Is Theism Incompatible with the Pauline Principle?
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. What Is the Pauline Principle
3. Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil
So then let’s consider the second type of case where God’s permitting a significant evil is the means to provide some significant good rather than to prevent some significant evil. Consider a case involving just human agents. Suppose parents you know were to permit their children to be brutally assaulted to make possible the soul-making of the person who would attempt to comfort their children after they have been assaulted or to make possible the soul-making that their children themselves could experience by coming to forgive their assailants. Would you think the parents were morally justified in so acting? Hardly. Here you surely would agree with the Pauline Principle’s prohibition of such actions. Permitting one’s children to be brutally assaulted is an action that is wrong in itself, and not something that could be permitted for the sake of whatever good consequences it might happen to have. That is why the Pauline Principle prohibits any appeal to good consequences to justify such actions in such cases. So for human agents, given that such intrinsically wrongful actions would significantly conflict with the basic interests of their victims, there are no exceptions to the Pauline Principle for cases of this sort where the significant evil that is to be done is just a means to securing a good to which the beneficiary is not entitled.
Moreover, if there are no exceptions to the Pauline Principle for humans in such cases, then the same should also hold true for God. If it is always wrong for us to do actions of a certain sort, then it should always be wrong for God to do them as well. So, for contexts where the issue is whether to permit a significant evil to achieve some additional good, God, like us, would never be justified in permitting evil in such cases.(p. 57)
[P1] There are many types of actions that human agents are always morally prohibited in virtue of their description as certain types of actions, regardless of any further good consequences they perceive will follow from these actions.[P2] Acts permitting people to inflict significant harm on others fall into this class of actions.[P3] If human agents are always prohibited from doing some action, then God is prohibited from doing that action.[P4] If an omniscient and omnipotent person exists, then he permits people to do acts that inflict significant harm on others.[P5] If a morally perfect person exists, he will not do any morally prohibited action.
4. A “Divine Command Defense” Response to Sterba’s Argument
4.1. Divine Command Theories and God’s Obligations
4.1.1. Does God Have Moral Duties?
4.1.2. Is the Content of God and Human Obligations the Same?
“One can even stipulate that God, as a benevolent legislator, must attend to the same kinds of considerations as a human legislator. The divine moral code’s content must account for the selfishness, fallibility, and other limitations of the mere mortals on whom it is imposed”.(emphasis added) (p. 8)
“Because God relates to the law of nature as a legislator, He cannot treat the law of nature merely as a set of principles of evaluation. The law of nature is also an instruction to fallible persons to act in specific ways, and as a rational legislator, God considers the imperfections of the beings who will execute the law on Earth”.
4.2. Divine Command Theories and the Pauline Principle: A Historical Model
Now, as God is a Being of Infinite Goodness, it is plain the end he proposes is Good. But God enjoying in himself all possible Perfection, it follows that it is not his own good, but that of his Creatures. Again, the Moral Actions of Men are entirely terminated within themselves, so as to have no influence on the other orders of Intelligences or reasonable Creatures: The end therefore to be procured by them, can be no other than the good of Men. But as nothing in a natural State can entitle one Man more than another to the favour of God, except only Moral Goodness, which consisting in a Conformity to the Laws of God, doth presuppose the being of such Laws, and Law ever supposing an end, to which it guides our actions, it follows that Antecedent to the end proposed by God, no distinction can be conceived between Men; that end therefore itself or general design of Providence is not determined or limited by any Respect of Persons: It is not therefore the private Good of this or that Man, Nation or Age, but the general wellbeing of all Men, of all Nations, of all Ages of the World, which God designs should be procured by the concurring Actions of each individual.
It must indeed be allowed, that the rational Deduction of those Laws is founded in the intrinsic Tendency they have to promote the Well-being of Mankind, on Condition they are universally and constantly observed. But though it afterward comes to pass, that they accidentally fail of that End, or even promote the contrary, they are nevertheless binding, as hath been already proved. …That whole Difficulty may be resolved by the following Distinction. In framing the general Laws of Nature, it is granted, we must be entirely guided by the Publick Good of Mankind, but not in the ordinary Moral Actions of our Lives. Such a Rule, if universally observed, hath from the Nature of Things, a necessary Fitness to promote the general Well-being of Mankind; therefore it is a Law of Nature: This is good Reasoning. But if we should say such an Action doth in this Instance produce much Good, and no Harm to Mankind; therefore it is lawful: This were wrong. The Rule is framed with respect to the Good of Mankind, but our Practice must be always shaped immediately by the Rule”.
5. Is a Divine Command Theory Coherent?
5.1. Interpretative Problems
[t]he U.S. judiciary in interpreting the laws often tries to determine what purpose the legislature had in passing a particular law, and whether that purpose accords with the U.S. Constitution. And sometimes the US judiciary strikes down laws passed by the legislature as unconstitutional. According to divine command theory, however, there would be no comparable role for humans to have with respect to the commands of God. We couldn’t, for example, strike down any of God’s commands because they failed to accord with some independent moral standard. Thus, our role in interpreting and applying God’s commands under divine command theory would be narrowly circumscribed.
5.2. Conflicting Rules
Here we seem to require some kind of a background theory that compares the good that would be accomplished in each case as well as weighs the competing obligations involved, and then makes a recommendation about what should be done. Yet divine command theory provides no such background theory for resolving conflicts between commands. Under the theory, each command is obligatory simply because it is commanded by God. Conflicts that arise among God’s commands could be appropriately resolved only by yet another command of God that shows which command has priority. This is because, according to divine command theory, the resolution of conflicts always could go either way. So there is no way for us to figure out, in advance, how it should go. This then would leave us with only a very minimal role when interpreting or applying the commands of God, and in cases where those commands conflict, we would be at a complete loss as to what to do.
5.3. Epistemological Problems
It would seem that divine command theorists maintain that God’s commands are received through special revelations to particular individuals or groups. But if the commands of God are made known only to a few, how can others know what those commands are or when they are reasonably bound to obey them? Presumably, people can only be morally bound by commands they know about and have reason to accept.
5.4. Conflicting Commands
Different individuals and groups have claimed to be recipients of special revelations that conflict in ways which would support conflicting moral requirements. Of course, if some of those who claim to have received a special revelation rise to power, they may be able to force obedience on the rest. But, then others would have no independent reason to go along with that forceful imposition.
5.5. The Anything Goes Objection
Just anything could turn out to be the right thing to do, such as torturing babies for the fun of it, depending on the sheer commands of God. But the idea that just anything could turn out to be the right thing to do, irrespective of how harmful it is to human beings, has been widely seen by theists and atheists alike to be sufficient to defeat the view.
In one important sense of the word, it is a paradigm case of injustice if a court declares someone to be guilty of an offence of which it knows him to be innocent. More generally, a finding is unjust if it is at variance with what the relevant law and the facts together require, and particularly if it is known by the court to be so. More generally still, any award of marks, prizes, or the like is unjust if it is at variance with the agreed standards for the contest in question: if one diver’s performance, in fact, measures up better to the accepted standards for diving than another’s, it will be unjust if the latter is awarded higher marks or the prize… The statement that a certain decision is thus just or unjust will not be objectively prescriptive: in so far as it can be simply true it leaves open the question of whether there is any objective requirement to do what is just and to refrain from what is unjust, and equally leaves open the practical decision to act in either way.
5.6. Is This Picture Consistent?
“However, if God cannot command us to do anything that goes against the law of reason that he embedded in our hearts because that would involve God in a contradiction, then, it would also seem that God could not act against that same law of reason that he embedded in our hearts because that too would involve God in a contradiction”.
5.7. Can God Be Coherently Called Good?
6. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See Mark 3:1–6, and Luke 13:10–17. |
2 | I am using the word “consequentialist” here to refer to forms of act consequentialism, where an act is morally right iff doing it has better (actual or foreseen) consequences than any alternative action. Below I will note that certain forms of rule consequentialism can be used to support the Pauline principle. Francis Howard Sydner has argued that rule consequentialist theories should be classified as deontological theories. Just as a rubber duck is not a duck rule, consequentialism is not consequentialism (Howard-Snyder 1993). |
3 | This characterisation comes from Elizabeth Anscombe, see (Anscombe 1958). |
4 | Brandt (1972) makes a similar point. Responding to Nagel’s objection that utilitarianism cannot justify absolute prohibitions on non-combatant immunity that apply, regardless of the consequences. He writes
The similarity to Berkeley is apparent. |
5 | See (Donagan 1977, pp. 146–49) for a critical discussion of the idea that precepts of a rational law must conflict. |
6 | Tuckness (2021) argues that Paley, who adopted essentially the same kind of divine command theory as Berkeley, worked out potential qualifications to rule in apparent clashes by “envisioning cases where a rule that includes an exception produces better results than one without an exception and so some rules should have escape clauses built into them.” (p. 86). |
7 | Immediately after the passage cited above, Berkeley (1712) adds:
|
8 | See (Peoples 2011) for a good elaboration on this point. |
9 | I discuss and defend this response in more detail in (Flannagan 2021). |
References
- Adams, Robert. 1999. Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Alimi, Tony. 2020. Covenants and Commands. Journal of Religious Ethics 48: 498–518. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Alston, William. 2005. Response to Zagzebski. In Perspectives on the Philosophy of William P. Alston. Edited by Heather D. Battaly and Michael P. Lynch. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, pp. 203–8. [Google Scholar]
- Anscombe, Elizabeth. 1958. Modern Moral Philosophy. Philosophy XXXIII: 1–19. Available online: https://www.cambridge.org/core/services/aop-cambridge-core/content/view/9E56836F22C34BE2CE4A3E763691C2FB/S0031819100037943a.pdf (accessed on 1 October 2022). [CrossRef]
- Augustine, Saint. 420. St. Augustine, Enchiridion: On Faith, Hope, and Love (1955) English Translation. Available online: https://www.tertullian.org/fathers/augustine_enchiridion_02_trans.htm#C27 (accessed on 29 September 2022).
- Austin, John. 1832. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Edited by W. Rumble. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Berkeley, George. 1712. A Discourse on Passive Obedience. Eighteenth Century Collections Online. Available online: https://quod.lib.umich.edu/e/ecco/004899015.0001.000/1:3?rgn=div1;view=fulltext (accessed on 15 September 2021).
- Brandt, Richard B. 1972. Utilitarianism and the Rules of War. Philosophy and Public Affairs 1: 143–65. [Google Scholar]
- Brogan, A. P. 1959. John Locke and Utilitarianism. Ethics 69: 79–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brown, John. 1751. On Motives to Virtue, the Necessity of Religious Principle’ from the Essays on the Characteristics of the Earl of Shaftesbury. In Utilitarianism and Religion. Edited by James Crimmins. Bristol: Theommes Press, 1998. pp. 54–106. [Google Scholar]
- Carson, Thomas L. 1990. Value and the Good Life. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Craig, William Lane. 2003. Philosophical Foundations of a Christian World View. Downers Grover: Intervarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Darwall, Stephen. 2006. Berkeley’s Moral and Political Philosophy. In Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. Edited by Kenneth Winkler. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 311–98. [Google Scholar]
- Donagan, Alan. 1977. The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Flannagan, Matthew Alexander. 2011. Tooley, Plantinga and the Deontological Argument from Evil. Philosophia Christi 13: 373–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Flannagan, Matthew Alexander. 2017. Robust Ethics and the Autonomy Thesis. Philosophia Christi 19: 345–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Flannagan, Matthew Alexander. 2021. Why the Horrendous Deeds Objection Is Still a Bad Argument. Sophia 61: 1–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gay, John. 1731. Preliminary Dissertation on the Fundamental Principle of Virtue or Morality. In Utilitarians and Religion. Edited by James E. Crimmins. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1998. pp. 31–33. [Google Scholar]
- Howard-Snyder, Frances. 1993. Rule Consequentialism Is a Rubber Duck. American Philosophical Quarterly 30: 271–78. [Google Scholar]
- Jenyns, Soame. 1757. A Free Inquiry into the Nature of Evil. In Utilitarians and Religion. Edited by James Crimmins. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1998. pp. 111–34. [Google Scholar]
- Law, Edmund. 1758. On Morality and Religion. In Utilitarians and Religion. Edited by James Crimmins. Bristol: Theommes Press, pp. 135–41. [Google Scholar]
- Louden, Robert. 1995. Butler’s Divine Utilitarianism. History of Philosophy Quarterly 12: 265–80. [Google Scholar]
- Mackie, John Leslie. 1955. Evil and Omnipotence. Mind 64: 200–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mackie, John Leslie. 1977. Inventing Right and Wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Mackie, John Leslie. 1982. The Miracle of Theism. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Paley, Wiliam. 1785. Principles of moral and Political Philosophy. In Utilitarians and Religion. Edited by James E. Crimmins. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, pp. 207–11. [Google Scholar]
- Peoples, Glenn. 2011. The Epistemological Objection to Divine Command Ethics. Philosophia Christi 13: 389–401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1967. God and Other Minds: A Study in the Rational Justification of Belief in God. London: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. God Freedom and Evil. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1986. Is Theism Really a Miracle? Faith and Philosophy 3: 109–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rutherford, Thomas. 1744. An Essay on the Nature and Obligations of Virtue. New York: Gale Ecco, Print Editions 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? New York: Palgrave. [Google Scholar]
- Tucker, Abraham. 1768. The Light of Nature Pursued. In Utilitarians and Religion. Edited by James Crimmins. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1998. pp. 158–206. [Google Scholar]
- Tuckness, Alex. 2000. Legislation and Non-neutral Principles: A Lockean Approach. The Journal of Political Philosophy 8: 363–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tuckness, Alex. 2021. Morality and Legislation: Rules and Consequences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Waterland, Daniel. 1730. The Nature, Obligation, and Efficacy, of the Christian Sacraments, Considered. Charleston: Nabu Press, 2011. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Flannagan, M. Is Theism Incompatible with the Pauline Principle? Religions 2022, 13, 1050. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111050
Flannagan M. Is Theism Incompatible with the Pauline Principle? Religions. 2022; 13(11):1050. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111050
Chicago/Turabian StyleFlannagan, Matthew. 2022. "Is Theism Incompatible with the Pauline Principle?" Religions 13, no. 11: 1050. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111050
APA StyleFlannagan, M. (2022). Is Theism Incompatible with the Pauline Principle? Religions, 13(11), 1050. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13111050