Abnormalities and Return: An Exploration of the Concept Fan 反 in the Laozi
Abstract
:1. Introduction: The Ambiguity of Interpreting Fan
2. Fan, Fu and the Return of Things
You have gone back to your true form while we remain as men!(“The Great and Venerable Teacher” da zong shi 大宗师) (Watson 2013, p. 49)
If the nature is trained, you may return to Virtue, and Virtue at its highest peak is identical with the Beginning.(“Heaven and Earth” Tiandi 天地) (Watson 2013, p. 89)
When within there is purity, fullness, and a return to true form, we have music.(“Mending the Inborn Nature” Shan Xing 缮性) (Watson 2013, p. 122)
‘Culture’ destroyed the substantial; ‘breadth’ drowned the mind; and after this, the people began to be confused and disordered. They had no way to revert to the true form of their inborn nature or to return once more to the Beginning.(“Mending the Inborn Nature”) (Watson 2013, p. 123)
The character fan 反 in these citations are all used to imply “return” (fan 返): indicating that when things or people depart from themselves they need to return to their own original authenticity or natural condition.If the fate of the times had been with them and they could have done great deeds in the world, then they would have returned to Unity and left no trace behind. But the fate of the times was against them and brought them only great hardship in the world, and therefore they deepened their roots, rested in perfection, and waited. This was the way they kept themselves alive.(“Mending the Inborn Nature”) (Watson 2013, p. 124)24
3. Why Is Return Necessary? “Desires Arise” and “Disasters Arise”
Dao and the sages act non-coercively and softly; correspondingly, it allows the myriad things and people to be on their own accord, to self-transform, and to accomplish on their own. At the same time, this non-coercive action and softness of Dao or sage rulers manifest as following the self-soing and self-transformation of all things (Dao emulates the self-so). Chapters thirty-seven and fifty-seven both make the connection between Dao and the myriad things as well as the connection between the sage rulers and the common people explicit:The myriad things and beings depend on it for their generation, but it does not give orders. Achievements are completed but it does not claim the name of having done it. It clothes all things as with a garment, and makes no assumption of being their overlord, constantly without desires, its name is in the minute; all things and beings return to it, but do not know their master, it may be named great. That is why the sage can accomplish the great by his not acting on the great, thus, he can accomplish the great.
Dao constantly acts non-coercively and nothing is left undone. If the marquises and kings can maintain this, all things transform on their own.(Chapter 37)
The relationship between Dao and all things is harmonious and cooperative: Dao generates all things, it follows them, and under its guardianship, they self-transform. We cannot see in this any possibility of things going astray or becoming abnormal. Then, where does the problem emerge?Therefore, the sages say: “I act non-coercively and the common people transform on their own; I cherish equilibrium, and the common people order themselves; I am non-interfering in my governance, and the common people prosper themselves; I am objectless in my desires, and the common people are of themselves like unworked wood.”(Chapter 57)
The key here is the saying “transforming and desires arise, I subdue it through the simplicity of the nameless.” The transformation in “the myriad things will then transform on their own” is normal. Laozi does not object to change and differentiation (“transform on their own”), he maintains that grand simplicity becomes a variety of vessels (“when unworked wood is split it is made into vessels, when the sages are employed they are made into head officials”). However, according to chapter thirty-two, differentiation and employment must be limited, if it exceeds limitations then estrangements happen:If the kings and marquises can guard it, the myriad beings and things will then transform on their own. Transforming and desires arise, I subdue it through the simplicity of the nameless. The simplicity of the nameless will lead them to be without desires. Not desiring is to be in equilibrium, the whole world will be ordered on their own accord.
We can see from the phrase “I then subdue it through the simplicity of the nameless” that “desires arise” is not normal. The character for arising (zuo 作) comes from the pictograph of a person lifting up his body. The meaning of this character was then extended to mean “to arise” and “to begin.” The character for desires (yu 欲) also incorporates many meanings, such as to want, to hope, to wish, to demand, to need, to take pleasure in, and so forth. In this sense, “desires arise” should not pose problems.When we start to regulate the world, we introduce names. But once names have been assigned, we must also know when to stop. Knowing when to stop is how to avoid danger.
Not displaying what can be desired, will lead the people’s hearts to be non-chaotic…constantly leading the people to absence of knowledge and absence of desires, will allow those who are wise to not dare to act.(Chapter 3)
Display a genuineness like raw silk and embrace simplicity like unworked wood, lesson your concern for yourself and reduce your desires.(Chapter 19)
Consistent in its absence of desires, it can be named minute.(Chapter 34)
The simplicity of the nameless will lead them to be without desires. Not desiring is to be in equilibrium, the whole world is ordered on its own accord.(Chapter 37)
There is no crime more onerous than greed, no misfortune more devastating than avarice. And no calamity that brings with it more grief than insatiability.(Chapter 46)28
I am objectless in my desires and the people are of themselves like uncarved wood.(Chapter 57)
As long as human beings exist, they will desire to fulfill life’s basic needs. Laozi certainly cannot, nor should he object to desires in this sense. Laozi does, however, object to excessive desires phrased in the text as “desirable,” “desire to obtain,” and other greedy activities or cravings. In response, he advocates “objectless desires” (wuyu 无欲), referring to desires that are harmful and improper, not to aspirations and needs in general. The “Explaining Laozi” chapter of the Han Feizi incorporates an explanation of Laozi’s phrase: “there is no crime more onerous than greed.” According to the explanation in the Han Feizi, “can be desired” (keyu 可欲) signifies excessive desires that may lead to harmful results:Therefore, the sages desire not to desire, do not esteem goods that are difficult to obtain.(Chapter 64)
Laozi opposes possessions and plunder, opposes the monopolization and centralization of wealth, or in other words, is against corruption and greed. He advocated to dismiss and overcome desires of this sort. This is precisely what chapters twenty-nine and forty-four tell us:If people have desires, their plans and calculations will become confused. If plans and calculations become confused, desires will deepen. If desires deepen, the perverted mind will prevail. If the perverted mind prevails, undertakings will be led astray and will cut off. If undertakings are lead astray and are cut off, misfortunes and difficulties arise. Looking at the matter from this perspective, misfortunes and difficulties are born of the perverted mind and the perverted mind is led by things that can be desired. Things that can be desired are [of two] sorts: if coming [to the country], they entice good people to do evil; if leaving [the country], they cause good people to suffer misfortunes. If evil arises, it encroaches upon and weakens the ruler above. If misfortunes arrive, the people suffer many afflictions. Thus, things that can be desired encroach upon and weaken the ruler above, while they afflict the people below. To encroach upon and weaken the ruler above and afflict the people below is a grave crime indeed. Thus, it is said: “there is no calamity greater than things that can be desired.” This is why the sage is not enticed by the five colors nor is he sullied by lewd music. The enlightened ruler scorns amusements and addictions and avoids the lewd and the lascivious trifles and dazzling beauties.29
Eschew the excessive, the superlative, and the extravagant.(Chapter 29)
To achieve social justice and fairness, Laozi advocated for the purity of the heart-mind and abandonment of desires. This shows that he objected to greediness. He maintained that the “way of heaven” (tiandao 天道) and great sages benefit in a different manner from those who monopolize and dictate, they “diminish superabundance and supplement deficiency” instead of “taking away from those who have not enough to add to his own superabundance:”Your reputation or your person—which is dearer to you? Your person or your property—which one is worth more? Gaining or losing—which is the greater scourge? Miserliness is certain to come at a huge cost; the hoarding of wealth is certain to lead to heavy losses. Therefore, those who know contentment avoid disgrace, and those who know where to stop avoid danger. They will be long-enduring.(Chapter 44)
The way of heaven is like archers drawing their bows. To hit something high in the air, they pull the string downward; to hit something lower, they pull the string upward. When they have drawn the string too far back, they let some go, and when they have not drawn it far enough, they pull harder. The way of heaven is also to let some go where there is excess and to augment where there is not enough. The way of human beings on the other hand is not like this at all. It is instead to take away from those who do not have enough in order to give more to those who already have too much. Who then in having too much is able to draw on this excess to make an offering to the world? Perhaps only those who have Dao.(Chapter 77)
Laozi defined profound efficacy as “generating without possessing, assisting yet making no claim, rearing yet not lording.” This definition stresses the fact that it generates but does not possess. According to the view that Laozi held towards desires, we can tell that the word “arise” in “desires arise” (that is, greed) is one of the reasons abnormalities and estrangements can happen. Another abnormal arising is “errors arise” (wangzuo 妄作) as recorded in chapter sixteen:The sages do not accumulate things. Yet the more they have done for others, the more they have gained themselves; the more they have given to others, the more they have gotten themselves. Thus, the way of heaven is to benefit without harming; the way of the sages is to do without contending.(Chapter 81)
According to the definition in the “Explanation of Characters,” errors (wang 妄) as in “errors arise” means chaos (luan 乱). The chapter “On Shepherding the People” (Mu Min 牧民) in the Guanzi 管子 tells us that: “if the sovereign lacks proper restraint, the people will behave recklessly.”30 “Twenty-five Years to Lord Ai” (Ai Gong ershiwu nian 哀公二十五年) in the Zuozhuan 左传 says: “those who are prone to taking sole possession over profits are in error.” Those cases of errors all refer to improper and illegitimate conduct (being in an uncontrolled state or situation, committing outrages, etc.). The reason errors arise is because one “does not know permanence.” Another arising in chapter sixteen is “arise together” (bingzuo 并作). If there is no problem with the word “together” (bing 并) then we should take a look whether the word “arise” is problematic. In the Hengxian恆先text of the Shanghai Museum bamboo collection we find:The myriad things arise together, so I observe their return. The things in the world are manifold, they all return to their root. Returning to the root means stillness, it is called returning to the propensity of things. Returning to the propensity of things is called constancy, knowing constancy is called clarity. Not knowing constancy—errors arise, and the unfortunate occurs. Knowing constancy is to be accommodating, accommodating is tolerance, tolerance is kingliness, kingliness is heavenly, heavenly is Dao, Dao is enduring. To the end of one’s days one will be free of danger.
According to the textual context, arising refers to illegitimate and improper arising. Arising as it appears in “arise together” may belong to the same category as “desires arise” and “errors arise,” meaning that it refers to illegitimate conduct. Furthermore, if things were to self-transform properly, return would not be an issue. The estrangement of things generally emerges while they arise together (there already is estrangement when they arise together).Auspicious appropriateness, beneficial craft,31 and diverse things emerge from arising. When there is arising, there is an endeavor; when there is no arising, there is no endeavor. Regarding the endeavors of heaven: they will arise of themselves to become endeavors. How then could they not be continued?32
The forged chapter “Successful Completion of the War” (Wucheng 武成) in the ancient “Book of Documents” (Shangshu 尚书) we find:Not to hunt when there was no business in the way was deemed an act of irreverence. To hunt without observing the rulers was deemed cruelty to the creatures of heaven.
“Creatures of heaven” literally means “all things in the world.” That is the same as saying “all things” (fuwu 夫物). The Guodian 郭店 version of the Laozi says: “the heavenly Dao is encompassing” (yuanyuan 员员). If we read the characters yuanyuan 员员as yuanyuan 圆圆 (circling): “the heavenly Dao circles around,” then not only does it not match the following phrase: “each returns to their roots,” it also has no connection to the previous phrase: “the myriad things arise together.” In Laozi’s philosophy, the issue of going back and returning can only be applied to the myriad things or common people. This problem does not exist for Dao or the heavenly Dao. As we see in the following quotations, all the occurrences of “heavenly Dao” or “Dao of heaven” do not mention the issue of return:The present king of Shang is without principle, cruel and destructive to the creatures of heaven, injurious and tyrannical to the multitudes of the people.
To withdraw oneself when the work proceeds—this is the Dao of heaven.(Chapter 9)
Not to look out the window—to know the Dao of heaven.(Chapter 47)
The Dao of heaven—without contending, it is good at winning.(Chapter 73)
The Dao of heaven is like flexing a bow.(Chapter 77)
The Dao of heaven does not establish any kinships, it is always with the good person.(Chapter 79)
We conclude that the “heavenly Dao” as written in the Guodian version is clearly an error; the original must have been “creatures of heaven” (tianwu 天物) or “all things” (fuwu 夫物). Moreover, in the Zaiyou 在宥chapter of the Zhuangzi we see: “the myriad beings and things are manifold, each returns to its roots.”The Dao if heaven benefits without doing harm.(Chapter 81)
Promoting those of superior character, prizing property that is hard to come by, and making show of what might be desired refer to bad conduct. Normally, the ruler engaging in political affairs should abide by traits of Dao such as non-coercive action, purity and equilibrium, simplicity, softness, non-contending and others. But in reality, since rulers assume the utmost power and have the most wealth, they are the ones that most easily betray Dao and give rise to errors. The outcomes of their malicious actions are the most severe.Not promoting those of superior character, will save the common people from being contentious, not prizing property that is hard to come by, will save them from becoming thieves, not making a show of what might be desired, will save them from becoming disgruntled.
The only things we have to fear in traveling the grand thoroughfare (Dao) are the turn-offs. The grand thoroughfare is perfectly level and straight, yet people have a great fondness for mountain trails. Their court is impeccably clean, yet the fields are overgrown with weeds and the granaries stand empty. Their clothing is embroidered, and colorful and sharp swords hang at their sides; they are stuffed with food and have wealth and property to throw away. This is called highway robbery, which ought not to be confused with Dao.(Chapter 53)
A very dim and pessimistic view towards humanity and civilization comes from political estrangements. Chapter eighteen expresses the degeneration and decline of civilization:The people’s hunger is because those above are eating too much in taxes—this is why they are hungry. The people’s lack of order is because those above manipulate them—this is why they are not properly ordered. And the people’s scoffing at death is because those above are exacting so much from life—this is why they scoff at death. It is precisely those who do not kill themselves in living who are more enlightened than those who treasure life.(Chapter 75)
According to the Confucian view, authoritative conduct (ren 仁), appropriateness (yi 义), wisdom (zhi 智), erudition (慧), filiality (xiao 孝), parental affection (ci 慈) and upright ministers (zhong chen 忠臣) are major ethical values and ideals. However, for the Laozi, they are calamitous outcomes resulting in the abandonment of the grand Dao. Surprisingly, the terms wisdom and erudition, filiality and parental affection, and upright ministers become synonyms to the notions of great duplicity, disharmony, and troubled times. For the Laozi, these notions become an unstoppable force that brings to the decline of one’s true nature and genuine values. The phrase “when the grand Dao is abandoned that authoritative conduct and appropriateness appear,” tells us that the decline of Dao is a product of historical advancement and the passage of time. Chapter thirty-eight depicts the process of the decline of Dao and De (德):It is when the grand Dao is abandoned that authoritative conduct and appropriateness appear. It is when wisdom and erudition arise, that great duplicity appears. It is when the six family relationships are disharmonious, that filiality and parental affection appear. It is when the state has fallen into troubled times, that the upright ministers appear.
Similar to many later commentaries, Han Feizi notes that ritual propriety is the source of passivity and other problems; however, his interpretation on the previous phrases are unique. He viewed Dao, excellence, authoritative conduct, appropriateness and ritual propriety as values that are contained in one another and not as an ongoing process of deterioration.33 This may be due to the variation in textual versions:Only when we have lost sight of Dao is there excellence (de), only when we have lost sight of excellence is there authoritative conduct, only when we have lost sight of authoritative conduct is there appropriateness, and only when we have lost sight of appropriateness is there ritual propriety. As for ritual propriety, it is the thinnest veneer of doing one’s best and making good one’s word, and it is the first sign of trouble.
Regardless of whether Han Feizi himself copied it wrong or this version was widespread at his time, the text cited is most likely incorrect. Two reasons for this assumption are (1) the transmitted and excavated materials are identical, and (2) since ritual propriety appears after the decline of civilization and becomes the first sign of trouble, it corresponds to the situation of a degenerated civilization rather than to a sequence of values which subsume one another. Thus, the “Knowledge Rambling in the North” (zhibeiyou 知北遊) chapter of the Zhuangzi offers a more precise understanding and commentary of this passage:When we have lost sight of Dao then we lose sight of excellence, when we lose sight of excellence we then lose sight of authoritative conduct, when we lose sight of authoritative conduct we then lose sight of appropriateness, when we lose sight of appropriateness we then lose sight of ritual propriety.
He Shanggong and Wang Bi interpreted this passage through the process of decline as well. It now becomes evident why Laozi advocated return. It is because things, especially human beings and their affairs, produce various abnormalities and estrangements in their reality and historical processes.Those who know do not speak; those who speak do not know, and hence the sage conveys his instructions without the use of speech. Dao cannot be made ours by constraint; its characteristics will not come to us (at our call). Authoritative conduct may be practiced; appropriateness may be partially attended to; by ritual propriety men impose on one another. Hence it is said: “When the Dao was lost, excellence appeared. When excellence was lost, authoritative conduct appeared. When authoritative conduct was lost, appropriateness appeared. When appropriateness was lost, ritual propriety appeared. Ritual propriety is but the (unsubstantial) flowers of Dao, and the commencement of disorder.” Hence, “he practices Dao, diminishes daily. He diminishes it and again diminishes it, until he arrives at non-coercive action. Having arrived at this non-coercive action, there is nothing that he does not do.” Here now there is something, a regularly fashioned utensil—if you wanted to make it return to the original condition of its materials, would it not be difficult to make it do so? Could any but the great man accomplish this easily?
4. Whence Is the Journey Back? “The Simplicity of the Nameless” and “Returning to the Root”
In this chapter, terms such as the newborn baby, the limitless, and simplicity offer the goal of return. The return of things is then returning to the state of a newborn baby, returning to the state of the limitless, and returning to simplicity. In the Laozi, the newborn baby, simplicity, and water (which “comes nearest to Dao”) are metaphors for Dao. Simplicity (pu 朴) in this chapter is equivalent to the response chapter thirty-seven gives to the problem of desires rising: “realign them with the unnamed simplicity.”Know the male yet safeguard the female and be a river gorge to the world. As a river gorge to the world, you will not lose your permanent efficacy, and not losing your permanent efficacy, you return to the state of a newborn baby. Know the clean yet safeguard the soiled and be a valley to the world. As a valley to the world, your permanent efficacy will be ample, and with ample potency, you return to the state of simplicity. Know the white yet safeguard the black and be a model for the world. As a model for the world, your permanent potency will not be wanting, and with your potency not wanting, you return to the state of the limitless.
Chapter nineteen expresses decrease in a more revolutionary and radical manner:Not promoting those of superior character, will save the common people from becoming contentious. Not prizing property that is hard to come by, will save them from becoming thieves. Now making a show of what might be desired, will save them from becoming disgruntled. It is for this reason that in the proper governing by the sages: they empty the heart-and-minds of the people and fill their stomachs, they weaken their aspirations and strengthen their bones, ever teaching the common people to be unprincipled in their knowing and objectless in their desires, they keep the hawkers of knowledge at bay. It is simply in doing things non-coercively that everything is governed properly.
One of the characteristics of Dao in the Laozi is simplicity. Returning to Dao and going back to the roots is also returning to simplicity and going back to genuineness. As a social ideal, Laozi imagines a “small country with few people.” According to his description, this ideal society makes very little use of utensils, does not have wars and conflicts, and people lead a happy life: “relishing their food, finding beauty in their garments, enjoying their customs, finding security in their homes.”Cut off sagacity and get rid of wisdom and the benefit to the common people will be a hundredfold. Cut of authoritative conduct and get rid of appropriateness and the common people will return to filiality and parental affection. Cut off cleverness and get rid of personal profit and there will be no more brigands and thieves. But these three sayings as they stand are still lacking and need to be supplemented by the following: display a genuineness like raw silk and embrace simplicity, lessen your concern for yourself and reduce your desires.34
Zhuangzi further imagines a more primitive state described as an “age of perfect virtue”:Have you alone never heard of that age of Perfect Virtue? Long ago, in the time of Yong Cheng, Da Ting, Bo Huang, Zhong Yang, Li Lu, Li Xu, Xian Yuan, He Xu, Zun Lu, Zhu Rong, Fu Xi, and Shen Nong, the people knotted cords and used them. They relished their food, admired their clothing, enjoyed their customs, and were content with their houses. Though neighboring states were within sight of one another and could hear the cries of one another’s dogs and chickens, the people grew old and died without ever traveling beyond their own borders. At a time such as this, there was nothing but the most perfect order.(“Rifling Trunks” Qu Qie 胠篋, Watson 2013, pp. 71–72)
As we can see from the Zhuangzi, the more primitive and natural things are, the better. This is the phenomenon of “beautiful imagination” that people have towards ancient long-gone historical periods. This Daoist historical image differs from the perfect historical staged imagined by other philosophers in pre-Qin times. For example, the Mohist and Legalist scholars believed that the natural, ancient, and primitive situation is not good, while civilization is the desired result of leaving a primitive situation. For instance, Mozi 墨子 believed that people in ancient times did not know how to build their homes, did not know how to make clothes, did not know the proper way to eat and drink, nor did they know how to manufacture means of transportation. Their lives were simply inconvenient. Thus, to meet the needs of human beings, the sage kings created civilization:The people have their constant inborn nature. To weave for their clothing, to till for their food—this is the Virtue they share. They are one in it and not partisan, and it is called the Emancipation of Heaven. Therefore, in a time of Perfect Virtue, the gait of men is slow and ambling; their gaze is steady and mild. In such an age, mountains have no paths or trails, lakes no boats or bridges. The ten thousand things live species by species, one group settled close to another. Birds and beasts form their flocks and herds; grass and trees grow to fullest height. So it happens that you can tie a cord to the birds and beasts and lead them about or bend down the limb and peer into the nest of the crow and the magpie. In this age of Perfect Virtue, men live the same as birds and beasts, group themselves side by side with the ten thousand things. Who then knows anything about “gentleman” or “petty man”? Dull an unwitting, men have no wisdom; thus their Virtue does not depart from them. Dull and unwitting, they have no desire; this is called uncarved simplicity. In uncarved simplicity, the people attain their true nature.(“Horses Hoofs” Mati 马蹄, Watson 2013, pp. 65–66)
Similar to the account in the Mozi, Han Feizi believed that people’s lives encountered various difficulties in the distant past, middle antiquity, and even in near history. The sages and great people appeared in time to solve the problems encountered in each era:Primitive people, before the art of building houses and palaces was known, lingered by the mounds and lived in caves. It was damp and injurious to health. Thereupon the sage-kings built houses and palaces. The guiding principles for these buildings were these: the house shall be built high enough to avoid the damp and moisture; the walls thick enough to keep out the wind and cold; the roof strong enough to stand snow, frost, rain, and dew; and the walls in the palace high enough to observe the propriety of the sexes. These are sufficient…Before clothing was known, the primitive people wore coats of furs and belts of straw. They were neither light and warm in winter nor light and cool in summer. The sage-king thought this did not satisfy the needs of man. So, he taught the women to produce silk and flax and to weave cloth and linen, therewith to make clothing for the people. The guiding principles for clothing were these: In winter the underwear shall be made of spun-silk as to be light and warm. In summer it shall be made of coarse flax so as to be light and cool. And this is sufficient…Before the art of cooking was known, primitive people ate only vegetables and lived in separation. Thereupon the sage taught the men to attend to farming and to plant trees to supply the people with food. And the sole purpose of securing food is to increase energy, satisfy hunger, strengthen the body and appease the stomach. He was frugal in spending wealth and simple in habits of living, and so the people became rich and the country orderly…Before the primitive people know how to make boats and carts they could neither carry a heavy load nor travel a great distance. Thereupon the sage-king made boats and carts to facilitate the people. The boats and carts were made durable and convenient so that they would carry much and travel far. Such an undertaking takes little wealth but produces many benefits. Naturally the people found it agreeable and convenient. The people were not tired out and yet the ruler’s needs were all supplied. So, people were attracted to him.(Mozi, Book I, “Indulgence in Excess” Ci Guo 辭過)
In the historical narratives by Mozi and Han Feizi, we learn that they differ from Zhuangzi. They did not beautify ancient times, on the contrary, they confirmed the rationality and legitimacy for human beings to depart from the most ancient stage, and further affirmed the advancement of civilization. However, at the same time, they were not merely theorists of historical progression as they did not hold a linear view of history. In different extents, their way of thinking was similar to the Confucian “ancient based reconstruction.” Overall, according to Mozi’s narrative, social practices and political conduct in his days betrayed the original intentions and aspirations of the sages who created civilization. He essentially idealized the early stages in the history of the sages’ creation. According to the characteristics of different historical periods, Han Feizi believed that civilization and way of government in each period had its particular rationality and legitimacy. This means that past governance cannot be idealized, and it cannot be used to measure future generations. It also means that future generations and the world at present must adopt methods of governance that suits best their needs:In the most ancient times, when men were few and creatures numerous, human beings could not overcome the birds, beasts, insects, and reptiles. Then a sage appeared who fashioned nests of wood to protect men from harm. The people were delighted and made him ruler of the world, calling him the Nest Builder. The people lived on fruits, berries, mussels, and clams—things rank and evil-smelling that hurt their bellies, so that many of them fell ill. Then a sage appeared who drilled with sticks and produced fire with which to transform the rank and putrid foods. The people were delighted and made him ruler of the world, calling him the Drill Man. In the age of middle antiquity there was a great flood in the world, but Gun and Yu of the Xia dynasty opened up the channels for the water. In the age of recent antiquity Jie and Zhou ruled in a violent and perverse way, but Tang of the Yin dynasty and Wu of the Zhou dynasty overthrew them.(Han Feizi, Chapter 49 “The Five Vermin”, Wudu 五蠹)35
Han Feizi’s famous theory of historical stages also comes to illustrate this point. According to his schema, society in ancient times strove for morality, society in middle antiquity strove for wisdom, and society in his time strove for power.36 Han Feizi did not say that striving for morality or wisdom is bad, on the contrary, he praises it. However, he did maintain that they were merely suitable for society in ancient times and middle antiquity. Society in his time strove for power. If they were to strive for morality and wisdom like in past times, it would be no different from the stump watcher waiting for rabbits.Now if anyone had built wooden nests or drilled for fire in the time of the Xia dynasty, Gun and Yu would have laughed at him, and if anyone had tried to open channels for the water during the Yin or Zhou dynasties, Tang and Wu would have laughed at him. This being so, if people in the present age go about exalting the ways of Yao, Shun, Yu, Tang, and Wu, the sages of today are bound to laugh at them. For the sage does not try to practice the ways of antiquity or to abide by a fixed standard but examines the affairs of the age and takes what precautions are necessary.(Han Feizi, Chapter 49) (Watson 2003, p. 98)
The method to heal the ill situation of civilization is not by adding things, but only through reduction—that is the reduction of all the extra and unnecessary things (on behalf of Dao decrease daily). Appealing to Dao for assistance is to give up and eliminate civilized alternatives, to return to the origin of Dao and its efficacy, thereby returning to the original state of all things. This is the fundamental solution and way to escape the illness of civilization. Reductionism in science believes in restoring the natural disposition of things. Laozi and Zhuangzi want to restore the natural state of things through return. Strictly speaking, we cannot go back in history, nor can we erase events that already passed. The place where civilization degenerates is also the place where it should change. When things return to themselves they rebuild a better self. This happens over a progressing course of time rather than in a repetition of the past. Similarly, Laozi’s philosophy of return, on the surface, may seem to be saying that things ought to return to themselves by returning to their past. However, what this philosophy actually strives for is change in the present and advancement in the future.As these attitudes pertain to Dao, they are called indulgence and unseemliness. Such excess is so generally despised, that even those who want things, cannot abide it.
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Bi, Xiujie 毕秀洁. 2010. Dui fan fan gujin zi de chongxin kaocha 对 “反、返” 古今字的重新考察. Jiangnan daxue xuebao 江南大学学报 (ren wen shehui kexue ban 人文社会科学版), September 9. [Google Scholar]
- Brindley, Erica F., Paul R. Goldin, and Esther S. Klein. 2013. A Philosophical Translation of the Heng Xian. Dao 12: 145–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chen, Guying 陈鼓应. 2003. Laozi jinzhu jinyi 老子今注今译. Beijing 北京: Shangwu yinshuguan 商务印书馆. [Google Scholar]
- Dong, Shan 董珊. 2004. Chujian Hengxian “xiangyi liqiao” jieshi 楚简恒先“祥宜利巧”解释. Jianbo yanjiu wang 简帛研究网. Available online: https://www.jianbo.org/ (accessed on 11 November 2016).
- Feng, Youlan 冯友兰. 1984. Laozi zhexue 老子哲学. In San song tang xueshu wenji 三松堂学术文集. Beijing: Beijing University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Feng, Youlan 冯友兰. 2000. Zhongguo zhexueshi 中国哲学史, and San songtang quanji 三松堂全集. Zhengzhou 郑州: Henan renmin chubanshe 河南人民出版社, vol. 2. [Google Scholar]
- Goldin, Paul R., ed. 2013. Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Han Fei. New York: Springer Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ikeda, Tomohisa. 2006a. Laozi. Tokyo: Eastern Books Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ikeda, Tomohisa. 2006b. Mawangdui chutu wenxian yizhu congshu 马王堆出土文献译注丛书. Tokyo: Jigu shuyuan 汲古书院. [Google Scholar]
- Ikeda, Tomohisa. 2014. Metaphysics and Nature in Laozi’s Thought. East Asian Cultural Exchange Studies 7: 1–19. (In Japanese). [Google Scholar]
- Jiang, Xichang 蒋锡昌. 1988. Laozi Jiaogu 老子校诂. Chengdu 成都: Chengdu guji shudian 成都古籍书店. [Google Scholar]
- Li, Cunshan 李存山. 2008. Laozi 老子. Zhengzhou 郑州: Zhongzhou guji chubanshe 中州古籍出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Liao, W. K. 1939. The Complete Works of Han Fei Tzu. London: A. Probsthain. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, Xiaogan 刘笑敢. 2006. Laozi Gujin: wu zhong duikan yu xiping yinlun 老子古今: 五种对勘与析评引论. Beijing: China Social Sciences Press, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Lu, Yusan 卢育三. 1995. Laozi shiyi 老子释义. Tianjin 天津: Tianjin guji chubanshe 天津古籍出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Ma, Shulun 马叙伦. 1956. Laozi Zhenggu 老子正诂. Beijing: Guji chubanshe 古籍出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Rickett, Allyn. 1998. Guanzi: Political, Economic, and Philosophical Essays from Early China. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Ka 王卡. 1993. Laozi Daodejing Heshanggong Zhangju 老子道德经河上公章句. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中华书局. [Google Scholar]
- Wang, Shumin 王叔岷. 2007. Laozi sixiang gailun 老子思想概论. In Xianqin daofa sixiang jianggao 先秦道法思想讲稿. Beijing 北京: Zhonghua shuju 中华书局. [Google Scholar]
- Watson, Burton. 2003. Han Feizi: Basic Writings. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Watson, Burton. 2013. The Complete Works of Zhuangzi. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Xu, Kangsheng 许抗生. 1982. Boshu Laozi zhuyi yu yanjiu 帛书老子注译与研究. Hangzhou: Zhejiang renmin chubanshe 浙江人民出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, Dainian 张岱年. 1982. Zhongguo zhexue dagang 中国哲学大纲. Beijing 北京: Zhongguo shehui kexue chubanshe 中国社会科学出版社. [Google Scholar]
- Zhang, Dainian 张岱年. 1997. Zhongguo gudai bianzhengfa sixiang fawei 中国古代辩证法思想发微. In Zhang Dainian quanji 张岱年全集. Shijiazhuang: Hebei renmin chubanshe, vol. 5. [Google Scholar]
- Zhu, Qianzhi 朱谦之. 1984. Laozi jiaoshi 老子校释. Beijing: Zhonghua shuju中华书局. [Google Scholar]
1 | Methodologically speaking, a concept and terminology may be used in different meanings for different philosophers or even for a one specific philosopher. There is complete similarity between the ambiguity of texts and the different senses in which people employ them; but equally true, it is entirely possible for people to use the same concept in similar meanings. Those two situations are generally applicable to the concept of fan in the Laozi. In fact, whether it combines meanings or has only a single meaning depends on our own interpretation. If we say that in different linguistic contexts people employ similar notions, its meaning may be the same or different. Within a single linguistic context, using a specific word in the same place generally means that it should have only one meaning and cannot have two or multiple meanings at the same time (although there are meanings beyond language), otherwise, understanding and interpreting a text becomes impossible, communication and language referring to actions also become impossible. Setting out from this point, we can only say that the interpretation of concepts within a single text and linguistic context may have different possibilities, but we cannot say that a concept has multiple meanings within one location at one time. In fact, deciphering the exact meaning of the concept requires a substantive examination. In regard to this issue, see (Lu 1995, pp. 188–89). |
2 | |
3 | For this interpretation see (Chen 2003, pp. 170–71, 226; Lu 1995, pp. 128, 188–89; Li 2008, pp. 80, 99; Ikeda 2006a, pp. 20, 276). |
4 | Jiang Xichang 蒋锡昌 maintains that the concept of return in the entire philosophical and thought system in the Laozi is of primary importance and views it as having a single meaning with many intentions. See (Jiang 1988, pp. 264–68). |
5 | The Guodian 郭店 bamboo slips and the Mawangdui 马王堆 silk manuscripts do not have this phrase. The Peking University Han Dynasty version has “moving about, reaching everywhere and in no danger”. |
6 | There are also people who explain it as “opposites,” such as Feng Youlan 冯友兰. See (Feng 2000, p. 412). |
7 | See (Jiang 1988, p. 170). |
8 | |
9 | |
10 | |
11 | |
12 | Translated by Queen, Sarah A., in (Goldin 2013, p. 241). |
13 | |
14 | As for what “distance” and “return” refer to, I agree with Ikeda Tomohisa’s explanation, as for what “great” and “departure” refer to, my interpretation differs from his. |
15 | See (Lu 1995, p. 188; Liu 2006, pp. 421–22). |
16 | Wang Bi 王弼 commented that “return” refers to returning to absence (wu 无). The contemporary scholar Zhu Qianzhi 朱谦之 and many others adopt this reading. See (Zhu 1984, p. 165). |
17 | See (Ikeda 2006b, p. 20). |
18 | |
19 | See (K. Wang 1993, p. 255). Ikeda Tomohisa also interprets the meaning of this character as “opposites” (profound efficacy is opposite to things (wu 物)). See (Ikeda 2006a, p. 117). |
20 | |
21 | |
22 | Ma Shulun 马叙伦does not explain the character yu 与 in chapter sixty-five, but we may conclude that this character would be explained in the same manner as chapter seventy-nine. See (Ma 1956, p. 197). |
23 | |
24 | There are more examples of fan 反 as fan 返 in the Zhuangzi: “do not let what is human wipe out what is heavenly; do not let what is purposeful wipe out what is fated; do not let [the desire for] gain lead you after fame. Be cautious, guard it, and do not lose it—this is what I mean by returning to the True.” (“Autumn Floods” Qiushui 秋水, Watson 2013, p. 133); “To him there is no east or west—he begins in the Dark Obscurity and returns to the Great Thoroughfare.” (“Autumn Floods”, Watson 2013, p. 136); “Here is a man of the Middle Kingdom, neither yin nor yang, living between heaven and earth. For a brief time only, he will be a man, and then he will return to the Ancestor. Look at him from the standpoint of the Source, and his life is a mere gathering together of breath.” (“Knowledge Wandered North” Zhibeiyou 知北游, Watson 2013, p. 181); “Driving their bodies and natures on and on they drown in the ten thousand things and, to the end of their days never turn back. Pitiful, are they not?” (Xu wu gui 徐无鬼, Watson 2013, p. 204); “Keeping the scholars of the world from returning to the Source, capriciously setting up ideals of ‘filial piety’ and ‘brotherliness’ all the time hoping to worm your way into favor with the lords of the fiefs or the rich and eminent!.” (“Robber Zhi” Dao Zhi 盗跖, Watson 2013, p. 253). |
25 | Fu 复in chapter fifty-eight speaks of the transitions between straightforwardness and surprise, going well and dark and ominous “the straightforward reverts to surprise and what is going well again becomes dark and ominous.”; and fu in the phrase: “return to what most people have passed over” in chapter sixty-four is mostly interpreted as “to correct.” In the “Seal of Virtue Complete” (De Chongfu 德充符) chapter of the Zhuangzi it says: “This toeless cripple is still anxious to learn to make up for (fubu 复补) the evil of his former conduct.” “Fu 复” in “fubu 复补” should be understood as “to make up for” or “to compensate,” similar to the phrase in the Liji 礼记: “When the mourning is ended, will they not resume (fu 复) the marriage ceremonies?” Zheng Xuan 郑玄 explained this “fu 复” in terms of “compensation.” Like in the Zhuangzi, fu has nothing to do with correction. Therefore, in chapter sixty-four of the Laozi we should read fu in the phrase “return to what people have passed over” as “to forgive.” A similar usage is found in the “Spring and Autumn Annals of Lǚ” (Lǚshi Chunqiu 吕氏春秋): “thus we shall forgive the crimes of the Qin minister of defense.” |
26 | Translator’s note: for the sake of clarity in translation I do distinguish between fu 复 and fugui 复归. Fugui as a compound is thereby translated as “return again” instead of simply “return.” |
27 | See (Ikeda 2014, pp. 1–19). |
28 | The first phrase is missing in the Wang Bi version. In the Guodian version it says: “there is no crime worse than excessive desires”; “there is none greater” in the phrase “there is no greater calamity than insatiability” is recorded in the “Explaining Lao” chapter of the Han Feizi, the Mawangdui Laozi silk manuscript, and the Guodian bamboo version as: “no calamity that brings more grief.” |
29 | Translation excerpted from (Goldin 2013, p. 238). The commentary to the phrase “no misfortune more devastating than avarice” in the “Explaining Lao” chapter of the Han Feizi also clarifies that both ‘insatiability’ and ‘not knowing contentment’ refer to greedy conduct: People have neither fur nor feathers. Unclad, they cannot resist the cold. Above they do not belong to heaven and below they do not cleave to the earth. Rather, they consider the stomach and intestines as their fundamental root because if they do not eat they cannot survive. This is why they cannot avoid possessing minds that desire material benefit. If they cannot eradicate this mind desirous of material benefit, they grow anxious. Therefore, the sage wears just enough to resist cold and eats just enough to satiate hunger and so he is free from anxiety. Most people, however, are not like this. Whether you are as important as a regional lord or as unimportant as a person who merely possesses a surfeit of a thousand pieces of gold, you cannot eradicate the anxiety that comes along with the desire to obtain material benefit. Now the convict may receive a pardon and the criminal sentenced to death may gain a reprieve but those who are perplexed because they do not know contentment will live out their whole life without being released from such anxiety. Thus, it is said: “There is no misfortune greater than not knowing contentment.” (Goldin 2013, p. 239). |
30 | Translation excerpted from (Rickett 1998, p. 53). |
31 | “Craft” (qiao 巧) in “auspicious appropriateness, beneficial craft” was originally deciphered as the character “lord” (zhu 主) but Dong Shan 董珊 changed it to “craft” in his proofreading. See (Dong 2004). |
32 | Translation from (Brindley et al. 2013, p. 149). |
33 | In the “Explaining Lao” chapter, Han Feizi remarks: The Way has its accumulations, potency has its achievements. Potency is the achievements of the Way. Achievements have their concrete expressions; concrete expressions have their radiance. Humaneness is the radiance of Potency. Radiance has its saturating effect; its saturating effect becomes manifest in affairs. Righteousness is the affairs of Humaneness. Affairs have their Ritual; Ritual has its cultural expressions. Ritual is the cultural expression of righteousness. Thus, it is said: Losing the Way, potency is lost; losing potency, humaneness is lost; losing humaneness, righteousness is lost; losing righteousness, ritual is lost. (Goldin 2013, p. 230). |
34 | It is quite evident that the chapters “Horse’s Hoofs” and “Rifling Trunks” in the Zhuangzi display the spirit of the Laozi in criticizing civilization: “If the Way and its Virtue had not been cast aside, how would there be any call for benevolence and righteousness? If the true form of the inborn nature had not been abandoned, how would there be any use for rights and music? If the five colors had not confused men, who would fashion patterns and hues? If the five notes had not confused them, who would try to tune things by the six tones? That the unwrought substance was blighted in order to fashion implements—this was the crime of the artisan. That the Way and its Virtue were destroyed in order to create benevolence and righteousness—this was the fault of the sage” (“Horse’s Hoofs” Ma Ti 马蹄, Watson 2013, pp. 66–67). “The fish should not be taken from the deep pool; the sharp weapons of the state should not be shown to men. The sage is the sharp weapon of the world, and therefore he should not be where the world can see him. Cut off sageliness, cast away wisdom, and then the great thieves will cease. Break the jades, crush the pearls, and petty thieves will no longer rise up. Burn the tallies, shatter the seals, and the people will be simple and guileless. Hack up the bushels, snap the balances in two, and the people will no longer wrangle. Destroy and wipe out the laws that the sages has made for the world, and at last you will find that you can reason with the people. Discard and confuse the six tones; smash and unstring the pipes and lutes; stop up the ears of the blind musician Kuang; and for the first time the people of the world will be able to hold on to their hearing. Wipe out patterns and designs; scatter the five colors; glue up the eyes of Li Zhu; and for the first time, the people of the world will be able to hold on to their eyesight. Destroy and cut to pieces the curve and plumb line; throw away the compass and square; shackle the fingers of Artisan Chui; and for the first time, the people of the world will possess real skill. Thus it is said: “Great skill is like clumsiness.” Put a stop to the ways of Zeng and Shi; gag the mouths of Yang and Mo; wipe out and reject benevolence and righteousness; and for the first time, the Virtue of the world will reach the state of Mysterious Leveling. (“Rifling Trunks” Qu Qie 胠箧, Watson 2013, pp. 70–71). |
35 | |
36 | Han Feizi said: “Men of high antiquity strove for moral virtue; men of middle times sought out wise schemes; mon of today vie to be known for strength and spirit.” (“The Five Vermin”. Watson 2003, p. 101) He also said: “men of antiquity strove to be known as virtuous; those of the middle age struggled to be known as wise; and now men fight for the reputation of being powerful. In antiquity, events were few; measures were simple, naïve, crude and incomplete. Therefore, there were men using spears made of mother-of-pearl, and those pushing carts. In antiquity, again people were few and therefore kind to one another; things being few, they made light of profits and made alienations easy. Hence followed alienations of the throne by courtesy and transfer of the rule over all under heaven. That beings so, to do courteous alienations, promote compassion and beneficence, and follow benevolence and favor, was to run the government in the primitive way. In the age of numerous affairs, to employ the instruments of the management of affairs that were few, is not the wise man’s measure. Again, in the age of great struggles, to follow the track of courteous alienations, is not the sage’s policy. For this reason, wise men do not personally push carts and sages do not run any government in the primitive way.” (Han Feizi “Eight Fallacies” translated by W.K. Liao (1939, p. 484)). |
37 | The Zhuangzi says: “The true man of ancient times got it and lived, lost it and died, got it and died, lost it and lived. Medicines serve as an example. There are monkshood, balloonflower, cockscomb, and chinaroot; each has a time when it is the sovereign remedy, though the individual cases are too numerous to describe.” (Xu Wu Gui, Watson 2013, p. 212). |
© 2019 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Wang, Z. Abnormalities and Return: An Exploration of the Concept Fan 反 in the Laozi. Religions 2019, 10, 32. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010032
Wang Z. Abnormalities and Return: An Exploration of the Concept Fan 反 in the Laozi. Religions. 2019; 10(1):32. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010032
Chicago/Turabian StyleWang, Zhongjiang. 2019. "Abnormalities and Return: An Exploration of the Concept Fan 反 in the Laozi" Religions 10, no. 1: 32. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010032
APA StyleWang, Z. (2019). Abnormalities and Return: An Exploration of the Concept Fan 反 in the Laozi. Religions, 10(1), 32. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10010032