Next Article in Journal
Dynamics of Strategy Distributions in a One-Dimensional Continuous Trait Space for Games with a Quadratic Payoff Function
Previous Article in Journal
Evolution of Cooperation for Multiple Mutant Configurations on All Regular Graphs with N ≤ 14 Players
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Hybrid Assessment Scheme Based on the Stern- Judging Rule for Maintaining Cooperation under Indirect Reciprocity

1
Faculty of Business Administration, Soka University, Tangi 1-236, Hachioji City, Tokyo 192-8577, Japan
2
Department of Information Systems and Operations, Vienna University of Economics, 1020 Wien, Austria
3
Faculty of Business Administration, Rissho University, Shinagawa City, Tokyo 141-8602, Japan
4
Research Center for Ethi-Culture Studies, RINRI Institute, Chiyoda City, Tokyo 102-8561, Japan
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Games 2020, 11(1), 13; https://doi.org/10.3390/g11010013
Submission received: 18 December 2019 / Revised: 11 February 2020 / Accepted: 17 February 2020 / Published: 20 February 2020

Abstract

:
Intensive studies on indirect reciprocity have explored rational assessment rules for maintaining cooperation and several have demonstrated the effects of the stern-judging rule. Uchida and Sasaki demonstrated that the stern-judging rule is not suitable for maintaining cooperative regimes in private assessment conditions while a public assessment system has been assumed in most studies. Although both assessment systems are oversimplified and society is most accurately represented by a mixture of these systems, little analysis has been reported on their mixture. Here, we investigated how much weight on the use of information originating from a public source is needed to maintain cooperative regimes for players adopting the stern-judging rule when players get information from both public and private sources. We did this by considering a hybrid-assessment scheme in which players use both assessment systems and by using evolutionary game theory. We calculated replicator equations using the expected payoffs of three strategies: unconditional cooperation, unconditional defection, and stern-judging rule adoption. Our analysis shows that the use of the rule helps to maintain cooperation if reputation information from a unique public notice board is used with more than a threshold probability. This hybrid-assessment scheme can be applied to other rules, including the simple-standing rule and the staying rule.
PACS:
02.30.Hq; 02.70.-c; 05.45.-a; 87.15.Aa; 87.23.-n; 87.23.Kg
JEL Classification:
C62; C72; C73

1. Introduction

Indirect reciprocity [1,2,3,4,5] is a well known mechanism for maintaining cooperation among unrelated players, in which cooperators request information about potential recipients. This reciprocity-based cooperation mechanism prevents free-riders, i.e., players who do not cooperate but receive benefits from naive cooperators, from invading the population of players. It does this by imposing a discrimination that allows players to cooperate only with players with a good reputation, i.e., a good image. The logic of this rule is evidenced by the existence of many reputation systems in online shopping systems.
Along with the many empirical studies that have been done on indirect reciprocity over several decades [6,7,8,9,10], there have been a number of intensive theoretical studies. These studies focused on identifying assessment rules for discriminating good and bad reputations because the rules for maintaining cooperation regimes cannot be easily found. Let us consider the image-scoring rule proposed by Nowak and Sigmund [1,11]. This rule is quite simple: players who cooperate with other players develop a good reputation while those who do not develop a bad reputation. Although this rule is intuitive, it suffers from what we call the “scoring dilemma”, as illustrated by this example. If a player, say Alice, must play with a player with a bad reputation, say Bob, then Alice may be confused about whether to cooperate or not. This is because her reputation will be hurt if she does not cooperate with Bob. Nowak and Sigmund’s theoretical analysis [3] on the simplest version of this rule demonstrated that image-scoring does not have evolutionary stability. Therefore, as Sigmund pointed out, this rule has an Achilles heel [12].
The main reason for this Achilles heel is that the image-scoring rule cannot distinguish justified rejections from unjustified ones. In our example, the reason why Alice does not cooperate with Bob should be considered. A better assessment rule would take into account not only Alice’s action but also Bob’s image. The stern-judging rule [13], i.e., the Kandori norm [14], was devised to address this problem. This rule enhances the image of players who cooperate with players with a good image and of those who do not cooperate with players with a bad image. Following this rule, Alice should be assessed as a good player because her rejection is justified. Many studies have extended this approach by considering other types of assessment rules as well as the stern-judging rule [3,5,12,15].
Although the stern-judging rule works well and intensive studies on the rule have been performed [13,16], Uchida and Sasaki [17] demonstrated that it does not work well in a private assessment scheme. To clarify this shortcoming, we considered two types of assessment schemes: public and private. In a public assessment scheme, assessment information is public, so each player’s image is determined uniquely. This scheme is based on player reputations. In a private assessment scheme, players assess each other privately, so a player’s image is not necessarily the same in the eyes of the other players. The scheme is based on impressions of the other players. The majority of theoretical studies on indirect reciprocity assumed a public assessment scheme [12,15,18,19,20,21,22,23,24]. This is because the public scheme is easy to analyze although it is an over-simplification since the image that one individual has of another is not necessarily the same as the image that other individuals have of that individual. Several studies have analyzed the private assessment scheme [17,25,26,27,28,29,30,31,32]. However, the private scheme is also an over-simplification because there are no reputations (i.e., public images) for the players. In the real world, the most accurate representation is found midway between these two extremes.
Previous studies simply assumed either a public or private assessment scheme, with no consideration of a hybrid-assessment scheme, one that mixes public and private schemes. In the real world, however, this either-or situation is rare, as people generally use multiple information resources to assess other people. Although a hybrid scheme is more realistic because it uses both reputation information and individuals’ private images (i.e., impressions) of others, there has been little analysis of such an approach.
Here, we considered a hybrid-assessment scheme based on the stern-judging rule in indirect reciprocity because this rule works completely differently for the two extreme schemes (i.e., public and private). It helps to maintain cooperative regimes in the public scheme [26,33,34] but not in the private scheme [17,35]. This means that we can investigate how much weight on the use of information originated from a public source is needed to maintain cooperative regimes for players adopting the stern-judging rule when players get information from both public and private sources.
We do this by using a giving game [5,12,13,15,16,17,18,19,20,21,22,23,24,25,26,27,28,29,31,32,34,35] in the framework of evolutionary game theory. This game is very simple and reflects cooperative behavior. As it is in many related studies, cooperation is defined here as the action of a player giving another player something of value that has a certain cost for the player, such as time or effort. So, every cooperator loses a cost while its recipient receives a benefit. This is why many theoretical studies on the evolution of cooperation have used this game.
We focused on an adaptive process for this rule and used a replicator dynamics analysis, a widely accepted method, to analyze the dynamics of several strategies. We focused on three types of strategies: stern judgers (who apply the stern-judging rule), perfect cooperators, and perfect non-cooperators. The standard theory on the evolution of cooperation teaches us that naive cooperators are defeated by naive non-cooperators. Therefore, preventing free-riders from invading cooperative regimes is a core objective of this study. Using a typical theoretical approach, we considered the effect of the stern-judging strategy for a population including both naive strategies.

2. Model of Hybrid-Assessment Scheme

We built a model of a hybrid-assessment scheme based on the stern-judging rule in the framework of evolutionary game theory.

2.1. Game and Strategy

We considered an infinite number of well mixed players who play a giving game multiple times. Time is discrete, and only one game is played each period. In this game, two players, a donor D and a recipient R, are randomly chosen, and D decides whether to contribute to R or not. If D contributes, R gains benefit b, while D pays cost c. Otherwise, nothing happens. We assume that b > c . Each player adopts one of three strategies: perfect cooperation X, perfect defection Y, or stern-juding rule adoption Z. Set S = { X , Y , Z } . An X player always contributes when it is a donor while a Y player never contributes. Contributions by a Z player depend on the recipient. If the recipient is assessed as Good by a Z player, the player contributes to R; if the recipient is assessed as Bad, the player does not contribute to the recipient. Each stern judger thus labels the images of the other players as either Good or Bad. The contribution patterns under the rule are shown in Table 1. For example, if D contributes to R, and R has a Bad image, D will also be labeled as Bad, as shown by the third pattern.
To generalize the game, we introduced two types of errors. One is an implementation error, in which there is a probability e of not contributing when a player intends to contribute. The other is a cognitive error in which there is a probability e that a donor’s image is reversed when updating. We assume that both probabilities are constant. Let ϵ = ( 1 e ) ( 1 e ) + e e .

2.2. Hybrid Assessment

We consider a hybrid assessment using two types of assessment schemes: a public scheme and a private scheme. In the public scheme, when a Z player is chosen as D, the player accesses a public notice board and obtains reputation information on R, i.e., R’s image, and decides on the basis of this information whether to contribute to R. In the private scheme, when a Z player is chosen as D, the player decides whether to contribute in accordance with the player’s private image of R. We combined the two schemes by introducing a constant probability, p. When a Z player is chosen as D, the player adopts either the public scheme with probability p or the private scheme with probability 1 p . That is, stern judgers use the public assessment scheme with probability p and use the private one with probability 1 p . Let g ( p ) be a rate at which a Z player assesses players as Good.
The updating rule for images in the public scheme is simple. A donor’s action in every game is immediately reflected on the public notice board. If a player i is the donor and j is the recipient, i’s image updated at the end of the game in accordance with the patterns in Table 1. For example, if i did not make a contribution and j’s image is Good on the public notice board, i’s image on the board is switched to Bad if it was Good before the game.
The updating rule for images in the private scheme is not so simple. First, there are three possible assessments for each game: it is observed and assessed as Good, it is observed and assessed as Bad, or it is not observed, in which case the donor player’s image is not updated. If a Z player observes a game, the player updates its image of the donor in that game on the basis of the donor’s action in accordance with the assessment pattern in Table 1. Note that if the number of observers goes to infinity, a theoretical analysis is virtually impossible because the number of equation systems also goes to infinity [32]. Therefore, we assume that the number of observers of each game is limited. Under this assumption, the image of a player in the eyes of a stern judger is rarely updated. This is why infinite time is required to saturate the value of g ( p ) [29].

3. Results

We analyzed our model theoretically to explore the effects of hybrid assessment under the stern-judging rule on indirect reciprocity using replicator dynamics. First, g ( p ) is solved to obtain the expected payoff for each strategy. Then the replicator dynamics are solved. Finally, the evolutionary stable points are calculated, and their conditions are solved.

3.1. Image Dynamics

We first consider the public assessment scheme. Let x, y, and z be the fractions (population ratios) of players using X, Y, and Z strategies, respectively, where x + y + z = 1 . Like Sasaki [24], we use g s P u b to denote the fraction of players with a Good image on a unique public notice board adopting each strategy, where s S . We use g P u b to denote the average fraction of players with Good images over the population. Thus, g P u b = x g X P u b + y g Y P u b + z g Z P u b . In addition, we use g S , I to denote the probability that a Good image is assigned to a potential donor who adopts strategy S and also faces a potential recipient with an image score I = Good [G] or Bad [B]. The population size is infinite, so we assume that the composition of the population does not change between consecutive one-round giving games. Thus, the population frequencies of Good players satisfy
g X P u b = g X , G g P u b + g X , B ( 1 g P u b ) g Y P u b = g Y , G g P u b + g Y , B ( 1 g P u b ) g Z P u b = g Z , G g P u b + g Z , B ( 1 g P u b ) .
Using the patterns in Table 1, Equation (1) yields
g X P u b = ϵ g P u b + ( 1 ϵ ) ( 1 g P u b ) g Y P u b = e g P u b + ( 1 e ) ( 1 g P u b ) g Z P u b = ϵ g P u b + ( 1 e ) ( 1 g P u b ) .
We consider g X , G as an example. This example considers the case where a donor is X while a recipient is assessed as Good. In this case, the donor contributes to the recipient with the probability 1 e , and if so, this donor is assessed as Good. However, with the probability e, this assessment is changed to Bad. On the other hand, the donor does not contribute to the recipient with the probability e , and this donor is assessed as Bad. However, with the probability e, this assessment is changed to Good. Summing up, for the probability assessed as Good, g X , G yields ( 1 e ) ( 1 e ) + e e .
For simplicity, we assume that 0 < e < 1 / 2 < ϵ < 1 . Therefore,
g P u b = 1 e x ( ϵ e ) 2 ( 1 e ) ( 2 x + z ) ( ϵ e )
is satisfied. Note that g P u b 1 / 2 is satisfied regardless of the values of ( x , y , z ) .
We next consider the private assessment scheme. In this scheme, all stern judgers (Z) have images of all players privately. Therefore, there is an image matrix, I = ( i u v ) where i u v is an image of player v in the eyes of player u, and u adopts Z strategy [26]. In each game, if a player adopting the Z strategy observes a game, the player updates a donorfs private image following their private image of a recipient and the donorfs action based on the assessment rule shown in Table 1.
We used g s P r i to denote the fraction of players with a privately labeled Good image adopting each strategy, where s S . Players using the same strategy are homogeneous, so the value of g s P r i is unique, as discussed in detail by Okada et al. [32]. The definition of g Z P r i differs from that in the public scheme only because the actions of perfect cooperators and perfect defectors are pre-determined regardless of the images of the potential recipients. Let there be a case in which a stern judger is chosen as a potential donor. In the public scheme, both the potential donor and an observer who also adopts the stern-judging rule use the same public reputation to assess the potential recipient. In the private scheme, however, the two stern judgers (the donor and observer) use their private images of the potential recipient. Thus, we introduce a new parameter, g 2 P r i , which is the probability that the two stern judgers share the same image of the potential recipient.
Thus, the population frequencies of Good players satisfy
g X P r i = ϵ g P r i + ( 1 ϵ ) ( 1 g P r i ) g Y P r i = e g P r i + ( 1 e ) ( 1 g P r i ) g Z P r i = ϵ g 2 P r i + ( 1 ϵ ) ( g P r i g 2 P r i ) + e ( g P r i g 2 P r i ) + ( 1 e ) ( 1 2 g P r i + g 2 P r i ) .
If the observers are limited to a finite number as assumed, g 2 P r i = ( g P r i ) 2 is satisfied. Substituting g P r i = x g X P r i + y g X P r i + z g X P r i into Equation (4) yields
( 2 g P r i 1 ) [ 1 e x ( ϵ e ) + z ( ϵ e ) g P r i ] = 0 .
Thus, g P r i = 1 / 2 is satisfied regardless of the values of ( x , y , z ) .
Finally, we consider the hybrid assessment scheme. A player who adopts the stern-judging rule mixes information on the public notice board and the player’s own private image. They use the reputation information provided by the public assessment system with the probability p, and use the private impression provided by the private assessment system with the probability 1 p . Thus, the average population frequencies of Good players satisfy
g = p g P u b + ( 1 p ) g P r i g s = p g s P u b + ( 1 p ) g s P r i ,
where s S .

3.2. Replicator Dynamics

We use evolutionary game theory for the updating rule to investigate whether cooperative regimes are maintained with the stern-judging rule. We calculate replicator equations using the expected payoffs of the strategies. The replicator dynamics are described as
x ˙ = x ( U X U ¯ ) y ˙ = x ( U Y U ¯ ) z ˙ = x ( U Z U ¯ ) ,
where U s is the expected payoff for players whose strategy is s S , and U ¯ = x U X + y U Y + z U Z is the average payoff over the population. These values can be calculated using g ( p ) . The expected payoffs of the three strategists are
U X = b ( x + z g X ) c U Y = b ( x + z g Y ) U Z = b ( x + z g Z ) c g ,
where we omit the factor 1 e .
Our results show that a population consisting of only stern judgers (the top vertices of the triangles in Figure 1) cannot be invaded by either perfect cooperators or perfect defectors if p exceeds a certain threshold, as shown in Figure 1.

3.3. Stability Analysis

The replicator dynamics of the system have a trivial asymptotically stable point at ( x , y , z ) = ( 0 , 1 , 0 ) . This is because g P u b ( y = 1 ) = 1 / 2 , so ( U X , U Y , U Z ) = ( 1 , 0 , 1 / 2 ) . There is another asymptotically stable point at ( x , y , z ) = ( 0 , 0 , 1 ) if p exceeds the threshold. We solve for the value of p. Since U Z ( z = 1 ) U X ( z = 1 ) = ( 1 g ) [ b ( ϵ e ) p g P u b + c ] > 0 , X cannot invade a population consisting of Z players only.
U Z ( z = 1 ) U Y ( z = 1 ) = b ( g Z g Y ) c g = b p ( g Z P u b g Y P u b ) c ( p g P u b + 1 p 2 ) = p [ b g P u b ( ϵ e ) c g P u b + c 2 ] c 2 > 0
is satisfied. Substituting g P u b ( z = 1 ) = 1 e 2 e ϵ into this relationship yields
p > c ( 2 e ϵ ) ( ϵ e ) [ 2 b ( 1 e ) c ] .
There is a phase transition on the threshold, as shown in Figure 2.
To prove that no other stable points exist, we first consider the non-existence of inner fixed points (that is, that all x > 0 , y > 0 , and z > 0 are satisfied). This is because if an inner fixed point exists, U X = U Y = U Z is satisfied at that point. If so, U X = U Y yields p b z ( ϵ e ) ( 1 2 g ) = c and U Y = U Z yields p b z ( ϵ e ) = c , so g P u b must be 1 / 2 . However, g P u b > 1 / 2 when z > 0 , which is a contradiction. Next, we consider the three edges of the triangle. When y = 0 , U Z > U X is satisfied. When z = 0 , U Y > U X is satisfied. When x = 0 , U Z = U Y z = c p b ( ϵ e ) ( z ) . Therefore,
d d z ( U Z U Y ) ( z ) = ( ϵ e ) ( 1 e ) [ 2 ( 1 e ) z ( ϵ e ) ] 2 [ 2 p b ( 1 e ) c ] > 0
is satisfied because p > c b ( ϵ e ) if z < 1 . This positive condition means that the point ( x , y , z ) = ( 1 z , 0 , z ) is unstable. Therefore, there are no other stable points except for ( x , y , z ) = ( 0 , 1 , 0 ) and ( 0 , 0 , 1 ) .
We calculate the border of b (in the left panel of Figure 2). Equation (9) yields
b = ϵ e + c 2 ( 2 e ϵ ) 2 c ( 1 e ) ( 2 e ϵ ) .

4. Discussion

We analyzed a hybrid scheme of public and private assessments, that is, based on the stern-judging rule using an evolutionary game. This rule maintains cooperation in a public system but not in a private one, so whether it maintains cooperation in a hybrid system is worth consideration. Our theoretical analysis shows that the stern-judging rule maintains cooperation if holders of the rule can access reputation information on a unique public notice board with more than a threshold probability, as shown in Figure 1. Theoretically, actions based on a public reputation are more successful than ones based on a private image because g P u b g P r i = 1 / 2 , as shown in the Results Section.
As Figure 2 shows, the hybrid system can maintain cooperation if the cost-benefit ratio of a cooperative action exceeds a threshold (depending on the errors). The greater the cost-benefit ratio, the lower the limit of the probability for using the public assessment scheme. Moreover, the smaller the implementation and cognition errors, the lower the lower limit of the probability for using the public scheme. A cognitive error affects the lower limit more than an implementation error.
The stern-judging rule is too strict to maintain cooperative regimes in a private system. In part, this is because the rule is vulnerable to errors and unintended non-contributions. This vulnerability is emphasized more in a private assessment system. This is a problem related to “justified defection” [12,31,32]. For example, if a potential donor faces a potential recipient labeled as having a Bad image, a donor adopting the stern-judging rule does not contribute in accordance with the patterns in Table 1. However, this justified defection is seen as justified only by those whose image of the recipient is also Bad. There is thus no stable cooperative regime in a perfectly private system.
This justification dilemma does not seem like it would be eliminated in the hybrid scheme because players use their private images with a certain probability. Our theoretical results suggest, however, that this assumption is incorrect. Even if a justified defection sometimes does not appear justified to others, the payoff to the stern-judging rule adopters can exceed that of unconditional defectors because their other justified defections can be seen as justified due to common reputations in the public assessments.
This paper is a first step in examining a hybrid assessment using a mix of public and private assessment schemes in the context of indirect reciprocity and thus, we analyzed the case of the stern-judging rule only. However, hybrid assessment can be applied to other rules. For example, the simple-standing rule [36,37] and the staying rule [10,24,31,32] should be considered in future work. This is because a private assessment scheme under both the simple-standing rule and the staying rule brings a higher cooperation rate than a public one while the stern-judging rule is the opposite, as shown by Okada et al. [32].
We next compared our hybrid assessment scheme with the “imperfect monitoring scheme” [38], which is often referenced in game theory literature. In general, the imperfect monitoring scheme considers the case of a player playing a game against an opponent without observing the opponent’s actions. Therefore, in the “imperfect monitoring” scheme, players themselves cannot observe their opponents’ actions, and thus, this is a situation between the parties. Here, the term “hybrid assessment” means that it is the third persons, not the players playing games, that are observing games. Therefore, our analysis of such a hybrid assessment has originality.
In this paper, we used the probability of choosing one of the two systems; thus, in our model, the players mix the two systems. This assumption reflects actual society because people generally use public and private schemes effectively. When they have to assess another person, they sometimes access the reputation information generated by a public assessment scheme and sometimes consider their own impression generated by a private assessment scheme.
Despite the above-mentioned extension of conventional indirect reciprocity models, we must note that our model still has limitations. It is true that players of our model use both public and private information sources in the long run, but they judge a single game based on either public or private information. The probability that public information is chosen is p. However, it is likely that real human beings even make a single decision based on mixture of information from various sources. This type of information mixing is not included in our present model and incorporating it into our model remains a future task.
We can extend our scheme for mixing public and private assessments. For example, there could be two types of players (those who use a public system and those who use a private system) and there could be homogeneous players who adaptively change their usage of the two systems. Another extension is to make the probability of choosing an assessment scheme endogenous. That is, the players’ strategies include the probability. Adaptive dynamics [39] may be able to solve such a system.
Other extensions can also be considered. In our paper, the system provides information on a unique public notice board in the public assessment scheme. However, people could use a majority voting system as public information instead [29]. Future work will explore such extensions. Exploring a norm ecosystem [40,41] consisting of many norms would be another good extension. Introducing these aspects would bring the system closer to actual society, as well as considering hybrid assessment.

Author Contributions

All authors designed and discussed the research; I.O. performed the research and wrote the paper. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

Part of this work was supported by JSPS (Grants-in-Aid for Scientific Research) 17KK0055(IO), 17H02044(IO and HY), 18H03498 (HY and IO), 19K21570 (HY) and 19H02376 (IO and HY).

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Nowak, M.A.; Sigmund, K. Evolution of indirect reciprocity by image scoring. Nature 1998, 393, 573–577. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  2. Leimar, O.; Hammerstein, P. Evolution of cooperation through indirect reciprocity. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2001, 268, 745–753. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  3. Nowak, M.A.; Sigmund, K. Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Nature 2005, 437, 1291–1298. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  4. Rockenbach, B.; Milinski, M. The efficient interaction of indirect reciprocity and costly punishment. Nature 2006, 444, 718–723. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  5. Sasaki, T.; Okada, I.; Nakai, Y. Indirect reciprocity can overcome free-rider problems on costly moral assessment. Biol. Lett. 2016, 12, 20160341. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  6. Milinski, M.; Semmann, D.; Krambeck, H.J. Reputation helps solve the ‘tragedy of the commons’. Nature 2002, 415, 424–426. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Sommerfeld, R.D.; Krambeck, H.J.; Semmann, D.; Milinski, M. Gossip as an alternative for direct observation in games of indirect reciprocity. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2007, 44, 17435–17440. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  8. McNamara, J.M.; Doodson, P. Reputation can enhance or suppress cooperation through positive feedback. Nat. Commun. 2015, 6, 6134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  9. Swakman, V.; Molleman, L.; Ule, A.; Egas, M. Reputation-based cooperation: Empirical evidence for behavioral strategies. Evol. Hum. Behav. 2016, 37, 230–235. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Okada, I.; Yamamoto, H.; Sato, Y.; Uchida, S.; Sasaki, T. Experimental evidence of selective inattention in reputation-based cooperation. Sci. Rep. 2018, 8, 14813. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Wedekind, C.; Milinski, M. Cooperation through image scoring in humans. Science 2000, 288, 850–852. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  12. Sigmund, K. The Calculus of Selfishness; Princeton University Press: Woodstock, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  13. Pacheco, J.M.; Santos, F.C.; Chalub, F.A.C.C. Stern-judging: A simple, successful norm which promotes cooperation under indirect reciprocity. PLoS Comput. Biol 2006, 2, 1634–1638. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Kandori, M. Social norms and community enforcement. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1992, 59, 63–80. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  15. Ohtsuki, H.; Iwasa, Y. The leading eight: Social norms that can maintain cooperation by indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2006, 239, 435–444. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  16. Santos, F.P.; Pacheco, J.M.; Santos, F.C. Evolution of cooperation under indirect reciprocity and arbitrary exploration rates. Sci. Rep. 2016, 6, 37517. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  17. Uchida, S.; Sasaki, T. Effect of assessment error and private information on stern-judging in indirect reciprocity. Chaos Solitons Fract. 2013, 56, 175–180. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  18. Panchanathan, K.; Boyd, R. Indirect reciprocity can stabilize cooperation without the second-order free rider problem. Nature 2004, 432, 499–502. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  19. Brandt, H.; Sigmund, K. The logic of reprobation: Action and assessment rules in indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2004, 231, 475–486. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  20. Brandt, H.; Sigmund, K. The good, the bad and the discriminator ? Errors in direct and indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2006, 239, 183–194. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  21. Chalub, F.; Santos, F.C.; Pacheco, J.M. The evolution of norms. J. Theor. Biol. 2006, 241, 233–240. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Masuda, N.; Ohtsuki, H. Tag-based indirect reciprocity by incomplete social information. Proc. R. Soc. B 2007, 274, 689–695. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  23. Panchanathan, K. Two wrongs don’t make a right: The initial viability of different assessment rules in the evolution of indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2011, 277, 48–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  24. Sasaki, T.; Okada, I.; Nakai, Y. The evolution of conditional moral assessment in indirect reciprocity. Sci. Rep. 2017, 7, 41870. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
  25. Uchida, S.; Sigmund, K. The competition of assessment rules for indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2010, 263, 13–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  26. Uchida, S. Effect of private information on indirect reciprocity. Phy. Rev. E 2010, 82, 036111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Sigmund, K. Moral assessment in indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2012, 299, 25–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  28. Martinez-Vaquero, L.A.; Cuesta, J.A. Evolutionary stability and resistance to cheating in an indirect reciprocity model based on reputation. Phys. Review. E 2013, 87, 052810. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  29. Ohtsuki, H.; Iwasa, Y.; Nowak, M.A. Reputation effects in public and private interactions. PLoS Comput. Biol. 2015, 11, e1004527. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  30. Olejarz, J.; Ghang, W.; Nowak, M.A. Indirect reciprocity with optional interactions and private information. Games 2015, 6, 438–457. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  31. Okada, I.; Sasaki, T.; Nakai, Y. Tolerant indirect reciprocity can boost social welfare through solidarity with unconditional cooperators in private monitoring. Sci. Rep. 2017, 7, 9737. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  32. Okada, I.; Sasaki, T.; Nakai, Y. A solution of private assessment in indirect reciprocity using solitary observation. J. Theor. Biol. 2018, 455, 7–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Takahashi, N.; Mashima, R. The importance of subjectivity in perceptual errors on the emergence of indirect reciprocity. J. Theor. Biol. 2006, 243, 418–436. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  34. Inaba, M.; Takahashi, N. Linkage Based on the Kandori Norm Successfully Sustains Cooperation in Social Dilemmas. Games 2019, 10, 10. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  35. Hilbe, C.; Schmid, L.; Tkadlec, J.; Chatterjee, K.; Nowak, M.A. Indirect reciprocity with private, noisy, and incomplete information. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2018, 115, 12241–12246. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  36. Sugden, R. The Economics of Rights, Cooperation and Welfare; Basil Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1986. [Google Scholar]
  37. Milinski, M.; Semmann, D.; Bakker, T.C.M.; Krambeck, H.J. Cooperation through indirect reciprocity: Image scoring or standing strategy? Pr. R. Soc. B 2001, 268, 2495–2501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  38. Kandori, M. Introduction to repeated games with private monitoring. J. Econ. Theo. 2002, 102, 1–15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  39. Dieckmann, U.; Law, R. The dynamical theory of coevolution: A derivation from stochastic ecological processes. J. Math. Biol. 1996, 34, 579–612. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  40. Yamamoto, H.; Okada, I.; Uchida, S.; Sasaki, T. A norm knockout method on indirect reciprocity to reveal indispensable norms. Sci. Rep. 2017, 7, 44146. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  41. Uchida, S.; Yamamoto, H.; Okada, I.; Sasaki, T. A theoretical approach to norm ecosystems: Two adaptive architectures of indirect reciprocity show different paths to the evolution of cooperation. Front. Phys. 2018, 6, 14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
Figure 1. Replicator dynamics of hybrid assessments. Each triangle represents a simplex of the state space, where x, y, and z are non-negative real numbers denoting the frequencies of unconditional cooperators (AllC), unconditional defectors (AllD), and the stern judgers (SJ), respectively. The arrows in the triangles show the direction of replicator dynamics at each point. Trajectories following the dynamics are also drawn. If the top vertex ( x , y , z ) = ( 0 , 0 , 1 ) is asymptotically stable, the average rate of cooperation (AveC) at that point is calculated and the basin of attraction is shown in yellow. The four triangles represent the results for different values of p. The parameter values are b = 3 , c = 1 , e = 1 % , and e = 1 % .
Figure 1. Replicator dynamics of hybrid assessments. Each triangle represents a simplex of the state space, where x, y, and z are non-negative real numbers denoting the frequencies of unconditional cooperators (AllC), unconditional defectors (AllD), and the stern judgers (SJ), respectively. The arrows in the triangles show the direction of replicator dynamics at each point. Trajectories following the dynamics are also drawn. If the top vertex ( x , y , z ) = ( 0 , 0 , 1 ) is asymptotically stable, the average rate of cooperation (AveC) at that point is calculated and the basin of attraction is shown in yellow. The four triangles represent the results for different values of p. The parameter values are b = 3 , c = 1 , e = 1 % , and e = 1 % .
Games 11 00013 g001
Figure 2. Phase transitions of p. The panels show parameter spaces in which the stern-judging rule is stable. The vertical axis shows p while the horizontal axis shows b (in the left panel, with e = 5 % and e = 5 % ), e (in the center panel, with b = 3 and e = 5 % ), and e (in the right panel, with b = 3 and e = 5 % ). The borders of the yellow basin are b = 1.16 in the left panel and e = 0.33 in the right panel. The other parameter value is c = 1 .
Figure 2. Phase transitions of p. The panels show parameter spaces in which the stern-judging rule is stable. The vertical axis shows p while the horizontal axis shows b (in the left panel, with e = 5 % and e = 5 % ), e (in the center panel, with b = 3 and e = 5 % ), and e (in the right panel, with b = 3 and e = 5 % ). The borders of the yellow basin are b = 1.16 in the left panel and e = 0.33 in the right panel. The other parameter value is c = 1 .
Games 11 00013 g002
Table 1. Contribution patterns under stern-judging rule.
Table 1. Contribution patterns under stern-judging rule.
PatternContr. to
Good Recipient
No Contr.
to Good Recipient
Contr. to
Bad Recipient
No Contr.
to Bad Recipient
AssessmentGoodBadBadGood

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Okada, I.; Yamamoto, H.; Uchida, S. Hybrid Assessment Scheme Based on the Stern- Judging Rule for Maintaining Cooperation under Indirect Reciprocity. Games 2020, 11, 13. https://doi.org/10.3390/g11010013

AMA Style

Okada I, Yamamoto H, Uchida S. Hybrid Assessment Scheme Based on the Stern- Judging Rule for Maintaining Cooperation under Indirect Reciprocity. Games. 2020; 11(1):13. https://doi.org/10.3390/g11010013

Chicago/Turabian Style

Okada, Isamu, Hitoshi Yamamoto, and Satoshi Uchida. 2020. "Hybrid Assessment Scheme Based on the Stern- Judging Rule for Maintaining Cooperation under Indirect Reciprocity" Games 11, no. 1: 13. https://doi.org/10.3390/g11010013

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop