Identifying Nothing: Anti-Realist Strategies for the Identity of Fictional Characters
Abstract
:1. Introduction
(1) Miss Marple was created by Agatha Christie.
(2) Miss Marple is the same as Jessica Fletcher.
“[…] about questions of identity of fictional entities, there is no fact of the matter when they are identical. This is so because there is no actual individual entity that bears the identity relationship to itself”4.
Despite its intuitive appeal, on second thoughts, the Negation Strategy is likely to leave us with a strong sense of dissatisfaction. Even the anti-realist wants to concede that (2) is perfectly intelligible: it must have a precise meaning and a definite truth value. In fact, she presumably wants to maintain that (2) does not concern ficta but ficta-surrogates instead—perhaps games of make-believe, according to the pretense theorist, or some sort of cognitive/descriptive/propositional contents according to other strands of anti-realism.“One may well dismiss the matter [of identifying a character of one work with a character of another work] on the ground that the questions are silly”5.
“[…] in situations in which fiction is being discussed, and we are speaking as though the characters, events, etc., are real, our sentences are to be understood as prefixed by ‘According to NR, …’ [where NR stands for Naive Realism]”6.
As a matter of fact, such a strategy particularly fits within a pretense-theoretic framework. Nevertheless, it is crucial to point out that it is not necessary to endorse a fictionalist stance towards ficta in order to make use of the Simulation Strategy: an anti-realist may decide to tackle identity issues about fictional characters within the pretense that there are such entities, without believing or assuming that any talk about fictional characters is to be understood as produced and consumed within such a pretense.“[…] since I deny the existence of fictional characters, I take [their identity conditions] to hold not in reality but rather within the scope of the pretense that there are such things as fictional characters”7.
2. The Simulation Strategy
as follows:(3) Miss Marple is a detective.
In the same vein, I suggest paraphrasing the metatextual reading of (1) as follows:(3*) All Marple-depictions (compliant with the canon) are detective-depictions.
We are now equipped with a general schema for each kind of fictional discourse:(1*) Marple-depictions are (collectively) such that Agatha Christie was the first human being who produced any of them.
(PT) all N-depictions are F-depictions.
Where N is typically a proper name and F is a unary predicate. The (PT) schema can be easily adapted to cover n-ary predications as well: for instance, a binary predication would have the form “All N-depictions and M-depictions couples are R-depictions”.(MT) the N-depictions are F.
Although equipped with a strong sense of plausibility, such a property-based criterion leads us to a pair of unwanted consequences that we need to take into account.(ISN) necessarily, x and y are the same fictional character if and only if x and y are ascribed exactly the same properties within the relevant stories.
It would follow from (ISN*) that King’s Miss Marple is the same as Christie’s Miss Marple and that Miss Marple could have lived in St John Mead rather than in St Mary Mead.(ISN*) necessarily, x and y are the same fictional character if and only if x and y are ascribed exactly the same essential properties within the relevant stories.
(IN) is much weaker than its predecessors, for it only provides us with necessary conditions for the identity of fictional characters: in order to be Miss Marple, it is necessary to be ascribed, within the relevant stories, the property of being a human person gifted with extraordinary observation and reasoning skills, who solves plenty of murder cases.(IN) necessarily, x and y are the same fictional character only if x and y are ascribed exactly the same essential properties within the relevant stories.
(4) The protagonist of Atwood’s story is the character created by Christie.
(5) The protagonist of Christie’s stories is not the character that features in Atwood’s story.
3. Back to the Translation Strategy
Such a parthood relation is to be understood as follows: any Marpled-depiction is one of the Marpleg-depictions. On the other hand, when we wonder if the protagonist of Christie’s stories belongs to Atwood’s derivative tradition, the answer is clearly negative. Indeed, (5) can be translated into(4*) The Marpled-depictions are part of the Marpleg-depictions.
Again, this is to say: it is not the case that any Marplec depiction is one of the Marpled-depictions. Both (4*) and (5*) seem to be true. Figuratively, it is useful to conceive of such pluralities as sets. The set of the Marpled-depictions is included in the general set of the Marpleg-depictions (but the opposite does not hold); on the other hand, the set of the Marplec-depictions is not included in the set of the Marpled-depictions—in fact, they are disjoint sets. Moreover, the set of the Marplec-depictions would be nothing but the difference between the general set and all the derivative sets included in it20.(5*) It is not the case that the Marplec-depictions are part of the Marpled-depictions.
(6) Gregor Samsa is a cockroach according to Nabokov and Levi.
At first glance, one may suspect that different characters correspond to different interpretive acts and wonder whether the following sentence is true or false:(7) Gregor Samsa is a beetle according to the majority of literary critics.
Although the ‘two’ Samsa are characterized differently, commonsense would presumably suggest to us that (8) is true, and I do not see any good reason to reject it in such cases: there is just one single fictional character, Gregor Samsa, who is interpreted as being transformed into a beetle (within the relevant story) according to a certain interpretive act, and is also interpreted as being transformed into a cockroach (within the relevant story) according to a different, yet equally legitimate, interpretive act.(8) Gregor Samsa the cockroach is the same as Gregor Samsa the beetle.
(6*) the Samsac-depictions are interpreted as beetle depictions by Nabokov and Levi.
(6*) and (7*) are both true, as expected. According to Nabokov and Levi, Gregor Samsa is depicted by Kafka as transformed into a beetle. On the other hand, according to the majority of literary critics, Gregor Samsa is depicted by Kafka as transformed into a cockroach. Still, Nabokov, Levi, and most of the critics are all talking about the same plurality of fictional depictions: the canonical one generated by Kafka’s creative activities. Thus, (8) can be translated into the language of anti-realism as the true sentence(7*) the Samsac-depictions are interpreted as cockroach depictions by the majority of literary critics.
(8*) the Samsac-depictions interpreted as beetle-depictions are the same plurality as the Samsac-depictions interpreted as cockroach-depictions.
4. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Strictly speaking, it is the view according to which there are no fictional entities in general. This paper shall be concerned with a particular subclass of fictional entities, i.e., fictional characters. Paradigmatic examples of fictional entities that are not characters are fictional places such as the Hogwarts School of Witchcraft and Wizardry; see Kroon and Voltolini (2023). |
2 | While the first choice explicitly rejects orthodox Millianism, according to which the semantic value of a proper name is nothing but the entity to which it refers, the second one attempts to preserve it: see, respectively, Sainsbury (2009), Tiedke (2011), Orlando (2016), Favazzo (2019), and Braun (1993), Adams et al. (1997), Taylor (2000). |
3 | See Walton (1990), Crimmins (1998), Kroon (2000), and Everett (2013). There is also a peculiar variety of fictionalism about ficta, according to which (1) is actually asserted but elliptical for a prefixed sentence of the form “In the pretense of fictional realism, Miss Marple was created by Agatha Christie”: see Phillips (2000), Brock (2002). Such differences shall play no substantial role throughout this paper. |
4 | |
5 | |
6 | |
7 | |
8 | One may follow Currie (1990, p. 153) and suppose that a fictional author should always be included among the characters of a story. Even so, and even if such an omniscient author were to be identified with a fictional Agatha Christie, it would still be false that, within the story, Miss Marple was created by Agatha Christie. |
9 | Two remarks are in order here. First, I take true negative existentials, i.e., sentences such as “Miss Marple does not exist”, to be a special sub-kind of metatextual discourse (clearly enough, if read paratextually, they would be unproblematically false). Secondly, I shall only focus on fictional discourse, which I take to be actually asserted. When you tell a fictional story to someone, you just pretend to perform the illocutionary act of asserting—what Bonomi (2008) would call textual discourse. On the contrary, when you want to make a critical statement, either paratextually or metatextually, you are actually performing the illocutionary act of asserting. Clearly enough, a pretense-theoretic anti-realist would disagree: from her point of view, critical statements are uttered within some sort of extended pretense. Nothing crucial to our purpose hinges on these matters. |
10 | Roughly speaking, a narrative or depictive tradition can be understood as a (typically) very complex and articulate causal chain that links together different human activities of the proper kind. |
11 | Artefactualism and Meinongianism are quite popular strands of objectual realism about ficta. According to the first one, fictional characters are existing abstract artifacts: see Van Inwagen (1977), Searle (1979), Thomasson (1999), Voltolini (2006), Kripke (2013), Abell (2020). According to the second one, fictional characters are non-existent objects: see Parsons (1980), Zalta (1983), Castañeda (1989), and Priest (2005). Some philosophers prefer to include ficta in the ontological inventory not as objects but rather as properties (or, however, as non-individual entities of a similar sort): see Wolterstorff (1980), Currie (1990), Cocchiarella (1982, 1996, 2007), Landini (1990), and Orilia (2012). |
12 | This is not to say that realist philosophers have no tools to refine (ISN) and avoid such blatantly unpalatable consequences. For instance, it may be assumed in this case that there is a single relevant story, i.e., the one that results from the merging of Christie’s original stories with King’s coherent sequel story, and according to this story Miss Marple, who used to live in St. Mary Mead, England, at a certain point in her life, decides to move to Cabot Cove, Maine. At any rate, our purpose here is to underline some fundamental problems that any property-based account of the identity of fictional characters needs to deal with somehow. |
13 | A counterpart analysis of such modal cases would be a natural move for the fictional realist: the Miss Marple who lives in St. John Mead is a fictum distinct from, but extremely similar to, the Miss Marple who lives in St. Mary Mead. Nevertheless, a typical objection may be raised on the antirealist’s side: we wanted to talk about that very fictum created by Christie when we claimed that Miss Marple could have lived in St. John Mead rather than in St. Mary Mead, not about another (although extremely similar) individual. |
14 | Everett (2013, p. 196) suggests a similar case while discussing the same problem. |
15 | See Everett (2013, pp. 97–99, 207). |
16 | As Everett (2005) shows, there are also troubles about identity with respect to the same story. It can be argued that inconsistent stories might generate fictional characters that are both the same character and not the same character, or that stories about ontic indeterminacy might generate fictional characters that are indeterminately identical. In this paper, I shall not focus specifically on such cases. |
17 | As strange as it may sound, according to Atwood’s story, Miss Marple is both a teenage girl and an elderly unmarried woman. She just exemplifies one property or the other in two different temporal scenarios. |
18 | For the sake of simplicity, I am assuming that the canon corresponds to the original depictive tradition. This is not necessarily so, though, and perhaps Mickey Mouse himself/itself is a good example thereof: presumably, when we think about the canonical Mickey Mouse, we do not have in mind the original depictions produced by Walt Disney but, rather, a certain depictive tradition that would have been developed later in time. |
19 | Outlining the exact criteria that such a causal chain should satisfy goes far beyond the purposes of this paper. However, any choice to this effect would strongly depend on the intuitions about cross-fictional identifications that one may prefer to stress. For instance, a conscious intention to import a character from a story to another should be necessarily included among the criteria in order to rule out the identification of Cervantes’ Don Quixote with Menard’s Don Quixote. |
20 | If one prefers to distinguish between the original and the canonical tradition, such a remark can be adjusted as follows. While the difference between the general set and all the derivative sets included in it is the original set, the difference between the general set and all the deviant sets included in it is the canonical set. |
21 | This case raised some discussion among philosophers: see Friend (2011) and García-Carpintero (2020). |
22 | Besides having been important writers themselves, both Nabokov and Levi had some competence on the matter: the former was fond of entomology while the latter was a natural scientist in the first place. |
23 | More precisely, any Samsac-depiction is a transformed-into-a vermin-depiction. For the sake of simplicity, I shall not specify it in the following examples. |
24 | Provided that, in the text, there is no overwhelming evidence in favor of one choice or the other. Moreover, questions about the author’s intention may be raised. For instance, did Kafka actually intend to leave the kind of vermin undetermined? If not so, and he had a specific interpretation in mind, would it be relevant to our interpretive practices as common readers or scholarly experienced ones? Settling these questions, albeit extremely interesting as a theoretical enterprise, is not crucial to our purposes. |
References
- Abell, Catharine. 2020. Fiction. A Philosophical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Fred, Gary Fuller, and Robert Stecker. 1997. The Semantics of Fictional Names. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78: 128–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bonomi, Andrea. 2008. Fictional Contexts. In Perspectives on Contexts. Edited by Paolo Bouquet, Luciano Serafini and Richmond H. Thomason. Stanford: CSLI Publications, pp. 213–48. [Google Scholar]
- Braun, David. 1993. Empty Names. Noûs 27: 449–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brock, Stuart. 2002. Fictionalism about Fictional Characters. Noûs 36: 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Castañeda, Hector-Neri. 1989. Thinking, Language, and Experience. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cocchiarella, Nino. 1982. Meinong Reconstructed Versus Early Russell Reconstructed. Journal of Philosophical Logic 11: 183–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cocchiarella, Nino. 1996. Conceptual Realism as a Formal Ontology. In Formal Ontology. Edited by Roberto Poli and Peter Simons. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Cocchiarella, Nino. 2007. Formal Ontology and Conceptual Realism. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Crimmins, Mark. 1998. Hesperus and Phosphorus: Sense, Pretense, and Reference. The Philosophical Review 107: 1–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Currie, Gregory. 1990. The Nature of Fiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Everett, Anthony. 2005. Against Fictional Realism. The Journal of Philosophy 102: 624–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Everett, Anthony. 2013. The Nonexistent. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Favazzo, Jansan. 2019. Sherlock Holmes Is Not Out There: Some Ideas for an Anti-Exoticist Account of Fictional Characters. Quaderns de Filosofia 6: 17–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friend, Stacie. 2011. The Great Beetle Debate: A Study in Imagining with Names. Philosophical Studies 153: 183–211. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- García-Carpintero, Manuel. 2020. Co-Identification and Fictional Names. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101: 3–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kripke, Saul. 2013. Reference and Existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kroon, Frederick, and Alberto Voltolini. 2023. Fictional Entities. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fictional-entities/ (accessed on 4 March 2025).
- Kroon, Frederick. 2000. Negative Existentials. In Empty Names, Fiction, and the Puzzles of Non-Existence. Edited by Anthony Everett and Thomas Hofweber. Stanford: CSLI Publications, pp. 95–116. [Google Scholar]
- Landini, Gregory. 1990. How to Russell Another Meinongian: A Russellian Theory of Fictional Objects Versus Zalta’s Theory of Abstract Objects. Grazer Philosophische Studien 37: 93–122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Orilia, Francesco. 2012. A Theory of Fictional Entities Based on Denoting Concepts. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4: 577–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Orlando, Eleonora. 2016. Files for Fiction. Acta Analytica 32: 55–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Parsons, Terence. 1980. Nonexistent Objects. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Phillips, John. 2000. Two Theories of Fictional Discourse. American Philosophical Quarterly 37: 107–19. [Google Scholar]
- Priest, Graham. 2005. Towards Non-Being. The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sainsbury, Mark. 2009. Fiction and Fictionalism. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Searle, John. 1979. The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse. In Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Edited by Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. and Howard K. Wettstein. Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press, pp. 233–43. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Kenneth. 2000. Emptiness without Compromise. In Empty Names, Fiction, and the Puzzles of Non-Existence. Edited by Anthony Everett and Thomas Hofweber. Stanford: CSLI Publications, pp. 17–36. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, Amie. 1999. Fiction and Metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tiedke, Heidi. 2011. Proper Names and their Fictional Uses. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89: 707–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Inwagen, Peter. 1977. Creatures of Fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly 14: 299–308. [Google Scholar]
- Voltolini, Alberto. 2006. How Ficta Follow Fiction. A Syncretistic Account of Fictional Entities. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Walton, Kendall. 1990. Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1980. Works and Worlds of Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Zalta, Edward. 1983. Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics. Dordrecht: Reidel. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Favazzo, J. Identifying Nothing: Anti-Realist Strategies for the Identity of Fictional Characters. Humanities 2025, 14, 62. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14030062
Favazzo J. Identifying Nothing: Anti-Realist Strategies for the Identity of Fictional Characters. Humanities. 2025; 14(3):62. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14030062
Chicago/Turabian StyleFavazzo, Jansan. 2025. "Identifying Nothing: Anti-Realist Strategies for the Identity of Fictional Characters" Humanities 14, no. 3: 62. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14030062
APA StyleFavazzo, J. (2025). Identifying Nothing: Anti-Realist Strategies for the Identity of Fictional Characters. Humanities, 14(3), 62. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14030062