It is difficult to shake off the feeling that all these rules and principles have a strongly pragmatic and instrumentalist character. They do not say what frameworks are or what they are supposed to represent, but instead they tell us merely how to use them and what we may or may not do with them. Observe, for example, that the single-framework rule, central to the CH approach, has the form of an unconditional command “you must not use two incompatible frameworks in one reasoning”. However, there is no explanation of the source of this postulate (a divine decree?). What would happen if we obstinately ignored this rule? Would we end up with a logical contradiction? Most certainly not, since the rules of the CH interpretation do not have the status of logical laws. Perhaps there would be some other unpleasant consequences, such as consistently losing bets (the Dutch book argument). Alternatively, there may be some ontological reasons for not mixing up different frameworks, if they turn out to describe distinct realities, as will be suggested in what follows.
The emphasis put on the rules of reasoning within particular frameworks seems to show an affinity with quantum Bayesianism (or operationalism) and its antirealist attitude towards quantum theory [
12,
13,
14]. It is no wonder then that David Wallace has voiced his doubts about whether CH is a realist theory in the conventional sense of the word [
15] (p. 39). Griffiths seem to be less pessimistic in regards to this issue, but his clarifications are rather nebulous. First off, he stresses that the choice of a particular framework does not in any way influence reality. This is little consolation to a realist, unless we specify what reality truly consists of and what its relation to the multitude of incompatible frameworks is. Griffiths uses a series of classical analogies that are supposed to throw some light on this problem [
6] (p. 99). Unfortunately none of these analogies are complete, since in the classical case there is no analogue of the quantum concept of incompatibility. For instance, he compares the choice of a quantum framework to the selection of an inertial frame of reference in special relativity, only to observe that in the latter case all inferences performed in one frame of reference can be translated into inferences in any other frame, which is not true in the quantum case. Another incomplete analogy drawn by Griffiths likens frameworks to different perspectives adopted when observing an object (for instance viewing a mountain from different sides). However, he quickly admits that these observations can be combined together into a consistent description, in contrast to the case of quantum frameworks. As we can see, it is very difficult, if not outright impossible, to explicate the concept of frameworks under the assumption of the existence of one, unified reality.
It seems to me that the only realist, objectual interpretation of a framework is that frameworks refer to some observer-independent and distinct realities. It is hopefully not too far-fetched to call these realities “worlds”. Adopting this interpretation, we can immediately explain the single-framework rule, or its cognate, the principle of incompatibility. Any reasoning has to be done in exactly one framework, because separate worlds do not overlap, and thus their descriptions cannot be combined into one consistent story. This interpretation also accounts for the principle of equality, since among alternative worlds we do not distinguish more or less real ones. The remaining principles (liberty and utility) of course will have to retain their pragmatic character, but this should not be particularly worrying for the realist (pragmatic choices regarding which world we wish to consider do not threaten the objective character of the framework-selected worlds). It may be worth noting that alternative worlds corresponding to distinct and incompatible frameworks do not have to be mutually contradictory, in the sense that there is a quantum-mechanical statement which is true in one of them and false in another. Nevertheless, they are still distinct. Their distinctness may follow from the fact that there are some properties that may be used to characterize objects in one world but not in the other. In other words, different worlds are characterized by different sets of available properties (for instance, in one world, these properties may include spin in the z direction, and in another, spin in the x direction).
The Many-Worlds Variant of CH
In spite of the above-mentioned advantage over the standard version, the hidden-variable interpretation of CH may still not be the first choice for many philosophers. It presupposes the existence of a fundamental rift between what is (the actually obtaining history) and what can be known (the probability distribution over alternative histories). Those who prefer not to introduce elements of reality that cannot be known, even in principle, may be compelled to follow a different route. Alternative histories whose probabilities under a given dynamics are non-zero may be assumed to represent distinct and parallel realities, in line with the many-worlds interpretation (MWI) of quantum mechanics. Griffiths himself makes a disparaging remark regarding this approach, but without giving any deeper reason for his preference [
6] (p. 102). However, on some occasions he slips into language that may suggest an objectivist interpretation of distinct frameworks. For instance, in [
7], he spells out the thesis of unicity, which he subsequently rejects, as follows: “at any point in time there is one and only one state of the universe which is “true”, and with which every true statement about the world must be consistent”. By negation, if we reject this claim, we have to assume that there are more than one “true” states of the universe, which we may call “worlds”. It seems to me that the many-worlds variant of CH (henceforth abbreviated as MWCH) is rather natural, so I will try to analyze it further, in spite of Griffiths’ reservations, contrasting it with the well-known Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics.
According to MWCH, there is not a single world associated with a given family of histories, but a collection of mutually exclusive worlds (except in the case of unitary families). Thus the set of all worlds can be partitioned into families, which then divide up further into individual worlds. We can illustrate this with the help of the example from the previous section. Family 0 includes just one possible world (let us call it ) with the unitary history (10), since this is the only history in this family that receives a non-zero probability. However, another group of worlds contains equally probable histories from family 1. In one of these worlds (), the electron has a well-defined x-spin before entering the magnet and then acquires the value “up” of the z-spin, while simultaneously travelling along the upper trajectory. The alternative world () differs, in that the electron leaves the magnet following the lower trajectory and possesses the “down” value of spin in the z direction. The third considered family 2, which—it has to be stressed—is equally acceptable, also separates into two worlds. One world contains an electron that already exhibits the “up” value of its z-spin before entering the magnet, and consequently follows the upper trajectory, while in the other world the electron consistently possesses z-spin “down” from the moment t1. All in all, in our simple example we have five distinct worlds , , , , and grouped into three families 0, 1, and 2.
Let us observe that worlds belonging to the same family differ with respect to the specific values possessed by the same measurable parameter (z-spin in our example). However, the differences between worlds belonging to distinct families are more subtle. For instance, worlds and diverge due to the fact that in at time t2 the electron is in a superposition with no well-defined z-spin, while in it possesses a definite value z+. On the other hand, worlds , diverge with respect to the definite values of z-spin at t2, as well as regarding the state of the electron at t1. In world , the electron has a definite value of x-spin at t1, whereas in the electron is characterized by a definite z-spin at the same moment t1. In worlds and there are no differences regarding the possessed values of the same parameter, but nevertheless the worlds are different due to their incompatible characterizations of the electron’s state at t1.
We may contrast the MWCH approach with the standard many-worlds interpretation ([
17,
18,
19]). According to the latter, the evolution of the system is given by the unitary history (10) from family
0. No other histories are admissible; they do not represent any real physical processes. However, MWI interprets the superposition
characterizing the system at time
t2 as describing two independent realities: one in which the electron has spin “up” in the
z direction, and the other in which the
z-spin of the electron is “down”. Thus, MWI admits the existence of two worlds
and
, even though no history corresponding to these worlds represents a genuine quantum-mechanical process, since these histories clearly violate the universal law of quantum mechanics, i.e., the Schrödinger equation.
This point is rarely made, so it bears repeating. Even though “officially” MWI insists that the Schrödinger equation is universally valid with no exceptions, individual worlds clearly violate it. The law of the unitary evolution applies to the entire multiverse and not the separate worlds constituting it. Observe that, in contrast to MWCH, MWI does not admit the world as a separate entity. The unitary history refers to the collection of worlds and rather than a distinct world. For the proponent of MWI there is no single world in which the electron after leaving the magnet would still be in a superposition of states with distinct locations. Superpositions of states with well-defined locations, by necessity, refer to distinct realities.
Incidentally, we may observe that many authors have combined the assumption of the fundamental reality of the wave function and its unitary evolution with the formalism of CH ([
15,
20]). That is, they admit a family of histories corresponding to the components of the universal wave function writtenin the preferred basis with respect to which the splitting into separate worlds occurs. However, this is not a full CH (at least not according to Griffiths), since it ignores other available histories. This explains a remark made in [
6], p. 95 ft. 2, that “the discussion of consistent histories presented in (Wallace 2008) bears little resemblance to what is found in (Griffiths 2002)”.
How about worlds
and
? Here, the thorny issue of the exact moment of the splitting of the worlds comes into view. The “traditional” variant of MWI assumes that the splitting occurs at the precise moment of measurement (I am tempted to call this variant the Copenhagen version of the many-worlds interpretation), when macroscopic outcomes are revealed to us. However, this solution relies on the concept of measurements being fundamentally distinct from other types of physical interactions. An alternative, rather popular view is that the splitting is a result of a physical process of decoherence, which is a physical interaction with the environment possessing a huge number of degrees of freedom (see [
21] for a comprehensive physical and philosophical analysis of decoherence). Given some specifics of this interaction, the components of the superposition corresponding to states with distinct spatial locations become “recorded” in approximately orthogonal states of the environment, which leads to the suppression of the interference (“non-diagonal”) coefficients in the density operator used to calculate the probabilities of finding the system in particular states. In our simplified example, we assume that the decohering interactions (for instance with air molecules) occur after the electron leaves the magnet and that its unitarily evolved state decomposes into parts with distinct locations. Consequently, the splitting takes place at moment
t2, which eliminates the worlds
and
, since they seem to move the moment of splitting back in time to point
t1.
On the other hand, the many-worlds variant of CH does not require any objective process leading to the splitting of the initial world into several copies, whether in the form of an interaction with a measuring device or as a result of the decoherence with the environment. For the proponent of MWCH, it just does not make sense to ask generally when exactly the electron whose initial state is splits into a number of copies corresponding to the different outcomes of the measurement down the line. There is one framework in which the splitting seems to occur at the last possible moment, and another in which from the very beginning, the electron evolves in the form of distinct copies associated with the later recorded outcomes. To make matters even more interesting, there is also a framework in which no splitting takes place at all, and the electron is always in the state of superposition. Thus, ultimately, we can get rid of the objective branching of the actual world, replacing it with the multitude of different worlds grouped in various frameworks.
Another related difference between MWI and MWCH that is worth emphasizing is that the latter easily circumvents the problem of the preferred basis that affects earlier versions of MWI. As is well known, MWI requires that there be a unique decomposition of the unitary wave function into mutually orthogonal states that define appropriate worlds. Since formally there is an infinity of ways we can decompose any vector, there has to be an additional rule selecting the preferred orthogonal basis with respect to which the decomposition is made. On the other hand, MWCH admits any decomposition of that sort, according to the principle of liberty. Any decomposition of the unitary wave function corresponds to a set of objectively existing worlds, and no decomposition is considered to be privileged.
It may be asked what is to be gained by introducing the ontologically extravagant hypothesis of the existence of a myriad of distinct worlds, far surpassing the number of the worlds admitted in the standard MW interpretation. My answer to that question would not be in terms of an immediate gain but rather in terms of the lack of a satisfactory alternative. The CH interpretation derives its flexibility from admitting an infinite number of incompatible but equally admissible frameworks in which we can describe a particular quantum process. However, from a realist perspective, these frameworks must correspond to some objective, observer-independent reality. Since incompatible frameworks cannot be combined into a consistent story, the corresponding realities must be in some sense distinct. Calling these realities “worlds” merely reflects the fact that they cannot be summed up to obtain a consistent whole. I do not see any other way to uphold the central postulates of CH while retaining the basic assumptions of scientific realism. The only alternative is to admit that quantum facts are in some sense created by the observer by the very act of selecting a particular framework.