrative identity, which Joseph
Campbell (
2008) called the “journey of the hero”. This narrative structure interpreted past cultural myths and created present day stories that emphasized and idealized the often violent events of an individual battling against adversarial forces through a profusion of collective representations. This new narrative structure was consistent with the now buffered, disconnected, and isolated “self” that no longer could presuppose meaningful and harmonious connections that would develop through a deepened sense of character. By using words and suggesting narratives that framed the world as adversarial, modern individuals were increasingly driven to focus on the shallow and uncertain guesses about the thoughts of what others think. It became less likely that people would want to question these underlying presuppositions because such questions would risk ostracization and isolation. Struggle, victory, and even loss were all preferable to the prospect of being outside society altogether.
3.2. How Arche and Hierarchy Structure the Modern Western Social Imaginary
The disconnection from a felt sense of reality skewed the imagination toward merely verbal or conceptual fantasies anchored in social conformity. Character originally bore the imprint of a person’s unique preferences and convictions as they developed capacities through a stochastic process that resulted in an expanded narrative identity. Eventually, these reduced to what the social imaginary found acceptable. The social imaginary in this way began to supplant, rather than supplement, genuine individual identities until only collective representations remained. The unthinkable no longer provided a portal to the imagination: it became synonymous with the impossible. Those who succeeded at embracing and embodying the standard of complete coherence and total self-identity became more similar to objects whose essence and value could be quickly ascertained and extracted, i.e., they became nominalizable. Self-definition conformed to given essentialized collective representations that lacked individuality. Individuality was expressed by choosing among unimaginative options. Character became measured by how well one conformed to external expectations. Performing roles required an exhausting amount of effort. It became difficult to recall the self’s innate potential to emerge in imaginative explication.
The structure of the social imagination became increasingly distanced from the nature-based mirror of collaborative flourishing that Bateson depicted. Hierarchy replaced harmony, as dominator models of relating self and world (
Eisler 2019) began to structure civilization. It ordered society based on rigid binaries anchored in the use of fear and violence. The body (the feeling-based anchor to the sensory world and qualitative experiences) was often devalued so that the mind (the gateway to the literal world of language and concepts) could be glorified. Feelings were neglected, including the natural feelings of pleasure and joy that came in response to truthful and creative expressions. This limited the ideal functioning of an
ipse identity, which increasingly was reduced to searching through distorted collective representations in the social imaginary. Rather than curiosity in partnership with the world, societies and people became ruled by the potential of a dominator’s way of relating to the internal and external world. Life was experienced as competitive rather than collaborative. The foundational binaries became presuppositions that replaced pre-existing relational possibilities (
Eisler 2019). This resulted in the positive valuation of exerting violent power as a forceful way of altering one’s self and others’ (
Eisler 2019;
Jantzen 1998).
If life is relational, as Bateson’s model would suggest, then becoming disembedded and disconnected from relationships would lead to being preoccupied with death. Grace
Jantzen (
1998) argued that the social imaginary that grounds Western civilization “has had both a fascination with and dread of death”, as is shown in “its continuous involvement with war” (p. 129). This can, perhaps, be understood as a cultural character trait. Ricoeur alluded to the fact that narrative identities were not exclusive to individuals, hinting that the oscillation between
ipse and
idem also occurs in groups of humans in ways that span generations. Similar to Campbell’s journey of the hero, individual stories that are told (including religious myths, secular histories, and contemporary entertainment) continuously resupply collective representations useful to instill the conventional values and models that an individual’s
ipse finds as points of identification. These reinforce the seeming inevitability of the social order as a “necessary evil”. It becomes more difficult to imagine alternatives.
In addition to their fixation on death, Jantzen found that overarching cultural narratives that arc through the imaginary—even when they conflict at an ipse level—nonetheless often have shared assumptions at the idem level. She identifies some of these narrative assumptions of the Western imaginary: “assumptions of progress, of the worth of rationality understood in terms of objectivity and universality, and of the dignity and value of the individual and of freedom. It is within this framework that thought in the west proceeds” (p. 128). Jantzen’s target is not these values, but the ways that progress, rationality, and individuality serve as presuppositions that limit alternatives (such as contentedness, imagination, and community). To demonstrate how ostensible opponents share presuppositions, Jantzen described how contemporary conflicts between science and religion fail to move forward. Both scientists and fundamentalists largely agree that reality involves progress, objective rationality, and individual freedom (rather than alternatives). They only disagree about what the terms mean rather than exploring how science or religion could be thought of otherwise.
This “idem” level agreement of a social imaginary reduces both the conceptual availability of potential alternatives as well as the ability to assess reality in a way that can encompass multiple perspectives. For example, many social imaginaries have historically rejected the belief that women and children should be treated with respect. Often, those who asserted that all persons have dignity were dismissed as being “irrational” or as “irreligious” depending on the audience. Resolving a problem requires more than simply shifting debates of whether reason or religion is more true. It is not sufficient to value only subjective or only communal standards. The correct path forward requires forming descriptive propositions that avoid valuing only one side of a binary rather than a relationship between complementary poles. The best way places potential truths into conversation.
We are trained to evaluate the ongoing truth of a descriptive proposition with an exclusive focus on verbal formulas. Thus, we sometimes overlook that loud and sometimes violent disagreements actually protect the same core presuppositions. Following the tradition of the Anglo-American philosophy of religion, but largely responsive to the historical thrust of Christian theological development, Jantzen called merely verbal formulas “justified true beliefs”. She argued that “the increased emphasis on beliefs is itself a consequence of modernity and the privatization of religion (p. 20)”. This insight anticipated much of what Taylor described in The Secular Age. Such rationally articulated that beliefs provide a verbal gateway into the social imaginary. The status of what makes beliefs “justified” is necessarily put in relation to that particular imaginary rather than a more holistic or personally sensed reality.
Put back into Ricoeur’s terminology, both the “belief” and the “justification” relate wholly to the infinite, abstract, and conceptual pole of language rather than to any grounding, finite feeling of sensory experience. It presupposes and thus uses only one portion of what could be known (language) at the expense of the other (sense). Further, the justifications are aimed toward perpetuating the presuppositions of the social imaginary and its values at the expense of a more holistic sense of reality. Thus, any kind of faith or truth articulated as a justified true belief would be unlikely to have the integrative, transformative effect of faith that Kierkegaard described. The vitality of faith arises from felt experience.
As in other important cultural forms informed by abductive social systems and structures, religions became rooted in the social imaginary and thus grounded in literal idolatry. When this happens in a religious tradition, verbal formulas of “belief” or creedal statements replace the lived, creative vitality of faith. Observable obedience to literal traditions supplants the capacity to transform the world through an inner awakening based on imaginative encounters with unknowable realities (the focus of
Section 3 of this essay). Undermining this source of faith diminished the sense of confidence people could have in their intuitive understandings. Embracing collective representations that held hierarchies as natural generated approval. Both the merely mental definition of good and exclusively verbal formulations of truth became disconnected from embodied reality. Internalized systems of morality perpetuated the hierarchical collective representations of the social imaginary. People enacted psychological violence upon themselves and thus reduced the need for actual physical violence to maintain social cohesion (
Foucault 1977). Violence is an application of force that compels adherence to an unnatural, externally imposed end or result; one common artificial end is the perpetuation of hierarchical organizations. One example of this is the violent demand for self-identity and complete coherence that Butler described. People desire an externally imposed result (total self-identity) at the expense of the natural evolution of character. A contemporary example of violence that compels complete narrative coherence is the use of RINO (Republican in Name Only) as an insult targeting those who deviate from the ideologically framed narrative coherence that dominates contemporary American politics.
Often, that which “justified” the “true beliefs” was less a forceful argument than an appeal to an authority within the system of hierarchies violently imposed on the social imaginary. These are unlike beliefs in innate virtue or goodness, which persist as attitudes of faith outside of systems of justification or authority. Justified true beliefs became laden with values that promote a given social order (the order that justifies them as true), whose premises violate the normative potential of harmonious flourishing. Jantzen unsurprisingly notes that such beliefs, even when “justified true beliefs”, have “clear class and gender implications” (p. 20). Attempting to justify one’s beliefs to others requires putting them in terms of the social system. Doing so strengthens the social system without providing any true ground of confidence for what was felt.
Many contemporary authors have exposed important flaws in how the social imaginary excludes valid perspectives. This limits what is presumed possible to know or experience. “Man represents the western configuration of the human as synonymous with the heteromasculine, white, propertied, and liberal subject that renders all those who do not conform to these characteristics as exploitable nonhumans, literal legal no-bodies” (
Weheliye 2014, p. 135). These artificially limited world views that are projected as absolute truth have historically led to a narrowed way of knowing the world, rendering a vast amount of potential experience as extraneous (
Neumann 2017). The imaginary Jantzen describes has been imposed throughout the world. It conforms to the power that a left-brained approach to experience (
McGilchrist 2021) has retained as foundational and particularly useful for the development of technologies. Often these technologies provide military advantages. Because the imaginary of western culture has been successful at marginalizing other kinds of knowing, it has been addressed by various critiques of “epistemicide” (
Santos 2014), the advocacy of queer phenomenology (
Ahmed 2006), and the validation of women’s ways of knowing (
Belenky 1986;
Gilligan 2006).
Believing that conforming to “moral ideals” is beneficial, especially in religious contexts, often generates harmful effects to oneself and others in a horrifying feedback loop. The pursuit of the idealized “coherent” self, organized around justified true beliefs as the source of a total self-identity, projects violence onto the surrounding world. It does not test the truth of its descriptive propositions by drawing internal and external sources into conversation. It results in a narrow, one-sided character unlike the potential Ricoeur and Gendlin described. Alex
Zamalin (
2019), in his study of
Black No More, described this narrowness as consistent with self-interested pursuits. Operating in the exclusively verbal and conceptual realm of the imaginary allows things to be called by terms antithetical to what they are. He writes, “concealing lack of virtue requires reversing its meaning” such that “Hard work becomes exploitation. Theft is a natural right…white supremacy represses and rationalizes this process. Whiteness becomes an organized religion”. Zamalin then describes how the contemporary social imaginary and the demand for complete coherence work together: “One submits to its fixed identity to wash away their contradictions. But there is a cost: it is morally deadening” (p. 68). Zamalin’s insight also reflects the ways that ostensible opposites at the level of
ipse fuse at the level of
idem. The harmful consequences of those pursuing purity with an air of sanctimoniousness creates a “static” identity that must be preserved at all costs. The pursuit of this ideal is the illusion of certainty within the limits of rationality, not real faith.
In religious settings, any sense of “faith” grounded in a social imaginary that generates and is protected by a hierarchy tends to be compensatory. It advises sacrifice for a future reward. Hierarchies tend to proliferate based on what Ricoeur (
Ricœur and Ihde 2007) identifies as the twin themes that comprise the “corrupt forms of religion”:
accusation and
consolation. These themes correlate to “taboo and refuge” as the “two main aspects of religion”, and to two poles of religious feeling in its simplest sense: “the fear of punishment and the desire for protection” (p. 441). These two options derive from the death-based dominator model of the contemporary social imaginary. Ricoeur (
Ricœur and Ihde 2007) explores how Nietzsche and Freud offered “a critique of cultural representations considered as disguised symptoms of desire and fear” by focusing on its forms of “prohibition, accusation, punishment, and condemnation” grounded on a “god who both threatens and consoles” (p. 441). Notably, the shared premise in these themes is the avoidance of perceived harm, not the pursuit of the good.
Often, a religion anchored on the fear of punishment and the corresponding desire for protection takes the collective representations of the divine literally. Such religious approaches create conceptual idols. Worshippers are encouraged to identify with the idol, sacrificing what is uniquely given in character for power and influence. Habits are evaluated relatively to external conformity to the idol’s standard, rather than through an innate desire to grow or develop. The pursuit of a character that conforms to religious ideals that were distorted by collective representations often leads to a diminished, rather than empowered, sense of self. A sense of natural unique goodness is lost, replaced by a sense of guilt or shame for deviating from collective representations of appropriateness. When the powerful potential of a narrative identity is lost, it results in becoming a character in someone else’s story.
Fromm (
1994, p. 78) indicated that a “faith” generated out of these conditions of fear and estrangement becomes a fearful, anxious reaction against unbearable conditions. Such conditions compromise the integrated expressions of inner relatedness that comprise an affirmation of life. As an example, Luther’s forceful faith derived “certainty by elimination of the isolated individual self by becoming an instrument in the hands of an overwhelmingly strong power outside of the individual”. This surrender to a greater power can develop into a drive to display loyalty to authority against all personally felt and rational impulses. This form of faith, which springs from a dominator model of the social imaginary, is literally understood as the only possibility of faith and becomes either desired or reviled as though it comprised the true capacity of faith. Because it demands the annihilation of the self and the destruction of one’s given character, Kierkegaard would classify this inner erosion as an act of despair rather than a work of faith.
Jerome
Miller (
1992, p. 14) referred to an unquestioned level of presupposition as an “arche”, a foundation that bestows an air of certainty onto knowledge, which happens in our current social imaginary through the use of justified true beliefs. As a form of
idem at the cultural level, it narrows the range of
ipse to its terms. Miller states that the loss of an
arche “uproots our tradition at its source, removes its Archimedean principle, creates an-arche”. Defining the
arche as a support of one’s preferred interpretive framework enables those who stand unquestioningly on its principle to claim a position of superiority over alternatives. Miller explored the paradoxical relationship between
arche and truth in this way:
And how could one go about making a case for such superiority when the very principle whose superiority one intends to prove would have to be intuited at the beginning because it alone could provide a basis for one’s argument? The more one reflects on that paradox, the more one is led to suspect that the real but repressed purpose of every universe of meaning is to construct a system of defenses around a primal prejudice which is treated as an absolute principle so that its ungrounded character can be disguised. (p. 14).
A truly grounded character is open to correction. It explores vulnerably, without attempts at external justification. In time, and with the permission of incoherence that establishes the ongoing truth of a character based on an evolving range, narrative identities tend to deepen. Even those who never feel summoned to the level of conviction that occurs at the imaginative level of faith nonetheless naturally gravitate to the promptings of conscience as a basic guiding principle. This natural inclination to the good is subverted by the modern social imaginary. Lacking the resources of felt experience and with an epistemology that embraces the literal, conscience became equated with obedience. The modern social imaginary is predicated on an
arche that values conformity to conventional moral authority, complete coherence in the self, and the promotion of an artificial hierarchy.
A lack of growth combined with cultural inflexibility becomes part of the
idem of the individual thinkers within a given system.
Miller (
1992) found that having an
arche “makes its lack of knowledge the dogmatic starting point of a whole system” (p. 15), a systemic limitation inherited by those born into that narrowed way of knowing. Once the imaginary that bridges language and sensory experience loses curiosity about the ongoing truth of its propositional status, it shifts from understanding X
as if it were Y to positing that X
is Y. The formula X
is Y becomes a rigid, unchanging statement of identity. Because living in a punitive, dominator culture makes it desirable to repress a capacity for fallibility, the resulting diminution of
ipse possibilities leads to a restricted and inopportunely rigid
idem structure. This restricts the capacity to think creatively.
Understood at an individual level, this rigid sense of identity becomes the demand for a completely coherent, self-identical person. The sense of self, still shorn of a secure (unquestioned) position in a disembedded social world or religious cosmos, is not eager to dismiss the social imaginary that provides a sense of commonality. Curiosity and openness become associated with fallibility (or fallenness); thus, these traits are punished, especially when it comes to questioning the arche. What remains is a violent struggle for domination and superiority based on claiming the right to define the arche, and thus the basis of the cultural norms and the social imaginary. Dimly aware that something has been repressed but dreading an encounter with it, anxiety pervades the felt experience of the imaginary no matter where one fits in its organization.
An arche initially had a positive function: as a descriptive proposition of the world whose ongoing truth was assessed, it allowed humans to experience the world “as if” it fit a particular set of rules. These rules consisted of harmonious integrations of language and sensory experience. Children’s games of make-believe, in which they create temporary rules around reality to open up new experiences, show the usefulness of a temporary arche. This playful embrace of an abundant and vital world is lost once a particular arche ceases to be one possibility among many and becomes experienced as something certain or necessary, even when it has outlived its best functioning. This results in a distinct disadvantage: our ability to interact with the world becomes limited.
This is especially true of the contemporary
arche, scientific rationality. It perpetuates itself by identifying knowledge as “everything [that can] be measured, known, tested, fully understood”. What it jettisons are the essential qualities for a spontaneous life. These vital qualities emerge from “…a sensitivity to human expressiveness—the different gestures, tones of voice, and textures of speech—that provide cues for responding to and engaging with the person who appears before them” (
Zamalin 2019, p. 53). Believing in the
arche that serves as the foundation for a social structure reduces what could be
chosen. This then eliminates the ability for the
ipse identity to engage confidently with the surrounding world.
Barfield related literalness to the embrace of a subject–object world. This provides a helpful way of understanding the change that created the modern religious landscape and social imaginary. Ricoeur described how narrative identity is a dynamic work of self-creation that moves between an idem level of foundational sameness and an ipse level of identificatory recognition. This ongoing process of recognition and self-discovery is stochastically fallible and relates to how the imagination provides a synthesis connecting sense experience and language reminiscent of Gendlin’s definition of truth. At the level of the collective representations that serve as the arche of a social imaginary, modernity tends to limit the capacity of the imagination by making experience certain, indubitable, and literal: a small set of conceptual, verbal imaginings.
At the level of the cultural narratives that govern the directions that societies (and the individuals in them) evaluate as desirable, the arche contains the sorts of unquestioned narrative structures that Jantzen described, including the assumption of progress, the value of rationality, and the focus on individuals and freedoms. These fixed imaginative connections are disguised moral evaluations that rank mind over body, men over women, power over pleasure, and word over body. Collective representations become a more dominant and increasingly assumed (unquestionable) origin at the heart of a social imaginary, the “modern” equivalent to being embedded in a social or cosmic order. The construction of a narrative identity devolves into the work of developing habits that support a connection to a particular idolatrous collective representation, presupposed as desirable.
3.3. How Literal Idolatry Limits the Capacity for Creative Change
Bateson’s description of a stochastic process provides a model for how change is natural and intuitive. It provides a flexible sense of self-consistency (internal identity) and a sense of continuity (over time) without becoming overly rigid. Such a system prioritizes development over total coherence or absolute certainty. Stochastic processes value guesses but remain anchored in a harmonious congruence grounded in reality, in conversation with ongoing environmental circumstances. Ricoeur’s description of narrative identity shows how our characters can change and develop over time when anchored in the primacy of sense experience and a spontaneous imagination. It seems fair to state that Ricoeur’s narrative identity emerges on a stochastic basis because it employs a random component (ipse-based explorations of different external environments that allow for a scattering of unpredictable events) and a selective process (Ricoeur’s sense of imagination and character) to only allow certain outcomes to endure (idem as a stable sense of sameness). When internal or external changes indicate an inadequate or outdated idem identity (such as what happens during puberty or when moving to a new vocation or residence), it requires a certain number of stochastic experiments where identities are “tried on” or “tried out”. Character integrates what is more authentic into an emergent idem identity.
The question of the selective process works at the level of judgment as well as at the level of narrative identity. The imagination, which frames sensory experiences in terms that we can recognize, filters out non-threatening extraneous elements and allows us to focus on experiential data that support our preferences. Similarly, character limits what beliefs and behaviors we will identify as belonging to us; within psychologically integrated or congruent persons, the beliefs and behavior are generally consistent with a person’s self-awareness. Following Taylor and Jantzen, in our modern world, the social imaginary provides a parallel evaluative function as it operates within individuals by arranging experiences and possibilities in terms of preset presuppositions. It guides guardians and authorities within cultural institutions (political, social, and religious) to make decisions that conform to the milieu of its social reality.
Often, such preset schemas become defined as “properties” that are imagined to be necessarily true. This process reflects Barfield’s description of how nouns become idols through the stilling influence of nominalizing processes. This sense of property comes in part from the philosophical notion referring to elements that are essential to the identity of something, the way that whiteness is a property of chalk. Once the imagined “property” is understood literally, in a totally definitive way, problems emerge—both at the level of individuals and the society. The modern social imaginary encourages this pattern of thought. As Jennifer
Nash (
2019) argued, “As it is currently structured, property deeply organizes sociality, and law operates to protect property from trespass and theft. Thus, law operates to create categories like property holder (owner) and trespasser (thief), and to organize the social world around proximities to ownership” (p. 125). A narrative identity does not need “properties” in this way, as character remains grounded by qualities, traits, and attributes that evolve over time.
Understanding how a stochastic process ideally functions provides a useful way to sense how idolatry is problematic for dynamic systems. Relative to the process of change, idolatry occurs when something interferes with this selective process by precluding the possibility of a partially random scattering. Gendlin might find that this occurs when the conceptual becomes literally understood as truth without recourse to felt experience. Barfield would argue that this occurs when we take created collective representations as literally real. Miller would suggest that this becomes the
arche that determines what counts as thinking. Nash might argue that this would come from possessing too many “properties”, things that we do not want to imagine ourselves without. Each of these makes humans more rigid, less flexible, more guarded, and less open. The resulting lack of curiosity prevents people from sensing large portions of otherwise available experiences, defining them as extraneous (
Neumann 2017). This would largely include the unknowable realities open to the imagination but closed to conventional beliefs—including Ricoeur’s summoned subject. At the level of narrative identity, a fixation on unchanging properties interrupts a natural stochastic process by freezing the
idem sense of identity.
A second way to interrupt a stochastic system at an individual level is through what
Sartre (
1996) identified as
bad faith. In
Being and Nothingness, Sartre discusses the “
metastable concept of ‘transcendence-facticity’” (p. 149). The latter terms are fairly similar to the sense of chosen and given, or Ricoeur’s use of
ipse and
idem. For Sartre, the terms are the “double property of the human being” and thus he (similar to Ricoeur) admitted that the “two aspects of human reality are and ought to be capable of a valid co-ordination” (p. 148). Unlike Ricoeur or Gendlin, Sartre did not attend to the ideal functioning of this system, i.e., what it would be to live in
good faith. Sartre wrote, “But bad faith does not wish either to co-ordinate them or to surmount them in a synthesis. Bad faith seeks to affirm their identity while preserving their differences” (p. 148). Bad faith allows someone to embrace the illusion of freedom without responsibility, treating these two realities as convenient, mutually exclusive, and non-integrated options. Bad faith allows us to affirm our facticity and believe we had no choice, or to affirm our transcendence and claim that we are not bound to past choices. This treats the given and chosen as mutually exclusive rather than as collaborative and generative elements within a person’s character.
Perhaps it is unsurprising, but it would seem as if the project of literal idolatry can only be undertaken as a bad faith project. Otherwise, the stochastic process of dynamic evolution would prohibit any form of idolatry. Arches and imaginaries would retain their sense of “as if”, leaving individuals with the joyful responsibility of constructing characters by a sorting process that results in increasingly appropriate habits and identifications. Sartre’s brilliant discussion of reasoning in bad faith shows that bad faith arguments, constructed to defend a premise, are persuasive precisely and only because “to the extent that I could be so persuaded, I have always been so”. The first choice one makes in bad faith is “the nature of truth”, after which, contrary to Gendlin, “…a peculiar type of evidence appears; non-persuasive evidence. Bad faith apprehends evidence but it is resigned in advance to not being fulfilled by this evidence, to not being persuaded and transformed into good faith” (pp. 162–63). The nonchalant pre-determination to sidestep the evaluative mechanism so central for the stochastic process (and, in Ricoeur’s work, for character development) ensures a system that shifts without actually moving. When engaging in bad faith, one selects a descriptive proposition as a way of ignoring the presentation of an ongoing truth. This results in feeling stuck, not stable.
One of the important services rendered by a stochastic process is that it invites organisms to respond to their environments, using feedback to determine strategies to meet their needs.
Bateson (
2002) argued that temporary changes are
adaptations to present circumstances. Over a prolonged period of time (in which, Ricoeur would say, new habits alter a character and recontextualize “normal”), organisms
acclimate to that which is initially experienced as extreme or excessive. As an example, Bateson related that the basic structure of an organism slowly changes when it moves into high-altitude (and oxygen-poor) environments. Bateson also allowed for another kind of change,
addiction, a category of change that is not adaptive and features no survival value (p. 178).
Acclimation uses the creative imagination in positive ways so that organisms can thrive in sites that would seem to be hostile.
Nash (
2019) demonstrated this capacity in her invitation for Black feminists to imagine the law as a place that would promote human flourishing. She wrote, “freedom and radical black feminist politics can be rooted in myriad sites, including spaces that have been rife with our own subordination” (p. 130). Nash also presents the problematic side of acclimation, which has led Black feminism to adhere to a property-based perspective. This happens when Black feminists identify intersectionality as part of a territory in need of defense. Nash described this problematic process as reflecting some aspects of Black feminism that align overmuch with the modern social imaginary, and thus “has mirrored a larger US tradition in which to care for something is to assert ownership over it, and thus to protect it from imagined threat of trespass”. But because she also knows that black feminist theory is “anticaptivity… fundamentally invested in radical conceptions of freedom”, she wishes to reanimate black feminism’s radical imagination, its capacity to continue to ask:
What if we imagined relationships with what we cherish beyond the racially saturated conceptions of property and ownership? Can we untether care and love from ownership? Can we express our deepest and most cherished investments otherwise? (p. 137)
The questions are carefully worded to inspire all readers to tell a different story, opening a shift from a historical awareness of legal oppression as being constitutive of identity through facticity to imagining it as a site of care. Even if social structures seem to define hierarchical binaries as facts, perpetuating beliefs such as the necessity to struggle over who dominates, such suggestions remain informed by the totalizing vision of literal idolatry.
To approach this a different way, one limitation of contemporary identity politics is that it suggests seeing people “as” Black or queer, presupposing that such terms provide a total knowledge of another’s identity. This focus on defining people as determined by external observables is limited. It distracts from the invitation to view social conditions as capable of being changed, i.e., from the potential for improving everyone’s lives, including those currently marginalized. Nash opens up the potential for the imagination to provide a work of good faith. Her imagination is not a fantasy of escapist transcendence. It opens a new direction within the self and thus, potentially, society. Exploring the world informed by descriptive propositions based on generosity and care would mean moving from the given (legal fixation on property) to a different chosen (a caring focus on loving relationships). This process of changing identities would create new habits and opportunities. It would free all people for fresh forms of action within emergent situations.
Unfortunately, addiction, the second potential for adaptation, is more available in our society than the imaginative acclimation Nash invites. Bateson argues that addiction occurs when an “innovator is hooked into the business of trying to hold constant some rate of change” (
Bateson 2002, p. 174). Constancy is achieved by neglecting the sorts of feedback evaluations that prefer dynamic, responsive growth. Addiction is the desire to maintain a static condition in a way that feels dynamic. Similar to bad faith, addiction preserves the larger system through creating the illusion of change. The error, one suspects, comes when a small element within a wider system exerts a powerful influence over the rest with catastrophic consequences. This definition of addiction works relative to social vices (where the desire to hold constant a specific kind of feeling, through the cycles of diminishing returns, proves to be more powerful than survival). It also works relative to social systems of addiction, such as technology, fuel, convenience, and wealth. Each of these evaluates success by holding constant (or improving/accelerating) the rate of change as measured by a particular vector in a certain direction.
Literal idolatry holds change at a constant level that deters potential rivals. Creative attention is compelled to resolve crises caused by addictive habits rather than considering how to best inhabit the world as part of a larger whole. No matter how much suffering a creative solution temporarily alleviates, ideas that remain within the confines of literal idolatry only perpetuate problems. By preserving
arche and hierarchy, the character structure remains unchanged and at best only new habits are enabled or acquired, leading to “static” rather than “dynamic” change. A dynamic change requires “new drives or character traits” (
Fromm 1994, p. 13).
Interestingly, a model for this kind of dynamic change exists in twelve-step recovery groups. Many people find that attempting to overcome addiction through some sort of control, especially when the addiction has become a “property” of one’s identity, results in only temporary relief. Addiction and control are mirrored psychological forms at an
idem level. Controlling responses to addiction focus on what Bennett would identify as causal logic that identifies only one seemingly dominant component. They ignore notions of distributive agency that examine reality more holistically. The true alternative, which opens up the potential for a qualitatively different future, occurs through surrender. The kind of surrender advised in twelve-step groups allows for a unifying move of faith whose first three steps provide a simplified, secularized echo of Kierkegaard’s definition of faith: “the self in being itself and in willing to be itself rests transparently in God” (
Kierkegaard et al. 1983). This work of surrender unites the chosen and the given rather than allowing them to remain opposed.