Sign in to use this feature.

Years

Between: -

Subjects

remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline

Journals

Article Types

Countries / Regions

Search Results (77)

Search Parameters:
Keywords = sterba

Order results
Result details
Results per page
Select all
Export citation of selected articles as:
20 pages, 259 KiB  
Article
A View on the Possibility of an Ethics Without God
by Elliott R. Crozat
Religions 2025, 16(7), 813; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16070813 - 22 Jun 2025
Viewed by 394
Abstract
This article addresses the question, “Is an ethics without God possible?” This question is explored in a special issue, edited by Prof. Dr. James P. Sterba, which directly poses this very inquiry. I argue that an objective ethics without God is epistemically possible. [...] Read more.
This article addresses the question, “Is an ethics without God possible?” This question is explored in a special issue, edited by Prof. Dr. James P. Sterba, which directly poses this very inquiry. I argue that an objective ethics without God is epistemically possible. Having addressed this initial point, I then make the case that an objective ethics without God is metaphysically possible. In other words, there are plausible explanations to support the thesis that ethics exists without God. Lastly, I propose that although God is not required for ethics, it is reasonable to postulate God’s existence to realize aspects of justice. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Is an Ethics without God Possible?)
11 pages, 170 KiB  
Article
Prolegomena to the Concept of God When Dealing with the Question: Is Ethics Without God Possible?
by Daniel A. Dombrowski
Religions 2025, 16(5), 651; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16050651 - 20 May 2025
Viewed by 438
Abstract
This article examines the assumption that, in order to respond adequately to the question in the title, one must have the classical concept of God in mind. Classical theism is criticized and neoclassical/process theism is briefly defended. Specifically, the classical theistic attribute of [...] Read more.
This article examines the assumption that, in order to respond adequately to the question in the title, one must have the classical concept of God in mind. Classical theism is criticized and neoclassical/process theism is briefly defended. Specifically, the classical theistic attribute of omnipotence receives four criticisms. The hope is that these criticisms prepare the way for a more fruitful response to the question in the title than is possible when the classical concept of God is assumed. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Is an Ethics without God Possible?)
17 pages, 198 KiB  
Article
Why Ethics Requires a God and Is Safer from Evolutionary Debunking Threats as a Result: A Reply to Sterba
by Gerald K. Harrison
Religions 2025, 16(3), 360; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030360 - 13 Mar 2025
Viewed by 955
Abstract
Sterba has argued that ethics does not require God and that an atheistic objectivist ethics is compatible with an evolutionary account of our development. This paper argues that though ethics does not require God specifically, it does require a god of some sort, [...] Read more.
Sterba has argued that ethics does not require God and that an atheistic objectivist ethics is compatible with an evolutionary account of our development. This paper argues that though ethics does not require God specifically, it does require a god of some sort, for all normative reasons require a god and moral reasons are simply a subset of normative reasons. Sterba’s criticisms of more orthodox divine command theories of ethics are shown to raise no challenge to my view. Furthermore, even if Sterba’s alternative atheistic objectivist ethics is coherent, it would leave moral norms vulnerable to a particular kind of evolutionary debunking threat in a way that my theistic alternative does not. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Is an Ethics without God Possible?)
18 pages, 2142 KiB  
Article
Towards DFO*12—Preliminary Results of a New Chelator for the Complexation of Actinium-225
by Irene V. J. Feiner, Dennis Svatunek, Martin Pressler, Tori Demuth, Xabier Guarrochena, Johannes H. Sterba, Susanne Dorudi, Clemens Pichler, Christoph Denk and Thomas L. Mindt
Pharmaceutics 2025, 17(3), 320; https://doi.org/10.3390/pharmaceutics17030320 - 1 Mar 2025
Viewed by 1411
Abstract
Background: Actinium-225 (225Ac) has gained interest in nuclear medicine for use in targeted alpha therapy (TAT) for the treatment of cancer. However, the number of suitable chelators for the stable complexation of 225Ac3+ is limited. The promising physical [...] Read more.
Background: Actinium-225 (225Ac) has gained interest in nuclear medicine for use in targeted alpha therapy (TAT) for the treatment of cancer. However, the number of suitable chelators for the stable complexation of 225Ac3+ is limited. The promising physical properties of 225Ac result in an increased demand for the radioisotope that is not matched by its current supply. To expand the possibilities for the development of 225Ac-based TAT therapeutics, a new hydroxamate-based chelator, DFO*12, is described. We report the DFT-guided design of dodecadentate DFO*12 and an efficient and convenient automated solid-phase synthesis for its preparation. To address the limited availability of 225Ac, a small-scale 229Th/225Ac generator was constructed in-house to provide [225Ac]AcCl3 for research. Methods: DFT calculations were performed in ORCA 5.0.1 using the BP86 functional with empirical dispersion correction D3 and Becke–Johnson damping (D3BJ). The monomer synthesis over three steps enabled the solid-phase synthesis of DFO*12. The small-scale 229Th/225Ac generator was realized by extracting 229Th from aged 233U material. Radiolabeling of DFO*12 with 225Ac was performed in 1 M TRIS pH 8.5 or 1.5 M NaOAc pH 4.5 for 30 min at 37 °C. Results: DFT calculations directed the design of a dodecadentate chelator. The automated synthesis of the chelator DFO*12 and the development of a small-scale 229Th/225Ac generator allowed for the radiolabeling of DFO*12 with 225Ac quantitatively at 37 °C within 30 min. The complex [225Ac]Ac-DFO*12 indicated good stability in different media for 20 h. Conclusions: The novel hydroxamate-based dodecadentate chelator DFO*12, together with the developed 229Th/225Ac generator, provide new opportunities for 225Ac research for future radiopharmaceutical development and applications in TAT. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Advances in Radiopharmaceuticals for Disease Diagnoses and Therapy)
Show Figures

Graphical abstract

18 pages, 241 KiB  
Article
An Ethics without God That Is Compatible with Darwinian Evolution
by James P. Sterba
Religions 2024, 15(7), 781; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070781 - 27 Jun 2024
Cited by 2 | Viewed by 1676
Abstract
Building on my recent argument that an all-good, all-powerful God is logically incompatible with all the evil in the world, I explore what grounding ethics can have without the God of traditional theism. While theists have argued that ethics is grounded either in [...] Read more.
Building on my recent argument that an all-good, all-powerful God is logically incompatible with all the evil in the world, I explore what grounding ethics can have without the God of traditional theism. While theists have argued that ethics is grounded either in God’s commands and/or in his nature, I show that no such adequate grounding exists, even if my argument—showing that the God of traditional theism is logically incompatible with all the evil in the world—were shown to be unsuccessful, and I further show that such a grounding is impossible, given that my argument is successful. I then go on to provide an account of the norms on which an ethics without God can be appropriately grounded and show how an ethics, so grounded, can be appropriately related to our biological and cultural past, present, and future, as understood through Darwinian evolutionary theory. In this way, I hope to undercut a recent attempt to use Darwinian evolutionary theory to debunk ethics. Full article
(This article belongs to the Section Religions and Humanities/Philosophies)
34 pages, 315 KiB  
Editorial
Forty Contributors: A Response
by James P. Sterba
Religions 2023, 14(11), 1355; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14111355 - 26 Oct 2023
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 1523
Abstract
In July of 2021, I finished guest-editing a Special Issue for Religions on the topic of my book Is a Good God Logically Possible [...] Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
10 pages, 192 KiB  
Article
Sterba’s Problem of Evil and a Penal Colony Theodicy
by Gerald Harrison
Religions 2023, 14(9), 1196; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14091196 - 19 Sep 2023
Viewed by 1322
Abstract
Sterba argues that God would be ethically bound to implement a set of exceptionless evil prevention requirements. However, he argues that the world as we know it is not as it would be if God were applying them. Sterba concludes that God does [...] Read more.
Sterba argues that God would be ethically bound to implement a set of exceptionless evil prevention requirements. However, he argues that the world as we know it is not as it would be if God were applying them. Sterba concludes that God does not exist. In this paper, I offer a penal colony theodicy that will show how the world as we know it is entirely compatible with God’s implementation of such evil prevention requirements. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
30 pages, 605 KiB  
Article
How Did Evil Come into the World? A Primordial Free-Will Theodicy
by Mark Johnston
Religions 2023, 14(3), 402; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030402 - 16 Mar 2023
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 3913
Abstract
James P. Sterba has provided a compelling argument to the effect that given the extent of significant, and indeed even horrendous, evil that an all-good and all-powerful being could have prevented, there is no God. There is a hidden assumption in Sterba’s reasoning, [...] Read more.
James P. Sterba has provided a compelling argument to the effect that given the extent of significant, and indeed even horrendous, evil that an all-good and all-powerful being could have prevented, there is no God. There is a hidden assumption in Sterba’s reasoning, involving an inference from God being able to do anything metaphysically possible (omnipotence) to his being, after creation, able to prevent evil. As what follows shows, that isn’t a purely logical matter. It depends on ruling out a determinate theological account of how creation limits what is then metaphysically possible for God, an account set out in detail below. So Sterba’s argument is not deductively valid, unless that account is incoherent. Accordingly, we are back in the realm of total judgments of theoretical plausibility, and the effects of God-given grace on what then will strike one as the right view to live by. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
6 pages, 190 KiB  
Opinion
Has James Sterba Established a Logical Argument from Evil or Just a Very Good Evidential One?
by Richard Carrier
Religions 2023, 14(3), 307; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030307 - 24 Feb 2023
Viewed by 2064
Abstract
James Sterba’s new treatise advancing a logical argument from evil against the existence of God fails in one respect and succeeds in another. As with all claimants to having found such a thing before him, Sterba fails in properly achieving a logical argument [...] Read more.
James Sterba’s new treatise advancing a logical argument from evil against the existence of God fails in one respect and succeeds in another. As with all claimants to having found such a thing before him, Sterba fails in properly achieving a logical argument from evil. But he succeeds in producing one of the most undefeatable evidential arguments from evil yet published. Elegantly dispatching all the common defenses, Sterba shows that there is no way to avoid the force of his argument against the existence of God without adopting extraordinarily improbable hypotheses that theists can’t even intelligibly articulate. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
17 pages, 273 KiB  
Article
Can Heaven Justify Horrendous Moral Evils? A Postmortem Autopsy
by Asha Lancaster-Thomas
Religions 2023, 14(3), 296; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14030296 - 22 Feb 2023
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 2422
Abstract
James Sterba has recently constructed a new and compelling logical problem of evil that rejects Plantinga’s free-will defense and employs the concept of significant freedom and the Pauline Principle to demonstrate an incompatibility between the existence of horrendous evil and the God of [...] Read more.
James Sterba has recently constructed a new and compelling logical problem of evil that rejects Plantinga’s free-will defense and employs the concept of significant freedom and the Pauline Principle to demonstrate an incompatibility between the existence of horrendous evil and the God of classical monotheism. In response, Jerry L. Walls, among others, has claimed that the doctrine of heaven can explain why God is justified in permitting horrendous evils in the world—an argument known as the afterlife theodicy. In this article, I explore this line of defense against Sterba’s logical problem of evil. I suggest that if the afterlife theodicy is to be effective, it must accept non-speciesist, strong universalism; deny or explicate divinely informed prior consent; reject an elective model of forgiveness; discard postmortem libertarian free will; and explain why God values libertarian free will in earthly life but not in the afterlife. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
5 pages, 180 KiB  
Opinion
Locating the Problem of Evil
by Charles Champe Taliaferro
Religions 2023, 14(2), 228; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020228 - 8 Feb 2023
Viewed by 1468
Abstract
I argue that James Sterba’s argument from evil involves a category mistake. He applies moral principles that pertain to ethical requirements that apply within creation to what may be called the ethics or axiology of creating and sustaining creation. The paper includes reflection [...] Read more.
I argue that James Sterba’s argument from evil involves a category mistake. He applies moral principles that pertain to ethical requirements that apply within creation to what may be called the ethics or axiology of creating and sustaining creation. The paper includes reflection on the relationship between justification and redemption, justice and mercy. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
15 pages, 254 KiB  
Article
A Kantian Response to the Problem of Evil: Living in the Moral World
by Christopher J. Insole
Religions 2023, 14(2), 227; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020227 - 8 Feb 2023
Cited by 3 | Viewed by 2397
Abstract
James Sterba has presented a powerful and existentially sincere form of the problem of evil, arguing that it is logically impossible for God to exist, given that there are powerful moral requirements to prevent evil, where one can, and that these requirements would [...] Read more.
James Sterba has presented a powerful and existentially sincere form of the problem of evil, arguing that it is logically impossible for God to exist, given that there are powerful moral requirements to prevent evil, where one can, and that these requirements would bind an all-powerful and good God, who would indeed be able to prevent such evil. The ‘Kantian’ argument that I set out, if accepted, would undermine the following stage of Sterba’s argument: Significant and especially horrendous evil consequences of immoral actions do obtain all around us, which, if God exists, would have to be through his permission. The Kantian argument will hold that we are able to believe that, in some sense, such horrendous evil consequences do not really obtain, although they appear to. The claim is not that the Kantian argument is ‘persuasive’, but that if some Kantian assumptions are granted, we do have a response to Sterba, which throws open a different way of looking at things. I conclude with some more informal reflections on what we might take away from the Kantian argument, even if we do not accept the deep assumptions, or the progression of the argument. I will not worry too much about demonstrating that this is a ‘correct reading’ of Kant, although I think it is. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
15 pages, 222 KiB  
Article
The “Heaven Ab Initio” Argument from Evil
by Carlo Alvaro
Religions 2023, 14(2), 200; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020200 - 2 Feb 2023
Viewed by 2873
Abstract
Logical and evidential arguments from evil are generally thought to have been rebutted by various refutations, defenses, and theodicies. While disparate, these responses employ similar strategies to show that God has morally sufficient reasons to permit evil and suffering in the world, either [...] Read more.
Logical and evidential arguments from evil are generally thought to have been rebutted by various refutations, defenses, and theodicies. While disparate, these responses employ similar strategies to show that God has morally sufficient reasons to permit evil and suffering in the world, either to preserve human freedom, for the sake of the moral growth of human souls, or to train humans to be able to act freely without sinning once in heaven. In this paper, I defend the heaven ab initio argument from evil (HAIAFE), which demonstrates that God could have accomplished all these goals, without the need for evil and suffering, by creating human beings directly as spiritual beings in a non-physical state of eternal bliss. Moreover, I will argue that the HAIAFE is both a logical argument from evil and a “deodicy”, i.e., a vindication of a deistic god. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
10 pages, 230 KiB  
Article
Against the New Logical Argument from Evil
by Daniel Rubio
Religions 2023, 14(2), 159; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020159 - 28 Jan 2023
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 2006
Abstract
Jim Sterba’s Is a Good God Logically Possible? looks to resurrect J. L. Mackie’s logical argument from evil. Sterba accepts the general framework that theists seeking to give a theodicy have favored since Leibniz invented the term: the search for some greater good [...] Read more.
Jim Sterba’s Is a Good God Logically Possible? looks to resurrect J. L. Mackie’s logical argument from evil. Sterba accepts the general framework that theists seeking to give a theodicy have favored since Leibniz invented the term: the search for some greater good provided or greater evil averted that would justify God in permitting the type and variety of evil we actually observe. However, Sterba introduces a deontic twist, drawing on the Pauline Principle (let us not do evil that good may come) to introduce three deontic side constraints on God’s choice of action. He then splits the possible goods into four categories: first- vs. second-order goods, goods to which we have a right, and goods to which we do not have a right. He argues that his deontic constraints rule out each combination, thereby showing that no God-justifying good is on offer. To defuse the argument, I draw on a pair of ideas from Marilyn McCord Adams: (i) God is outside the bounds of morality, and (ii) God can defeat evils by incorporating them into an incommensurately valuable friendship with each human. Properly appreciated, these show that the new logical argument relies on a false premise that is not easily repaired. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
9 pages, 217 KiB  
Article
Divine Morality or Divine Love? On Sterba’s New Logical Problem of Evil
by Jonathan C. Rutledge
Religions 2023, 14(2), 157; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14020157 - 28 Jan 2023
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 2478
Abstract
In his recent version of the logical problem of evil, James Sterba articulates several moral principles that, on the assumption that God is morally perfect, seem to entail God’s non-existence. Such moral principles, however, only apply to God on the assumption that he [...] Read more.
In his recent version of the logical problem of evil, James Sterba articulates several moral principles that, on the assumption that God is morally perfect, seem to entail God’s non-existence. Such moral principles, however, only apply to God on the assumption that he is a moral agent. I first argue against this assumption by appealing to recent work by Mark Murphy before, secondly, suggesting an alternative way to frame Sterba’s argument in terms of divine love. One can distinguish God’s motivation to promote creaturely welfare on the basis of love from a motivation grounded in morality, and I claim that doing so results in a stronger form of the logical argument. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Do We Now Have a Logical Argument from Evil?)
Back to TopTop