In this section, we show that the time-of-arrival probabilities suffer from small transient super-luminal terms. These terms originate from the fact that unitary evolution implies the Feynman propagation of sources, and the Feynman propagator does not vanish outside the light cone. We discuss possible strategies for removing such terms from the theoretical description, and we argue that this may not be possible in von Neumann-type models of measurement.
3.1. Apparent Causality Violation
Any theory of relativistic measurements for quantum systems must respect causality, in the sense that if the system is initially prepared within a localized spacetime region A, then there should be no detection signal in any region B space-like to A.
To implement this condition, we must first identify initial states that are localized in a spacetime region. This is a difficult task. First, we know that spatial localization at a moment of time does not work. Any notion of spatial localization in the single-time quantum state (even approximate ones) leads to faster-than-light signals [
6,
7]. This conclusion is not an artefact of specific models, but a consequence of fundamental properties of relativistic quantum systems, namely Poincaré covariance and energy positivity.
Rather than spatially localized states, we consider spacetime localized operations. We assume that the field is initially in the vacuum state
, and that we prepare an initial state for the time-of-arrival measurement by an external intervention. This intervention has support in a compact spacetime region that lies wholly before the Cauchy surface
. Then, we take the resulting state as
in Equation (
5).
The simplest type of external intervention on a field involves the switching on of a source. This intervention is implemented through the inclusion of a time-dependent term in the field Hamiltonian. Here, is a local composite operator and is a classical source with support in a compact spacetime region. Then, .
For
,
coincides with the field coherent state
, modulo a phase. Hence, the single-particle wave function is identified with
We note that states of this form cannot have support only on positive momenta; hence, the probability density
is not normalized to unity. Any state with only positive momenta has a tail in a position that extends up to the location of the detector, and is therefore not appropriate for testing causality).
We consider a source that vanishes outside the spatial interval
and
, where
and
. We work in regime
, i.e., a spatially localized interaction of long duration. For concreteness, we take
Then,
Causality requires that the detection probability at
vanishes for all
. This condition guarantees that the detector is only influenced by events that happen after the onset of the external intervention. This turns out not to be the case.
Figure 3 shows that
starts becoming appreciably larger than zero slightly before
and, in fact, it is non-zero for all times
. The non-causal component is more pronounced in the near-field regime, i.e., small
L.
We emphasize that this type of apparent causality violation is different from ones that have so far been considered in the literature. Past results focus on the evolution of spatially localized quantum states at a single moment of time. In contrast, here, we considered a time-extended external localized intervention. Hence, the causality problem is not an artefact of using idealizations from non-relativistic theory in describing a fundamentally relativistic system. It is also not an artefact of perturbation theory. The conditional probability density that manifests the causality violating terms is of order with respect to the field-apparatus coupling ; higher perturbative corrections are negligible for sufficiently weak coupling.
This result does not indicate a fundamental failure of causality; rather, it points at the limitations of von Neumann’s description of measurements, i.e., the description of measurements in terms of an interaction that is switched on. If we take the quantum formalism literally, Probability density (
3) does not describe a measurement that takes place at time
;
specifies the moment when the field-apparatus is on. Rather, Equation (
3) refers to a measurement that takes place
after the field-apparatus interaction is switched-off. Certainly, this distinction may be unimportant when the interaction time is very small. Indeed, in the models presented here, the width of the switching function can be made arbitrarily small.
In contrast, if we take the duration of the interaction larger than the distance between source and detector, no causality problem arises. However, the switching function is supposed to model a defining feature of a measuring apparatus; it cannot change arbitrarily if the distance between the source and the apparatus is changed. Hence, no matter how large the duration of the interaction is, we can always move the detector at a sufficiently large distance from the source so that the causality problem reappears.
In S-matrix theory, the coupling is assumed to be switched on and off adiabatically. This means that the effective duration of the interaction is arbitrarily large, and measurement takes place effectively at . In this description, transient terms disappear. However, this is not a solution of the problem, merely a sidestep. In any particle detector, particles are recorded at specific moments of time, i.e., particle detection is a temporally localized process.
An adiabatic switching of the interaction fails to localize the measurement event in time.
Hence, we conclude that von Neumann-type measurement models cannot account for a fundamental observed feature of the particle detection process, namely that particle detection is localized in time.
One possible way of restoring causality is by showing that the causality violating terms are impossible to measure, as a matter of principle. This resolution is conceivable, because QFT measurements are invariably characterized by false alarms, i.e., spurious detection events. Such events essentially define an irreducible background noise that persists even if the field is in the vacuum state. A detection signal exists only if it leads to a significant spike of recorded events over the noise background. This means that the super-luminal transient terms may be ignored if they contribute to probability less than the noise term due to vacuum.
In the present model, this noise is expressed by the constant background
of Equation (
13). This term is quite strong; in fact, it drowns a large part of the signal in the ultra-relativistic regime, and not only the transient terms. The strength of this term is an artefact of coupling switching. A realistic model for the apparatus must take into account that the initial state of the apparatus is correlated with the field vacuum, i.e., it is a dressed state. Term
of Equation (
13) incorporates also the equilibration of the apparatus with the field vacuum when the coupling is switched on. This equilibration is a spurious process. In the full description, the initial state of the apparatus is already equilibrated with the field. This implies that the restoration of causality through a signal/noise analysis requires a more nuanced approach to quantum measurements, beyond the use of switching functions. In
Section 3.3, we argue that such an analysis is feasible in the QTP approach.
3.2. Retarded Propagator versus Feynman Propagator
For the initial state (
33), the detection probability becomes
Here,
stands for
, where
is the Feynman propagator. The reason for the non-causal terms in the probability assignment is that the Feynman propagator does not vanish outside the light cone.
The causal solutions to the Klein–Gordon equation with a source,
, are retarded solutions, i.e., they are generated from
J through the retarded propagator,
. The retarded propagator
is simply the imaginary part of Feynman propagator
and it vanishes outside the light cone, i.e., for
.
In classical field theory, the restriction to retarded solutions is implemented as a boundary condition. This condition breaks the time-reversal invariance of the evolution equation; it defines an arrow of time. There are two main explanations for the emergence of this arrow: either it is a consequence of thermodynamic time asymmetry, or the boundary conditions must be specified at the cosmological level—see the analysis in Chapter 2 of [
25].
Certainly, if we substitute
with
in Equation (
36), the problem of causality is resolved. Analogous substitutions have been proposed in the context of photo-detection theory, in order to cure Glauber’s model from the transient super-luminal terms [
26,
27,
28,
29]). This amounts to a substitution of
with
in Equation (
12).
If we make this substitution, we cannot normalize probability density
by integrating
t along the whole real axis. The error due to the inclusion of negative times exactly equals the error in the substitution of
with
in
. The two error terms do not cancel, but they add up. Still, for a large class of initial states, the correction in the total probability is small, so it is meaningful to define the post-selected density matrices (
14) and (
16), and write the causally corrected version of Equation (
18),
modulo the fact that Probability density (
39) is not normalized to unity.
The problem is that the substitution of with is equivalent to the substitution of evolution operator for the field with operator which is non-unitary. Not only is such a substitution completely ad hoc, it also contradicts the basic rules of quantum theory. Furthermore, makes no sense as the evolution of an initial state, because . As long as we use a measurement model in which the instant of detection is determined by the Hamiltonian, the sources are Feynman propagated, and probabilities cannot be cured from super-luminal transients. A resolution requires, at the very least, an incorporation of time-irreversibility in the description of measurement in order to obtain some version of causal propagation.
3.3. Causal Propagation versus Restricted Propagation
Next, we describe the QTP approach to quantum field measurements [
13,
17,
20] because it has the potential to resolve the spurious superluminality problem from first principles. In QTP, detection probabilities are genuine densities with respect to the space-time coordinates, and the interaction between system and apparatus is always present. The key point here is that the propagator for an initial source is not the Feynman propagator. A resolution of the superluminality problem within QTP requires an explicit modeling of the macroscopic apparatus in a way consistent with thermodynamic irreversibility. This is taken up in a different publication.
In QTP, we describe measurement events as a transition between two complementary subspaces and of Hilbert space . Subspace describes the states of the system that are compatible with the realization of the event under consideration. If the event is a detection of a microscopic particle by a measuring apparatus, then subspace corresponds to all states of the apparatus compatible with a macroscopic detection record. We denote the projection operator onto as and the projector onto as .
Transitions that are correlated with the emergence of a macroscopic record of observation are logically irreversible. Once they occur, and a measurement outcome is recorded, further time evolution of the system does not affect our knowledge.
After transition occurs, a pointer variable of the measurement apparatus takes a definite value. We let be positive operators that correspond to the different values of . For example, when considering transitions associated with particle detection, the projectors may be correlated to the position or to the momentum of the microscopic particle. Since has a value only under the assumption that a detection event occurred, alternatives span subspace and not the full Hilbert space . Hence, .
Assuming that the systems is prepared in state
, and that the Hamiltonian is
, probability distribution
that the transition took place at time
t and an outcome
was recorded is
where the
class operator
is defined in terms of restricted evolution operator
which is the continuous limit of product
as number of steps
N continues to infinity. By the Mishra–Sudarshan theorem [
30],
is a unitary operator on
in this limit. However, one may modify the definition, for example, by regularizing the product so that there is an effective minimal time
—see, for example, the analysis of Ref. [
31]. Then,
may be non-unitary.
It is important to emphasize that Equation (
40) is a genuine probability density with respect to both
and
t [
17]. The derivation of Equation (
40) requires the assumption of decoherence in the measuring apparatus.
We note that
vanishes if for
. We consider Hamiltonian
, where
, and
a perturbing interaction. Since all transitions are due to
, to the leading order in the perturbation,
When we use Equation (
42) for the measurement model of
Section 2.1, and we take
to coincide with position
x of a record, we obtain Equation (
12). The derivation is conceptually more rigorous here, because Equation (
40) is a genuine probability density to all orders of perturbation theory. Furthermore, the interaction is always present; no switching is necessary in order to specify the instant of detection.
There are two distinct ways that the QTP approach to measurements could resolve the superluminality problem. First, in QTP, we can employ a dressed state for the apparatus, i.e., we may employ a non-factorized initial state for the field–apparatus system. In perturbation theory, , where is a correction to the leading order in the coupling. A first-principle identification of allow us identification of the vacuum noise for the measurement. Thus, we are able to check whether the super-luminal transients are strongly dominated by noise and are hence unobservable.
Second, in QTP, the initial state is propagated by restricted propagator . This implies that for states derived by localized source , the source is Feynman-propagated only at the tree level; higher-order terms incorporate contributions from the apparatus through projector . We conjecture that these contributions will introduce desired time asymmetry in the evolution of that may lead to a suppression of transient terms.