Cognition as Morphological/Morphogenetic Embodied Computation In Vivo
Abstract
:1. Introduction
- The established view of cognition and its open problems;
- New developments in cognitive science and contributing fields;
- Foundations of cognition: self-organization and autopoiesis;
- Cognition as a driver of evolution and evolution as a driver of cognition in living organisms and their relation to the extended evolutionary synthesis;
- Morphological/morphogenetic computation:
- 5.1.
- Morphogenesis as morphological computation generating an organism from active matter (embryogenesis, development, evolution);
- 5.2.
- Cells as information-processing agents. Morphogenesis as Bayesian inference. Free energy principle, agency;
- Conclusions.
2. The Established View of Cognition and its Open Problems
- The emotion challenge: cognitive science neglects the important role of emotions in human thinking;
- The consciousness challenge: cognitive science ignores the importance of consciousness in human thinking;
- The world challenge: cognitive science disregards the significant role of physical environments in human thinking, which is embedded in and extended into the world;
- The body challenge: cognitive science neglects the contribution of embodiment to human thought and action;
- The dynamical systems challenge: the mind is a dynamic system, not a computational system;
- The social challenge: human thought is inherently social in ways that cognitive science ignores;
- The mathematics challenge: mathematical results show that human thinking cannot be computational in the standard sense.
3. New Developments in Cognitive Science and its Contributing Fields
4. Foundations of Cognition: Self-Organization and Autopoiesis
5. Cognition as a Driver of Evolution and Evolution as a Driver of Cognition in Living Organisms. Relation to the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis
6. Morphological/Morphogenetic Computation
6.1. Morphogenesis as Morphological Computation Generating an Organism from Active Matter (Embryogenesis, Development, Evolution)
6.2. Cell Seen as an Information Processing Agent—Morphogenesis as Bayesian Inference: Free Energy Principle, Agency
7. Conclusions
- The emotion challenge: Currently, cognitive science neglects the important role of emotions in human thinking. This challenge is being met on various fronts. Recent research shows how emotions, feelings, and sensations are a result of embodied information processing and are inseparably related to other computational cognitive processes, see [78,79,80,81]. In the Bayesian perspective, with a focus on human cognition, and based on the free energy principle, the emotional inference is an active area of research from two key directions. First, as interoceptive inference [82,83,84,85]. Second, the emotional valences of various belief states are viewed through the lens of resolving uncertainty as the mathematical image of angst and anxiety, [86,87].
- The consciousness challenge: Currently, cognitive science ignores the importance of consciousness in human thinking. Several information–theoretic approaches are being developed to address consciousness. For example, the information integration solution, see [88,89,90,91]. The information geometry approach that builds on a formal specification of the boundary between a living system and its external environment (a Markov blanket) [92] has been introduced. Within a framework of dual-aspect monism, intrinsic and extrinsic information geometry are providing the link between the brain and mind [93,94].
- The world challenge: Currently, cognitive science disregards the significant role of physical environments in human thinking, which is embedded in and extended into the world. This represents the main motivation for the pragmatic turn and an activist or situated approach to cognition. The circular causality between a bounded cognition itself and the world is central for active inference and learning; in which the agent is observing sensations from her world. In machine learning, the role of a generative model has been introduced through the notion of a world model [95]. See also [96] for an elaboration of the path to physics from computing [97] on the process from information to behavior [98] on computation in neuroscience, and [54,60] with arguments for mechanisms of morphological computing as reality construction for a cognizing agent. As the development of artificial intelligent cognitive computational systems progresses, a framework that can connect the natural with the artificial is used for learning in both directions—from the natural system to the artificial and back, [99]. For example, we can mention the impact of deep learning research on understanding cognition. The recent work [100] discusses the necessity of embodiment in the case of LLM (Large Language Models).
- The body challenge: Currently, cognitive science neglects the contribution of embodiment to human thought and action. See previous paragraphs on the fundamental importance of embodiment to the processes of cognition, as argued by [4,6,101,102,103].This challenge has also inspired much of the work on interoception (the perception of sensations from inside the body) noted in [104], and the close relationship between action and perception resulting from the embodied brain with active vision and sensing, which is also a current focus in artificial intelligence research.
- The dynamical systems challenge: Currently, there is a supposed contradiction between dynamics systems and (old) computationalism, between the mind conceived as a dynamical system, and a computational system. A broader understanding of computation that includes dynamical systems solves this apparent contradiction. For the arguments from the theory of computation, see [105,106].The free energy principle addresses this challenge by developing a physics of sentience combining dynamical systems theory with the boundary separating self from nonself. Coupling of the dynamics of the particular partition of states external and internal to a system to the corresponding information geometry of belief updating and inference is carried out by Bruineberg et al. [107]
- The social challenge: Human thought is inherently social in ways that cognitive science ignores. Info-computational studies of social cognitive systems already exist that extend cognition to groups of cognizing agents, [22,41,46,108,109]. In a Bayesian setting, social cognition is addressed through interpersonal inference and niche construction as enactive and distributed inference. These lines of inquiry range from the nature of dyadic interactions to the spread of ideas over communities, [110,111].
- The mathematics challenge: Mathematical results show that human thinking cannot be computational in the standard sense, as shown by Cooper [6,7,8,9,54,76,112,113]. In addition, a move from inductive and deductive logic to the perspective of active inference brings forward abductive reasoning [114], which is making the best guess about the external states of affairs [93,115]. The key question here is the distinction between dynamics and belief updating on continuous states as opposed to discrete state space models used for a symbolic representation. This has emerged in the distinction between predictive processing (under continuous state space models) such as predictive coding [116,117], relative to the use of belief propagation and variational message passing (under discrete state space models).
- 8.
- The computational architecture challenge: Cognition is not only the result of the activity of the brain, not even the activity of neurons alone. It is the capacity of all somatic cells, that are interacting with each other, and with the environment, [23,25]. This challenge arises in many guises in different fields. For example, in radical constructivism, it is known as structure learning [118,119]. In Bayesian formulations of active inference, it is reduced to Bayesian model selection, which may be the mathematical image of natural selection [120]. In other words, evolution itself may be a belief-updating process in which the likelihood of various phenotypes reflects their fit to the environment as scored by things such as variational free energy [121].
- 9.
- The generative mechanisms challenge: Mechanistic models of cognition provide generation of cognition through the processes of (morphological/morphogenetic) computation, unfolding in networks of agents from molecules to biological organisms. Cognition is first understood when we know its generative mechanisms (constructive approach), [24,31,71]. This is an active field of research that in Bayesian learning, focuses on the structure and form of generative models that underwrite active inference and learning—and the nature of message passing that is realized in terms of biophysics.
- 10.
- The information processing (Bayesian learning) challenge: How is evolution learning? A variational free energy principle can be used, to formulate self-organization (morphogenesis) in terms of active Bayesian inference. In the Bayesian inference framework, cells are information processing agents, and the driving force behind morphogenesis is the maximization of a cell’s model evidence, [69,72,122,123,124].
- Our fundamental understanding of cognition in nature;
- An understanding of mechanisms of evolution and development;
- The design and engineering of cognitive computational artifacts;
- Medical applications.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Laws of Science and Laws of Nature in an Evolutionary Knowledge Ecology. In Understanding the Nature of Science; Lindholm, P., Ed.; Nova Scientific Publishers: New York, NY, USA, 2019; ISBN 978-1-53616-016-1. [Google Scholar]
- Thagard, P. Cognitive Science. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edward, N.Z., Ed.; 2020. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/cognitive-science/ (accessed on 25 October 2022).
- Thagard, P. Cognitive science. In Encyclopædia Britannica; Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc.: Chicago, IL, USA, 2013; Available online: https://www.britannica.com/science/cognitive-science (accessed on 25 October 2022).
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Cognition as Embodied Morphological Computation. In Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence 2017. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics; Müller, V.C., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2017; pp. 19–23. ISBN 978-3-030-07194-3. [Google Scholar]
- Keijzer, F. Theoretical behaviorism meets embodied cognition: Two theoretical analyses of behavior. Philos. Psychol. 2005, 18, 123–143. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Clark, A. Supersizing the Mind Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. Microcognition: Philosophy, Cognitive Science, and Parallel Distributed Processing; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Scheutz, M. Computationalism New Directions; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2002; ISBN 9780262283106. [Google Scholar]
- Pfeifer, R.; Iida, F.; Lungarella, M. Cognition from the bottom up: On biological inspiration, body morphology, and soft materials. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2014, 18, 404–413. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pfeifer, R.; Iida, F. Morphological computation: Connecting body, brain and environment. Japanese Sci. Mon. 2005, 58, 48–54. [Google Scholar]
- Pfeifer, R.; Bongard, J. How the Body Shapes the Way We Think—A New View of Intelligence; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Lyon, P. The biogenic approach to cognition. Cogn. Process. 2005, 7, 11–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- van Duijn, M.; Keijzer, F.; Franken, D. Principles of Minimal Cognition: Casting Cognition as Sensorimotor Coordination. Adapt. Behav. 2006, 14, 157–170. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ben-Jacob, E.; Shapira, Y.; Tauber, A.I. Seeking the Foundations of Cognition in Bacteria. Physica A 2006, 359, 495–524. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baluška, F.; Levin, M. On having no head: Cognition throughout biological systems. Front. Psychol. 2016, 7, 902. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Waters, C.M.; Bassler, B.L. Quorum Sensing: Cell-to-Cell Communication in Bacteria. Annu. Rev. Cell Dev. Biol. 2005, 21, 319–346. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Vallverdú, J.; Castroa, O.; Mayne, R.; Talanov, M.; Levin, M.; Baluska, F.; Gunji, Y.; Dussutour, A.; Zenil, H.; Adamatzky, A.; et al. Slime mould: The fundamental mechanisms of biological cognition. Biosystems 2018, 165, 57–70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Kull, K.; Deacon, T.; Emmeche, C.; Hoffmeyer, J.; Stjernfelt, F. Theses on biosemiotics: Prolegomena to a theoretical biology. Biol. Theory 2009, 4, 167–173. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Knowledge as Computation in vivo: Semantics vs. Pragmatics as Truth vs. Meaning. In In Proceedings of the Proceedings from Computers & Philosophy, an international Conference i-C&P, Laval, France, 3–5 May 2006; Schmidt, C., Ed.; Le Mans University: Laval, France, 2006; pp. 202–216. [Google Scholar]
- Levin, M. The Computational Boundary of a “Self”: Developmental Bioelectricity Drives Multicellularity and Scale-Free Cognition. Front. Psychol. 2019, 10, 2688. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fields, C.; Levin, M. Scale-Free Biology: Integrating Evolutionary and Developmental Thinking. BioEssays 2020, 42, e1900228. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lyon, P.; Keijzer, F.; Arendt, D.; Levin, M. Reframing cognition: Getting down to biological basics. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 2021, 376, 20190750. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Verny, T.R. The Embodied Mind. Understanding the Mysteries of Cellular Memory, Consciousness, and Our Bodies; Pegasus Books: New York, NY, USA, 2021; ISBN 9781643137995. [Google Scholar]
- Levin, M.; Keijzer, F.; Lyon, P.; Arendt, D. Basal cognition: Multicellularity, neurons and the cognitive lens, Special issue, Part 2. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 2021, 376. [Google Scholar]
- Fields, C.; Bischof, J.; Levin, M. Morphological Coordination: A Common Ancestral Function Unifying Neural and Non-Neural Signaling. Physiology 2020, 35, 16–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lizier, J.T. Rethinking Computational Approaches to the Mind. Fundamental Challenges and Future Perspectives Symposium. 2022. Available online: https://computationalmind.github.io/#joseph-lizier-hehim (accessed on 25 October 2022).
- Lizier, J.T.; Polani, D. JIDT: An information-theoretic toolkit for studying the dynamics of complex systems. Front. Robot. AI 2014, 5, 60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Brette, R. Is coding a relevant metaphor for the brain? Behav. Brain Sci. 2019, 42, E215V. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Maturana, H.; Varela, F. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living; D. Reidel Pub. Co.: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1980; ISBN 9789027710154. [Google Scholar]
- Stewart, J. Cognition = life: Implications for higher-level cognition. Behav. Process. 1996, 35, 311–326. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dobzhansky, T. Nothing in Biology Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution. Am. Biol. Teach. 1973, 35, 125–129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miller, W.; Torday, J.S.; Baluška, F. Biological evolution as defense of ‘self’ (2019). Prog. Biophys. Mol. Biol. 2019, 142, 54–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Haken, H. Self-Organization in Physics. In Proceedings of the Nonlinear Dynamics of Transcritical Flows. Lecture Notes in Engineering; Jordan, H.L., Oertel, H., Robert, K., Eds.; Springer: Berlin, Heidelberg, Germany, 1985; Volume 13, pp. 37–50. [Google Scholar]
- Tiezzi, E. Steps Towards An Evolutionary Physics; WIT Press: Ashurst, UK, 2006; ISBN 9781845640354. [Google Scholar]
- Orlik, M. Introduction to self-organization in chemical and electrochemical systems. J. Solid State Electrochem. 2015, 19, 3203–3206. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Krishnamurthy, R.; Hud, N.V. Chemical Evolution and the Origins of Life. Chem. Rev. 2020, 120, 4613–4615. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hanczyc, M.M.; Ikegami, T. Chemical Basis for Minimal Cognition. Artif. Life 2010, 16, 233–243. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Witzany, G. Crucial steps to life: From chemical reactions to code using agents. BioSystems 2016, 140, 49–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Malassé, A. Self-Organization as a New Paradigm in Evolutionary Biology. From Theory to Applied Cases in the Tree of Life; Malassé, A.D., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022; ISBN 978-3-031-04783-1. [Google Scholar]
- Heylighen, F. Self-organization in Communicating Groups: The Emergence of Coordination, Shared References and Collective Intelligence. In Complexity Perspectives on Language, Communication and Society. Understanding Complex Systems; Massip-Bonet, À., Bastardas-Boada, A., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2013; pp. 117–149. ISBN 978-3-642-32817-6. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. Eco-Cognitive Computationalism: From Mimetic Minds to Morphology-Based Enhancement of Mimetic Bodies. Entropy 2018, 20, 430. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Villalobos, M. Living beings as autopoietic bodies. Adapt. Behav. 2020, 28, 51–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miller, W.B.; Enguita, F.J.; Leitão, A.L. Non-Random Genome Editing and Natural Cellular Engineering in Cognition-Based Evolution. Cells 2021, 10, 1125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Torday, J.; Miller, W. Four Domains: Cognition-Based Evolution BT-Cellular-Molecular Mechanisms in Epigenetic Evolutionary Biology; Torday, J., Miller, W., Jr., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2020; pp. 103–112. ISBN 978-3-030-38133-2. [Google Scholar]
- Baluška, F.; Miller, W.B.; Reber, A.S. Cellular and evolutionary perspectives on organismal cognition: From unicellular to multicellular organisms. Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 2022, blac005. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Watson, R.; Buckley, C. The Scaling-up of Purpose in Evolution (evo-ego): Connectionist Approaches to the Evolutionary Transitions in Individuality-Research Project; John Templeton Foundation: Philadelphia, PA, USA; Available online: https://www.templeton.org/grant/the-scaling-up-of-purpose-in-evolution-evo-ego-connectionist-approaches-to-the-evolutionary-transitions-in-individuality (accessed on 25 October 2022).
- Laland, K.; Uller, T.; Feldman, M.; Sterelny, K.; Müller, G.B.; Moczek, A.; Jablonka, E.; Odling-Smee, J.; Wray, G.A.; Hoekstra, H.E.; et al. Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Nature 2014, 514, 161–164. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Jablonka, E.; Lamb, M. Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. In Revised Edition. Life and Mind: Philosophical Issues in Biology and Psychology, A Bradford Book; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Ginsburg, S.; Jablonka, E. The Evolution of the Sensitive Soul; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2019; ISBN 9780-2620-39307. [Google Scholar]
- Watson, R.; Szathmary, E. How can evolution learn? Trends Ecol. Evol. 2016, 31, 147–157. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Watson, R.A.; Mills, R.; Buckley, C.L.; Kouvaris, K.; Jackson, A.; Powers, S.T.; Cox, C.; Tudge, S.; Davies, A.; Kounios, L.; et al. Evolutionary Connectionism: Algorithmic Principles Underlying the Evolution of Biological Organisation in Evo-Devo, Evo-Eco and Evolutionary Transitions. Evol. Biol. 2016, 43, 553–581. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Natural Morphological Computation as Foundation of Learning to Learn in Humans, Other Living Organisms, and Intelligent Machines. Philosophies 2020, 5, 17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Nature as a Network of Morphological Infocomputational Processes for Cognitive Agents. Eur. Phys. J. 2017, 226, 181–195. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Pfeifer, R.; Gomez, G. Morphological computation - connecting brain, body, and environment. In Creating Brain-like Intelligence: From Basic Principles to Complex Intelligent Systems; Sendhoff, B., Sporns, O., Körner, E., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009; pp. 66–83. [Google Scholar]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Morphological Computing in Cognitive Systems, Connecting Data to Intelligent Agency. Proceedings 2020, 47, 41. [Google Scholar]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Information, Computation, Cognition. Agency-Based Hierarchies of Levels. In Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence. Synthese Library 377; Muüller, V., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2016; pp. 139–159. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfram, S. A New Kind of Science; Wolfram Media: Champaign, IL, USA, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Kauffman, S. Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Morphological computing as reality construction for a cognizing agent. In Proceedings of the 12th Swedish cognitive science society conference, Gothenburg, Sweden, 6 October 2016; Billing, E., Almér, A., Lowe, R., Eds.; Swedish Society for Cognitive Science: Gothenburg, Sweden, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hewitt, C. What is computation? Actor Model versus Turing’s Model. In A Computable Universe, Understanding Computation & Exploring Nature As Computation; Zenil, H., Ed.; World Scientific Publishing Company/Imperial College Press: Singapore, 2012; pp. 159–187. [Google Scholar]
- Skyrms, B. Signals: Evolution, Learning and Information; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Keller, E.F. Towards a science of informed matter. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part C Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2011, 42, 174–179. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lehn, J.-M. From matter to life: Chemistry? Resonance 1996, 1, 39–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rambidi, N. Roots and promises of chemical-based computing. Biosystems 2002, 64, 169–178. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hogeweg, P. Computing an organism: On the interface between informatic and dynamic processes. Biosystems 2002, 64, 97–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pismen, L. Morphogenesis Deconstructed: An Integrated View of the Generation of Forms; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2020; ISBN 978-3-030-36814-2. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K.; Levin, M.; Sengupta, B.; Pezzulo, G. Knowing one’s place: A free-energy approach to pattern regulation. J. R. Soc. Interface 2015, 12, 1383. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Kuchling, F.; Friston, K.; Georgiev, G.; Levin, M. Morphogenesis as Bayesian inference: A variational approach to pattern formation and control in complex biological systems. Phys. Life Rev. 2020, 33, 88–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fields, C.; Friston, K.; Glazebrook, J.F.; Levin, M.; Marciano, A. The Free Energy Principle drives neuromorphic development. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2207.09734v1. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K. Life as we know it. J. R. Soc. Interface 2013, 10, 475. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Isomura, T. Active inference leads to Bayesian neurophysiology. Neurosci. Res. 2022, 175, 38–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Badcock, P.; Friston, K.; Ramstead, M. The hierarchically mechanistic mind: A free-energy formulation of the human psyche. Phys. Life Rev. 2019, 31, 104–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Pio-Lopez, L.; Kuchling, F.; Tung, A.; Pezzulo, G.; Levin, M. Active Inference, Morphogenesis, and Computational Psychiatry. PsyArXiv. 2022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Manicka, S.; Levin, M. The Cognitive Lens: A primer on conceptual tools for analysing information processing in developmental and regenerative morphogenesis. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B 2019, 374. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Clark, A. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 2013, 36, 181–204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Millidge, B.; Seth, A.K.; Buckley, C.L. Predictive coding: A theoretical and experimental review. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2107.12979v4. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Damasio, A.R. Feeling & knowing: Making minds conscious. Cogn. Neurosci. 2021, 12, 65–66. [Google Scholar]
- Duncan, S.; Barrett, L.F. Affect is a form of cognition: A neurobiological analysis. Cogn. Emot. 2007, 21, 1184–1211. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Schroeder, M.J.; Vallverdú, J. Situated phenomenology and biological systems: Eastern and Western synthesis. Prog. Biophys. Mol. Biol. 2015, 119, 530–537. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boehner, K.; DePaula, R.; Dourish, P.; Sengers, P. Affect: From information to interaction. In Proceedings of the Proceedings of Critical Computing Fourth Decennial Aarhus Conference, Aarhus, Denmark, 20–24 August 2005; pp. 59–68. [Google Scholar]
- Seth, A.K. Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2013, 17, 565–573. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Fotopoulou, A.; Tsakiris, M. Mentalizing homeostasis: The social origins of interoceptive inference. Neuropsychoanalysis 2017, 19, 3–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Smith, R.; Kuplicki, R.; Feinstein, J.; Forthman, K.L.; Stewart, J.L.; Paulus, M.P.; Khalsa, S. A Bayesian computational model reveals a failure to adapt interoceptive precision estimates across depression, anxiety, eating, and substance use disorders. PLoS Comput. Biol. 2020, 16, e1008484. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tschantz, A.; Barca, L.; Maisto, D.; Buckley, C.L.; Seth, A.K.; Pezzulo, G. Simulating homeostatic, allostatic and goal-directed forms of interoceptive control using active inference. Biol. Psychol. 2022, 169, 108266. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Joffily, M.; Coricelli, G. Emotional Valence and the Free-Energy Principle. PLoS Comput Biol 2013, 9, e1003094. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hesp, C.; Smith, R.; Parr, T.; Allen, M.; Friston, K.; Ramstead, M.J. Deeply Felt Affect: The Emergence of Valence in Deep Active Inference. PsyArXiv. 2019. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Tononi, G. An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neurosci. 2004, 5, 1–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Tononi, G. The Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness: An Updated Account. Arch. Ital. Biol. 2012, 150, 290–326. [Google Scholar]
- Tononi, G. Consciousness as Integrated Information: A Provisional Manifesto. Biol. Bull. 2008, 215, 216–242. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bołtuć, P. Metacomputable. Entropy 2017, 19, 630. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Sakthivadivel, D.A.R. Weak Markov Blankets in High-Dimensional, Sparsely-Coupled Random Dynamical Systems. arXiv 2022, arXiv:2207.07620. [Google Scholar]
- Seth, A.K. Inference to the Best Prediction. In Open MIND Collection; Metzinger, T.K., Windt, J.M., Eds.; MIND Group: Bangalore, India, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Friston, K.J.; Wiese, W.; Hobson, J.A. Sentience and the Origins of Consciousness: From Cartesian Duality to Markovian Monism. Entropy 2020, 22, 516. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ha, D.; Schmidhuber, J. World Models. arXiv 2018, arXiv:1803.10122v4. [Google Scholar]
- Abramsky, S.; Coecke, B. Physics from Computer Science. Int. J. Unconv. Comput. 2007, 3, 179–197. [Google Scholar]
- Sloman, A. What’s information, for an organism or intelligent machine? How can a machine or organism mean? In Information and Computation; Dodig-Crnkovic, G., Burgin, M., Eds.; World Scientific Publishing: Singapore, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Piccinini, G.; Shagrir, O. Foundations of computational neuroscience. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 2014, 25, 25–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rozenberg, G.; Kari, L. The many facets of natural computing. Commun. ACM 2008, 51, 72–83. [Google Scholar]
- y Arcas, B.A. Do Large Language Models Understand Us? Daedalus 2022, 151, 183–197. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Properzi, M. Bodily Processing: What Progress Has Been Made in Understanding the Embodiment of Computing Systems? Stud. Univ. Babeș-Bolyai Philos. 2021, 66, 181–190. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Dijk, J.; Kerkhofs, R.; Van Rooij, I.; Haselager, P. Special Section: Can There Be Such a Thing as Embodied Embedded Cognitive Neuroscience? Theory Psychol. 2008, 18, 297–316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fresco, N. Physical Computation and Cognitive Science; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett, L.F.; Simmons, W.K. Interoceptive predictions in the brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 2015, 16, 419–429. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- van Leeuwen, J.; Wiederman, J. Knowledge, Representation and the Dynamics of Computation. In Representation and Reality in Humans, Other Living Organisms and Intelligent Machines; Dodig-Crnkovic, G., Giovagnoli, R., Eds.; Springer International Publishing Switzerland: Cham, Switzerland, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Burgin, M.; Dodig-Crnkovic, G. A Taxonomy of Computation and Information Architecture. In Proceedings of the Proceedings of the 2015 European Conference on Software Architecture Workshops (ECSAW ’15), Cavtat, Croatia, 7–11 September 2015; Galster, M., Ed.; ACM Press: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Bruineberg, J.; Dołęga, K.; Dewhurst, J.; Baltieri, M. The Emperor’s New Markov Blankets. Behav. Brain Sci. 2022, 45, e183. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barabasi, A.-L. Bursts: The Hidden Pattern behind Everything We Do; Dutton: London, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Epstein, J.M. Generative Social Science: Studies in Agent-Based Computational Modeling; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Veissière, S.P.L.; Constant, A.; Ramstead, M.J.D.; Friston, K.J.; Kirmayer, L.J. Thinking through other minds: A variational approach to cognition and culture. Behav. Brain Sci. 2020, 43, e90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Albarracin, M.; Demekas, D.; Ramstead, M.J.D.; Heins, C. Epistemic Communities under Active Inference. Entropy 2022, 24, 476. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cooper, S.B. The Mathematician’s Bias - and the Return to Embodied Computation. In A Computable Universe: Understanding and Exploring Nature as Computation; Zenil, H., Ed.; World Scientific Pub Co Inc.: Singapore, 2012; ISBN 9789-8143-742-93. [Google Scholar]
- Zenil, H. A Computable Universe. Understanding Computation & Exploring Nature As Computation; Zenil, H., Ed.; World Scientific Publishing Company/Imperial College Press: Singapore, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Douven, I. The Art of Abduction; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Seth, A.K. The cybernetic brain: From interoceptive inference to sensorimotor contingencies. In MINDS project. Open MIND Collection; Metzinger, T.K., Windt, J.M., Eds.; MIND Group: Bangalore, India, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Mumford, D. On the computational architecture of the neocortex. II. The role of cortico-cortical loops. Biol. Cybern 1992, 66, 241–251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lee, T.S.; Mumford, D. Hierarchical Bayesian inference in the visual cortex. J. Opt. Soc. Am. A 2003, 20, 1434–1448. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gershman, S.J.; Niv, Y. Learning latent structure: Carving nature at its joints. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 2010, 20, 251–256. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Tervo, D.G.R.; Tenenbaum, J.B.; Gershman, S.J. Toward the neural implementation of structure learning. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 2016, 37, 99–105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vanchurin, V.; Wolf, Y.I.; Katsnelson, M.I.; Koonin, E. V Toward a theory of evolution as multilevel learning. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2022, 119, e2120037119. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Campbell, J.O. Universal Darwinism as a process of Bayesian inference. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 2016, 10, 49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kirchhoff, M.; Parr, T.; Palacios, E.; Friston, K.; Kiverstein, J. The Markov blankets of life: Autonomy, active inference and the free energy principle. J. R. Soc. Interface 2017, 15, 0792. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Nakajima, T. Biologically inspired information theory: Adaptation through construction of external reality models by living systems. Prog. Biophys. Mol. Biol. 2015, 119, 634–648. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Friston, K.; FitzGerald, T.; Rigoli, F.; Schwartenbeck, P.; Pezzulo, G. Active inference: A process theory. Neural Comput. 2017, 29, 1–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Dodig-Crnkovic, G. Cognition as Morphological/Morphogenetic Embodied Computation In Vivo. Entropy 2022, 24, 1576. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24111576
Dodig-Crnkovic G. Cognition as Morphological/Morphogenetic Embodied Computation In Vivo. Entropy. 2022; 24(11):1576. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24111576
Chicago/Turabian StyleDodig-Crnkovic, Gordana. 2022. "Cognition as Morphological/Morphogenetic Embodied Computation In Vivo" Entropy 24, no. 11: 1576. https://doi.org/10.3390/e24111576