Sign in to use this feature.

Years

Between: -

Subjects

remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline
remove_circle_outline

Journals

Article Types

Countries / Regions

Search Results (4)

Search Parameters:
Keywords = Condorcet jury theorem

Order results
Result details
Results per page
Select all
Export citation of selected articles as:
33 pages, 1475 KB  
Article
The Condorcet Jury Theorem with Information Acquisition
by Jun Chen
Games 2021, 12(4), 79; https://doi.org/10.3390/g12040079 - 25 Oct 2021
Cited by 1 | Viewed by 3125
Abstract
We analyze a committee decision in which individuals with common preferences are uncertain which of two alternatives is better for them. Members can acquire costly information. Private signals and information choice are both continuous. As is consistent with Down’s rational ignorance hypothesis, each [...] Read more.
We analyze a committee decision in which individuals with common preferences are uncertain which of two alternatives is better for them. Members can acquire costly information. Private signals and information choice are both continuous. As is consistent with Down’s rational ignorance hypothesis, each member acquires less information in a larger committee and tends to acquire zero information when the committee size goes to infinity. However, with more members, a larger committee can gather more aggregate information in equilibrium. The aggregate information is infinite with the size going to infinity if and only if marginal cost at “zero information acquisition” is zero. When the marginal cost at “zero information acquisition” is positive, the probability of making an appropriate decision tends to be less than one. Full article
Show Figures

Figure 1

22 pages, 358 KB  
Article
Information Use and the Condorcet Jury Theorem
by Keiichi Morimoto
Mathematics 2021, 9(10), 1098; https://doi.org/10.3390/math9101098 - 13 May 2021
Cited by 2 | Viewed by 4333
Abstract
Using a simple model of a coordination game, this paper explores how the information use of individuals affects an optimal committee size. Although enlarging the committee promotes information aggregation, it also stimulates the members’ coordination motive and distorts their voting behavior through higher-order [...] Read more.
Using a simple model of a coordination game, this paper explores how the information use of individuals affects an optimal committee size. Although enlarging the committee promotes information aggregation, it also stimulates the members’ coordination motive and distorts their voting behavior through higher-order beliefs. On the determination of a finite optimal committee size, the direction and degree of strategic interactions matter. When the strategic complementarity among members is strong, a finite optimal committee size exists. In contrast, it does not exist under strategic substitution. This mechanism is applied to the design of monetary policy committees in a New Keynesian model in which a committee conducts monetary policy under imperfect information. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Economic Modelling: Theory, Methods and Applications)
Show Figures

Figure 1

12 pages, 753 KB  
Article
A Condorcet Jury Theorem for Large Poisson Elections with Multiple Alternatives
by Johanna M. M. Goertz
Games 2020, 11(1), 2; https://doi.org/10.3390/g11010002 - 23 Dec 2019
Viewed by 4808
Abstract
Herein, we prove a Condorcet jury theorem (CJT) for large elections with multiple alternatives. Voters have common interests that depend on an unknown state of nature. Each voter receives an imprecise private signal about the state of nature and then submits one vote [...] Read more.
Herein, we prove a Condorcet jury theorem (CJT) for large elections with multiple alternatives. Voters have common interests that depend on an unknown state of nature. Each voter receives an imprecise private signal about the state of nature and then submits one vote (simple plurality rule). We also assume that this is a Poisson voting game with population uncertainty. The question is whether the simple plurality rule aggregates information efficiently so that the correct alternative is elected with probability tending to one when the number of voters tends to infinity. The previous literature shows that the CJT holds for large elections with two alternatives, but there is also an example of a large election with three alternatives that has an inefficient equilibrium. We show that there always exists an efficient equilibrium, independent of the number of alternatives. Under certain circumstances (informative types), it is unique in elections with two alternatives. The existence of inefficient equilibria in elections with more than two alternatives is generic. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Political Economy, Social Choice and Game Theory)
23 pages, 1349 KB  
Article
Voting in Three-Alternative Committees: An Experiment
by Johanna M.M. Goertz and Kirill Chernomaz
Games 2019, 10(2), 20; https://doi.org/10.3390/g10020020 - 1 May 2019
Cited by 2 | Viewed by 7177
Abstract
We design an experiment to test how voters vote in a small committee election with three alternatives. Voters have common preferences that depend on an unknown state of nature. Each voter receives an imprecise private signal prior to the election and then casts [...] Read more.
We design an experiment to test how voters vote in a small committee election with three alternatives. Voters have common preferences that depend on an unknown state of nature. Each voter receives an imprecise private signal prior to the election and then casts a vote. The alternative with the most votes wins. We fix the number of voters in our experiment to be five and focus on differences in the information structure (prior and signal distributions). We test three different treatments (different prior and signal distributions) that pose different challenges for the voters. In one, simply voting for one’s signal is an equilibrium. In the other two, it is not. Despite the different levels of complexity for the voters, they come relatively close to the predicted strategies (that sometimes involve mixing). As a consequence, the efficiency of the decision is also relatively high and comes close to predicted levels. In one variation of the experiment, we calculate posterior beliefs for the subjects and post them. In another, we do not. Interestingly, the important findings do not change. Full article
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Political Economy, Social Choice and Game Theory)
Back to TopTop