Measuring and Disentangling Ambiguity and Confidence in the Lab
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. Overestimation
1.2. Overplacement
1.3. Overprecision
2. Results
2.1. Descriptive Statistics
2.1.1. Attitude towards External Ambiguity
2.1.2. Over/Under-Estimation and Perceived Competence
2.1.3. Over/Under-Placement and Perceived Competence
2.1.4. Over/Under-Precision and Perceived Competence When the Source of Ambiguity is “Internal”
2.1.5. Over/Under-Precision and Perceived Competence when the Source of Ambiguity is “External”
2.1.6. Investment Framing
2.2. No Self Selection
2.3. Principal Component Analysis
3. Discussion
4. Materials and Methods
4.1. Self Selection Treatment
- Investment Choice 1a: subjects have to decide how many tokens (Gi) out of their endowment Di that they want to allocate to a lottery where the probability of winning 2.5 Gi (instead of getting zero) corresponds to the percentile corresponding to their performance in task B.
- Investment Choice 1b: subjects have to decide how many tokens (Hi) out of their endowment Di that they want to allocate to a lottery where they win 2.5 Hi (instead of getting zero) if a yellow ball is drawn from the Bingo Blower.
- Investment Choice 2a: subjects have to decide how many tokens (Gi) out of their endowment Di that they want to allocate to a lottery where the probability of winning 2.5 Gi is ½ and the probability of getting 0 is ½.
- Investment Choice 2b: subjects have to decide how many tokens (Hi) out of their endowment Di that they want to allocate to a lottery where they win 2.5 Hi (instead of getting zero) if a yellow ball is drawn from the Bingo Blower.
4.2. No Self Selection Treatment
5. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A
Appendix B
- In Stage 1 you will be asked to make a simple choice between two lotteries.
- In Stage 2 you will answer questions presented in two different Questionnaires with 20 questions each, and you will be asked to make an evaluative assessment.
- In Stage 3 you will be asked to make some forecasts and on this basis to choose between 4 related pairs of lotteries that will be presented in sequence to you.
- In Stage 4 you will have the possibility to allocate the tokens you accumulated in the previous Stages between two different investment opportunities.
- Investment Opportunity 1a—you invest G tokens from your endowment D, where G is the number of tokens of your choice: this will give you the chance to win 2.5* G with a probability corresponding to your ranking in Questionnaire B. For example, if your ranking in Questionnaire B implies that you did better than 80% of participants in your session, your probability of winning will be 80%, if you did better than 20% of participants, so that 80% of the participants did better than you, your probability of winning will be 20%.
- Investment Opportunity 1b—you invest H tokens from your endowment D, where H is the number of tokens of your choice: this will give you the possibility of winning 2.5* H if a yellow ball is drawn and nothing if it is a blue or red ball.
- Importantly, also notice that you can decide not to invest any of your tokens in any of the two investment opportunities or you can decide to invest all of them in one or the other or you can decide to invest some tokens in one opportunity and some in the other (and perhaps also keep some without investing them). Thus, any division of the tokens between opportunity 1a, opportunity 1b, and not investing is allowed. The only rule that you have to respect is that the sum of tokens invested overall (G + H) does not exceed your endowment (D): G + H ≤ D.
- Investment Opportunity 2a—you invest G tokens from your endowment D: this will give you the possibility of winning 2.5* G with a probability of 50% and nothing otherwise;
- Investment Opportunity 2b—you invest H tokens from your endowment D: this will give you the possibility of winning 2.5* H if a yellow ball will be drawn out and nothing if it is a blue or red ball.
- As for Pair 1, you can choose any division of your tokens that you like between Investment Opportunity 2a, Investment Opportunity 2b, and keeping them, i.e., not investing. The only rule that you have to respect is that the sum of tokens invested overall (G + H) does not exceed your endowment (D): G + H ≤ D.
References
- Moore, D.A.; Healy, P.J. The trouble with overconfidence. Psychol. Rev. 2008, 115, 502–517. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Brenner, M.; Izhakian, Y.; Sade, O. Ambiguity and Overconfidence; Mimeo: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Shyti, A. Over-Confidence and Entrepreneurial Choice under Ambiguity; HEC Paris Research Paper No. SPE-2013-982; HEC Paris: Paris, France, 2013. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gysler, M.; Crouse, J.; Schubert, R. Ambiguity and Gender Differences in Financial Decision Making: An Experimental Examination of Competence and Confidence Effects; CER-ETH Economics working paper series 02/23; CER-ETH—Center of Economic Research (CER-ETH): Zurich, Switzerland, 2002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yang, X.; Zhu, L. Ambiguity vs risk: An experimental study of overconfidence, gender and trading activity. J. Behav. Exp. Financ. 2016, 9, 125–131. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Blavatskyy, P. Betting on own knowledge: Experimental test of overconfidence. J. Risk Uncertain. 2009, 38, 39–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cesarini, D.; Sandewall, O.; Johannesson, M. Confidence interval estimation tasks and the economics of overconfidence. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 2006, 61, 453–470. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Harrison, G.W.; Martínez-Correa, J.; Swarthout, J.T.; Ulm, E.R. Scoring Rules for Subjective Probability Distribution; Working Paper; Georgia State University: Georgia, GA, USA, 2012; p. 56. [Google Scholar]
- Abdellaoui, M.; Baillon, A.; Placido, L.; Wakker, P. The rich domain of uncertainty: Source functions and their experimental implementation. Am. Econ. Rev. 2011, 101, 695–723. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ellsberg, D. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Q. J. Econ. 1961, 75, 643–669. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Attanasi, G.; Gollier, C.; Montesano, A.; Pace, N. Eliciting ambiguity aversion in unknown and in compound lotteries: A smooth ambiguity model experimental study. Theory Decis. 2014, 77, 485–530. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Klibanoff, P.; Marinacci, M.; Mukerji, S. A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 2005, 73, 1849–1892. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Attanasi, G.; Corazzini, L.; Georgantzis, N.; Passarelli, F. Risk aversion, over-confidence and private information as determinants of majority thresholds. Pac. Econ. Rev. 2014, 19, 355–386. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Attanasi, G.; Corazzini, L.; Passarelli, F. Voting as a lottery. J. Public Econ. 2017, 146, 129–137. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lichtenstein, S.; Fischhoff, B. Do those who know more also know more about how much they know? Organ. Behav. Hum. Perform. 1977, 20, 159–183. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Juslin, P.; Winman, A.; Olsson, H. Naive empiricism and dogmatism in confidence research: A critical examination of the hard-easy effect. Psychol. Rev. 2000, 107, 384–396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Merkle, E.C. The disutility of the hard-easy effect in choice confidence. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 2009, 16, 204–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Urbig, D.; Stauf, J.; Weitzel, U. What Is Your Level of Overconfidence? A Strictly Incentive Compatible Measurement of Absolute and Relative Overconfidence; Discussion Paper Series 09–20; Utrecht School of Economics: Utrecht, The Netherlands, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, J.; Friesen, L. Overconfidence in forecasts of own performance: An experimental study. Econ. J. 2009, 119, 229–251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Murad, Z.; Sefton, M.; Starmer, C. How Do Risk Attitudes Affect Measured Confidence? J. Risk Uncertain. 2016, 52, 21–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Festinger, L. A Theory of social comparison processes. Hum. Relation. 1954, 7, 117–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Belsky, G.; Gilovich, T. Why Smart People Make Big Money Mistakes and How to Correct Them: Lessons from the New Science of Behavioral Economics; Fireside: New York, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Kwan, V.S.Y.; John, O.P.; Kenny, D.A.; Bond, M.H.; Robins, R.W. Reconceptualizing individual differences in self-enhancement bias: An interpersonal approach. Psychol. Rev. 2004, 111, 94–110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Alicke, M.D.; Govorun, O. The better-than-average effect. In The Self in Social Judgment; Alicke, M.D., Dunning, D., Krueger, J., Eds.; Psychology Press: New York, NY, USA, 2005; pp. 85–106. [Google Scholar]
- College Board. Student Descriptive Questionnaire; Educational Testing Service: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1976–1977. [Google Scholar]
- Svenson, O. Are we all less risk averse and more skillful than our fellow drivers? Acta Psychol. 1981, 47, 143–148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Camerer, C.; Lovallo, D. Overconfidence and excess entry: An experimental approach. Am. Econ. Rev. 1999, 89, 306–318. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grieco, D.; Hogarth, R.M. Overconfidence in absolute and relative performance: The regression hypothesis and Bayesian updating. J. Econ. Psychol. 2009, 30, 756–771. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moore, D.A.; Tenney, E.R.; Haran, U. Overprecision in judgment. In Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making; Wu, G., Keren, G., Eds.; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Silver, N. The Signal and the Noise: Why So Many Predictions Fail—But Some Don’t; Penguin Press: London, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Minson, J.A.; Mueller, J. The cost of collaboration: Why joint decision making exacerbates rejection of outside information. Psychol. Sci. 2012, 23, 219–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Daniel, K.D.; Hirshleifer, D.A.; Sabrahmanyam, A. Overconfidence, arbitrage, and equilibrium asset pricing. J. Financ. 2001, 56, 921–965. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Haran, U.; Ritov, I.; Mellers, B.A. The role of actively open-minded thinking in information acquisition, accuracy and calibration. Judgm. Decis. Mak. 2013, 8, 188–201. [Google Scholar]
- Griffin, D.; Brenner, L. Perspectives on probability judgment calibration. In Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making; Koehler, D.J., Harvey, N., Eds.; Blackwell Publishing: Malden, MA, USA, 2004; pp. 177–199. [Google Scholar]
- Kern, W. The Heterodox Economics of “the Most Orthodox of Orthodox Economists Frank H. Knight”. Am. J. Econ. Sociol. 1997, 56, 319–330. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Alpert, M.; Raiffa, H.; Alpert, M.; Raiffa, H. A progress report on the training of probability assessors. In Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases; Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., Tversky, A., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Speirs-Bridge, A.; Fidler, F.; McBride, M.; Flander, L.; Cumming, G.; Burgman, M. Reducing overconfidence in the interval judgments of experts. Risk Anal. 2010, 30, 512–523. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Moore, D.A.; Carter, A.; Yang, H.H.J. Overprecision and the Quincunx; Mimeo: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Jose, V.R.R.; Winkler, R.L. Evaluating quantile assessments. Oper. Res. 2009, 57, 1287–1297. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Etner, J.; Jeleva, M.; Tallon, J.M. Decision theory under ambiguity. J. Econ. Surv. 2012, 26, 234–270. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Camerer, C.; Weber, M. Recent development in modeling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguity. J. Risk Uncertain. 1992, 5, 325–370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Camerer, C. Individual decision making. In Handbook of Experimental Economics; Kagel, J., Roth, A., Eds.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1995; pp. 587–703. [Google Scholar]
- Abdellaoui, M.; Baillon, A.; Placido, L.; Wakker, P. The rich domain of uncertainty. Available online: http://static.luiss.it/hey/ambiguity/papers/Abdellaoui_Baillon_Placido_Wakker_2008.pdf (accessed on 6 December 2014).
- Halevy, Y. Ellsberg Revisited: An Experimental Study. Econometrica 2007, 75, 503–536. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ahn, D.; Choi, S.; Gale, D.; Kariv, S. Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment. Quant. Econ. 2014, 5, 195–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hey, J.D.; Lotito, G.; Maffioletti, A. The descriptive and predictive adequacy of theories of decision making under uncertainty/ambiguity. J. Risk Uncertain. 2010, 41, 81–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Loomes, G. Evidence of a new violation of the independence axiom. J. Risk Uncertain. 1991, 4, 91–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Andreoni, J.; Miller, J. Giving according to GARP: An experimental test of the consistency of preferences for altruism. Econometrica 2002, 70, 737–753. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Choi, S.; Fisman, R.; Gale, D.; Kariv, S. Consistency and heterogeneity of individual behavior under uncertainty. Am. Econ. Rev. 2007, 97, 1921–1936. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Trautmann, S.T.; Vieider, F.M.; Wakker, P.P. Preference reversals for ambiguity aversion. Manag. Sci. 2011, 57, 1320–1333. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maffioletti, A.; Schmidt, U.; Schröder, C. The effect of the elicitation method on ambiguity aversion: An experimental investigation. Econ. Bull. 2009, 29, 638–643. [Google Scholar]
- Kolenikov, S.; Angeles, G. Socioeconomic status measurement with discrete proxy variables: Is principal component analysis a reliable answer? Rev. Income Wealth 2009, 55, 128–165. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jolliffe, I.T. Principal Component Analysis, 2nd ed.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Giri, N.C. Multivariate Statistical Analysis; Marcel Dekker Inc.: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- McKenzie, P.J. A model of information practices in accounts of everyday—life information seeking. J. Doc. 2003, 59, 19–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Greiner, B. An online recruitment system for economic experiments. Available online: https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/13513/1/MPRA_paper_13513.pdf (accessed on 6 December 2014).
- Fischbacher, U. z-Tree: Zurich toolbox for ready-made economic experiments. Exp. Econ. 2007, 10, 171–178. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hey, J.D.; Pace, N. The explanatory and predictive power of non two-stage-probability theories of decision making under ambiguity. J. Risk Uncertain. 2014, 49, 1–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Gneezy, U.; Potters, J. An experiment on risk taking and evaluation periods. Q. J. Econ. 1997, 112, 631–645. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cox, J.C.; Sadiraj, V.; Schmidt, U. Paradoxes and mechanisms for choice under risk. Exp. Econ. 2015, 18, 215–250. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
1 | In Ellsberg’s (1961) [10] classical two-color paradox, the source of uncertainty can be represented by the color of a ball drawn randomly from an urn containing 50 black and 50 red balls (the known urn), or by the color of a ball drawn randomly from an urn with 100 black and red balls in unknown proportion (the unknown urn). Alternatively, other sources of uncertainty could be Stock indexes like the Dow Jones index or the Nikkei index (with the foreign index implying a higher level of uncertainty for a US resident due to the “home bias”). |
2 | Although Kwan et al. (2004) emphasized the need of distinguishing between the two manifestations [23]. |
3 | There are few, if any, documented reversals of overprecison, whereas there are many documented reversals of the other two varieties of overconfidence (overestimation and overplacement). |
4 | There is evidence (Speirs-Bridge et al., 2010 [37]) that people appear less confident when you give them an interval and ask them to estimate how likely it is that the correct answer is inside it, than if you specify a specific probability of being right and ask them for a confidence interval around it. In other words, people have higher confidence in probability estimates than confidence intervals. |
5 | At the end of Stage 3 each subject faces a screenshot resuming all the outcomes of choices made in Stages 1 to 3 separately. |
6 | Although the experiment seems at first sight quite cumbersome, this result confirmed that participants were able to understand it; this is also indirectly confirmed by the fact that all sessions lasted one hour and half without anybody delating the others. |
7 | The Bingo Blower is a rectangular-shaped, glass-sided: inside the glass walls are a set of pink, yellow, and blue balls in continuous motion being moved about by a jet of wind from a fan in the base (see the picture in Appendix A). In addition, during the sessions’ images of the Bingo Blower in action are projected via videocamera onto two big screens in the laboratory. Subjects are free at any stage to get closer to the Blower to examine it as much as they want. All the balls inside the Blower can at all times be seen by people outside, but, unless the number of balls in the Blower is low, the number of balls of differing colors cannot be counted because they are continually moving around: while objective probabilities do exist, subjects cannot know them. In this way, as noted by Hey and Pace (2014) [58], there is a “situation of genuine ambiguity which eliminates the problem of suspicion; the problem of using directly a second-order probability distribution; and the problem of using real events, therefore keeping the problem more similar to the original Ellsberg one”. |
Quest. A (High Competence) | Quest. B (Low Competence) | p-Value | Power | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Ex-ante estimation of performance | 14.07 out of 20 | 11.01 out of 20 | p < 0.000 | 0.999 |
Actual score | 10.14 out of 20 | 11.93 out of 20 | p < 0.000 | 0.819 |
Ex-ante overestimation of performance | 3.93 | −0.92 | p < 0.000 | |
% ex-ante overestimating subjects | 88% | 39% | p < 0.000 | |
Ex-post estimation of performance | 10.22 out of 20 | 11.13 out of 20 | p = 0.032 | 0.619 |
Ex-post overestimation of performance | 0.78 | -0.79 | p = 0.032 | |
% ex-post overestimating subjects | 47% | 30% | p = 0.013 |
Quest. A (High Competence) | Quest. B (Low Competence) | p-Value | |
---|---|---|---|
Overestimation of the degree of competition | 2.01 | n.a. | |
% subjects who declare to be “above the average” (ex-post) | 48% | 51% | p = 0.733 |
% ex-post overplaced subjects | 10% | 16% | p = 0.253 |
Quest. A (High Competence) | Quest. B (Low Competence) | ||
---|---|---|---|
# of subjects who bet on their precision | 58 out of 89 | # of subjects who bet on their precision | 49 out of 89 |
% subjects who bet on their precision | 65% | % subjects who bet on their precision | 55% |
# of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 50 out of 89 | # of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 23 out of 89 |
% of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 56% | % of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 26% |
Temperature of NY, 21 September (12 a.m.) | Number of Yellow Balls in the Bingo Blower | ||
---|---|---|---|
# of subjects who bet on their precision | 33 out of 89 | # of subjects who bet on their precision | 33 out of 89 |
% subjects who bet on their precision | 37% | % subjects who bet on their precision | 37% |
# of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 25 out of 89 | # of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 23 out of 89 |
% of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 28% | % of subjects who wrongly bet on their precision (overprecise) | 26% |
Quest. A (High Competence) | Quest. B (Low Competence) | p-Value | Power | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Ex-ante estimation of performance | 12.43 out of 20 | 9.97 out of 20 | p = 0.014 | 0.859 |
Actual score | 8.90 out of 20 | 10.93 out of 20 | p < 0.000 | 0.820 |
Ex-ante overestimation of performance | 3.52 | −0.95 | p < 0.000 | |
% ex-ante overestimating subjects | 64% | 43% | p < 0.000 | |
Ex-post estimation of performance | 9.84 out of 20 | 10.61 out of 20 | p = 0.074 | 0.673 |
Ex-post overestimation of performance | 0.93 | −0.31 | p = 0.032 | |
% ex-post overestimating subjects | 48% | 41% | p = 0.017 |
Quest. A (High Competence) | Quest. B (Low Competence) | p-Value | Power | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Overestimation of the degree of competition (average) | 2.20 | n.a. | ||
% subjects who declare to be “above the average” (ex-post) | 50% | 50% | p = 1.000 | 0.080 |
% ex-post overplaced subjects | 14% | 7% | p = 0.322 | 0.089 |
Variable Description | Mean | Std. Deviation | Factor Score |
---|---|---|---|
Internal Ambiguity | |||
Preference for high-competence-based ambiguity (vs. risk) | 0.684 | 0.466 | 0.684 |
Preference for low-competence-based ambiguity (vs. risk) | 0.526 | 0.501 | 0.274 |
Preference for no-competence-based ambiguity (BB # yellow balls) (vs. risk) | 0.360 | 0.402 | 0.672 |
Investment in competence-based-ambiguity (vs. risk) | 0.541 | 0.500 | 0.067 |
External Ambiguity | |||
Preference for BB-based ambiguity (vs. risk) | 0.511 | 0.501 | 0.703 |
Preference for no-competence-based ambiguity (temperature) (vs. risk) | 0.375 | 0.486 | 0.044 |
Investment in BB-ambiguity (vs. risk) | 0.684 | 0.466 | 0.709 |
SUR Model | |||
---|---|---|---|
Internal Ambiguity Score | External Ambiguity Score | ||
Treatment | 0.094 | Treatment | −0.356 |
(0.226) | (0.217) | ||
Score high-competence task | 0.031 ** | Score high-competence task | 0.044 |
(0.031) | (0.029) | ||
Score low-competence task | 0.025 | Score low-competence task | 0.014 |
(0.037) | (0.036) | ||
Earnings | 0.000 | Earnings | −0.001 * |
(0.001) | (0.001) | ||
Gender | 0.013 | Gender | −0.071 |
(0.184) | (0.191) | ||
Age | −0.005 | Age | 0.012 |
(0.044) | (0.046) | ||
Easy | 0.268 | Easy | 0.013 * |
(0.190) | (0.183) | ||
Constant | −0.979 | Constant | 0.235 |
(1.262) | (1.216) |
© 2019 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Di Cagno, D.; Grieco, D. Measuring and Disentangling Ambiguity and Confidence in the Lab. Games 2019, 10, 9. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10010009
Di Cagno D, Grieco D. Measuring and Disentangling Ambiguity and Confidence in the Lab. Games. 2019; 10(1):9. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10010009
Chicago/Turabian StyleDi Cagno, Daniela, and Daniela Grieco. 2019. "Measuring and Disentangling Ambiguity and Confidence in the Lab" Games 10, no. 1: 9. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10010009
APA StyleDi Cagno, D., & Grieco, D. (2019). Measuring and Disentangling Ambiguity and Confidence in the Lab. Games, 10(1), 9. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10010009