Crime and Punishment: A Rethink
Abstract
:1. Introduction
“To understand is not to forgive or to do nothing; whereas you do not ponder whether to forgive a car that, because of problems with its brakes, has injured someone, you nevertheless protect society from it.”
2. The Pentacephalous Janus of Justice
2.1. Head 1: Reparatory
“Reparative justice measures seek to repair, in some way, the harm done to victims as a result of…violations committed against them.”
finds itself at odds with empirical evidence and the innate nature of the human mind as it is, rather than as one might wish it to be [23]. An enshrinement of reparatory procedures in law—such as that by Article 75 of the Rome Statute, which came into force in 1998, for the victims of heinous crimes that fall within the jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court:“Rather than blaming the offender, his system considers crime as a problem to be solved collectively. With the input of the courts and the community, restitution is used fairly to deal with nearly all crimes.”
—can be helpful in this regard: it establishes a uniform and independent compensatory framework that removes the need for negotiation, this negotiation having been described by some victims as reducing the impact of crime to bargaining at a flea market [21].“The Court shall establish principles relating to reparations to, or in respect of, victims, including restitution, compensation and rehabilitation.”
2.2. Head 2: Incapacitating
“…a general increase in the use of incarceration as the sanction of choice is not likely to yield major crime control benefits.”
“Selective incapacitation strategies target a small group of convicted offenders, those who are predicted to commit serious crimes at high rates, for incarceration. These high-rate serious offenders, however, are difficult to identify accurately with information currently available in official criminal history records. Preliminary research, assuming moderate accuracy, suggests that selective incapacitation may prevent some crimes, such as 5 to 10 percent of robberies by adults….”
“Recent efforts to use predictions of individual crime rates as a basis for selective incapacitation are plagued by ethical and empirical problems.”
2.3. Head 3: Deterrent
with a similar finding by Kobrin et al. [44] that:“…cross-sectional correlations between perceptions of sanction threats and self-reported criminal/deviant behavior are moderately negative for diverse offenses…,”
“…higher sanction levels were almost uniformly associated with lower crime levels…”
with, for some types of crime at least, one’s perceived identity [45] being a factor of some importance. Perhaps most importantly, for arguably the most serious of crimes, such as murder, and arguably the most severe punishment, that is, the death penalty, the desired impact of deterrence seems to diminish; as noted by Donohue and Wolfers [47]:“…social factors had considerably greater effect on crime levels than did criminal justice operations”
“…the existing evidence for deterrence [by capital punishment] is surprisingly fragile…”
2.4. Head 4: Rehabilitative
also correctly point out that:“It was clear that many crime prevention and rehabilitation efforts did not work”
much like before, raising the possibility of the importance of targeting and selectiveness in the application of rehabilitation programmes. Taking a different approach and approaching the issue from the “lived experience” point of view, Bullock and Bunce [2] find that:“…taken study by study, they [systematic reviews] showed that some programs have large and significant impacts, whereas others do not,”
“From the perspective of prisoners, the prison climate—characterized by a lack of interest in rehabilitation among correctional staff, lack of empathy and concern, and mixed but often impersonal and sometimes antagonistic relationships between prisoners and correctional staff—disrupts any ethos of rehabilitation.”
2.5. Head 5: Punitive
“Expressive punishment need not have instrumental goals: it does not necessarily aim to reduce crime or render offenders better people: rather, it seeks to communicate to the offender and to wider society the moral wrong inherent in the offender’s actions.”
3. A Rethink of Structure, Permissibility, and Aims
3.1. Against Punitive Imprisonment
“The concept of incapacitation is simple—for as long as offenders are incarcerated they clearly cannot commit crimes outside of prison. Crime is reduced because the incarcerated offenders are prevented from committing crimes in the community. At least while they are in prison, they cannot continue to commit crimes.”
3.1.1. Punitive Imprisonment Is Torture
“Prison can be seen as a tough type of punishment because it takes away your freedom, potential support networks and in many ways, it strips away your identity.”
3.1.2. Torture (or…“Torture”?)
which the analysis of Bagaric and Allan [104] correctly concludes is:“At the international law level, numerous instruments use the notion of dignity, often according it cardinal status,”
“…itself vacuous. As a legal or philosophical concept it is without bounds and ultimately is one incapable of explaining or justifying any narrower interests; it cannot do the work nonconsequentialist rights adherents demand of it. Instead, it is a notion that is used by academics, judges, and legislators when rational justifications have been exhausted.”
3.1.3. Retribution
“Prison sentences are also a message to the wider public that this is what will happen if you commit a crime. Prison advocates would say this is a message to wider society about what is right and wrong and what will happen if you commit a crime.”
“I have to bear in mind that my function is to impose appropriate punishment… I conclude that the notional determinate sentence that would provide a just and proportionate punishment is…”(all emphasis added)
“I take account of the limited mitigating factors I have mentioned in fixing the punishment part of your life sentence which is the period of time you will serve in prison before being considered for parole. In fixing it, I must reflect the need to punish you for the crime of murder and deter you and others from committing it. The law requires me to ignore any risk that you may pose to the public in the future.”(all emphasis added)
“Sentencing must protect, punish and deter”(all emphasis added)
“The measures of prison severity do not reduce the probability of recidivism. Instead, all point estimates suggest that harsh prison conditions increase post-release criminal activity…”
“Overall, the evidence seems to support a retribution model of revenge over a deterrence model.”
3.1.4. In Favour of the Permissibility of “Torture” but against Punitive Imprisonment
“The Attorney General’s Office has received ‘multiple requests’ to appeal the ‘unduly lenient’ sentence prolific rapist David Carrick was handed down today.”
Corporal Punishment
“I say ‘corporal punishment’, but it is not clear what ground ‘corporal’ is to cover. If I lock people up in prison…it is clear that their bodies (Latin corpora) and not just their minds may be unpleasantly affected: the punishment, if it is a punishment, is physical and not just mental.”
“We have in mind, I suppose, some fairly direct kind of attack or assault on a person’s body: either (a) by the infliction of physical pain, as when someone is smacked or beaten or put in the stocks, and/or (b) by the infliction of physical damage, as when thieves have their hands amputated or rapists are castrated.”
“…I do not myself think that it has been shown that corporal punishment is an unacceptably demeaning form of punishment, or that it is morally inferior to imprisonment…”
but that does not wish to witness the consequences of the said punishment and their choices. Thus, there are sound reasons to expect that the reintroduction of a wider application of corporal punishment in lieu of punitive imprisonment can act so as to moderate punishment, rather than to lead to (an even) harsher treatment of offenders; this potential benefit is, of course, further to the rectification of all other transgressions of punitive incarceration previously discussed.“The general public does not believe prisons are tough enough…,”
Embarrassing Punishment
“No one shall be subjected to…degrading treatment or punishment.”
“…vacuous…without bounds and ultimately is one incapable of explaining or justifying any narrower interests…”
Capital Punishment
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The reader should note that what is classified as a serious crime varies by the jurisdiction. It generally involves such offences as murder, manslaughter, rape, robbery, kidnapping, arson, drug trafficking, human trafficking, terrorism, etc. That serious crime is variously defined is not an issue of concern to the argument herein, seeing that my focus is on the punishment that is usually imposed on the perpetrators of crimes which are in a particular jurisdiction considered “serious”. Indeed, as shall become apparent, I reject that there is any fundamental philosophical need to make this delineation, though I recognize the possible utility of such formalisations in juridical practice. |
2 | To emphasise, this does not mean that every mind can change to this degree, but merely that some can. |
3 | Available online: https://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-11723081/David-Carrick-country-s-worst-sex-offenders.html (accessed on 20 May 2023) |
References
- Melossi, D.; Pavarini, M. The Prison and The Factory: Origins of The Penitentiary System; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Bullock, K.; Bunce, A. ‘The prison don’t talk to you about getting out of prison’: On why prisons in England and Wales fail to rehabilitate prisoners. Criminol. Crim. Justice 2020, 20, 111–127. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hough, M. Populism and punitive penal policy. Crim. Justice Matters 2002, 49, 4–5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dugdale, W.; Hean, S. The application of Norwegian humane ideals by front-line workers when collaboratively reintegrating inmates back into society. In Improving Interagency Collaboration, Innovation and Learning in Criminal Justice Systems; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2021; p. 111. [Google Scholar]
- Ganapathy, N. Rehabilitation, reintegration and recidivism: A theoretical and methodological reflection. Asia Pac. J. Soc. Work Dev. 2018, 28, 154–167. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harrison, P.M.; Karberg, J.C. Prison and Jail Inmates at Midyear 2003; US Department of Justice: Washington, DC, USA, 2004.
- Warmsley, R. Prison health care and the extent of prison overcrowding. Int. J. Prison. Health 2005, 1, 3–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fair, H.; Walmsley, R. World prison population list. Educare 2021, 5. Available online: https://www.prisonstudies.org/sites/default/files/resources/downloads/world_prison_population_list_13th_edition.pdf (accessed on 20 May 2023).
- Ministry of Justice. Criminal Justice Statistics Quarterly: December 2019; Ministry of Justice: London, UK, 2020.
- World Prison Brief. World Prison Brief Data; Institute for Crime & Justice Policy Research: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Sturge, G.; Tunnicliffe, R. UK Prison Population Statistics; House of Commons Library: London, UK, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Bonta, J.; Gendreau, P. Reexamining the cruel and unusual punishment of prison life. Law Hum. Behav. 1990, 14, 347. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hartman, K.E. Too Cruel, Not Unusual Enough; The Other Death Penalty Project: Lancaster, CA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Rafter, N.H. Creating Born Criminals; University of Illinois Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Dissel, A. Rehabilitation and reintegration in African prisons. In Human Rights in African Prisons; HSRC Press: Cape Town, South Africa, 2008; pp. 89–103. [Google Scholar]
- Baybutt, M.; Dooris, M.; Farrier, A. Growing health in UK prison settings. Health Promot. Int. 2019, 34, 792–802. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zeki, S.; Goodenough, O.; Sapolsky, R.M. The frontal cortex and the criminal justice system. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London. Ser. B Biol. Sci. 2004, 359, 1787–1796. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arandjelović, O. Resolving the ethical quagmire of the persistent vegetative state. J. Eval. Clin. Pract. 2023. Available online: https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jep.13848 (accessed on 20 May 2023). [CrossRef]
- Muddell, K.; Hawkins, S. Gender and transitional justice: A training module series. Int. Cent. Transit. Justice 2018, 20, 26. Available online: https://www.ictj.org/sites/default/files/3_Gender%20%26%20TJ%20-%20Reparative%20Justice%20-%20Speaker%20Notes.pdf (accessed on 20 May 2023).
- Geistfeld, M.A. Punitive Damages, Retribution, and Due Process. S. Cal. L. Rev. 2007, 81, 263. [Google Scholar]
- Hulst, L.; Akkermans, A.J. Can money symbolize acknowledgment? How victims’ relatives perceive monetary awards for their emotional harm. Psychol. Inj. Law 2011, 4, 245–262. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weitekamp, E. Reparative justice: Towards a victim oriented system. Eur. J. Crim. Pol’y Rsch. 1993, 1, 70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chester, D.S.; Martelli, A.M. Why Revenge Sometimes Feels So Good. In Handbook of Forgiveness; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2019; pp. 43–51. [Google Scholar]
- Carlen, P. Against rehabilitation; for reparative justice. In Crime, Justice and Social Democracy; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2013; pp. 89–104. [Google Scholar]
- Buxton, R. Reparative justice for climate refugees. Philosophy 2019, 94, 193–219. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harman, S.; Erfani, P.; Goronga, T.; Hickel, J.; Morse, M.; Richardson, E.T. Global vaccine equity demands reparative justice—Not charity. BMJ Glob. Health 2021, 6, e006504. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wyns, A. COP27 establishes loss and damage fund to respond to human cost of climate change. Lancet Planet. Health 2022, 7, e21–e22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Agozino, B. Reparative justice: The final stage of decolonization. Punishm. Soc. 2021, 23, 613–630. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aertsen, I.; Pali, B. Critical Restorative Justice; Bloomsbury Publishing: London, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Tirrell, L. Transitional justice in post-genocide Rwanda: An integrative approach. In Theorizing Transitional Justice; Corradetti, C., Eisikovits, N., Rotondi, J., Eds.; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2015; pp. 237–252. [Google Scholar]
- Zimring, F.E.; Hawkins, G. Incapacitation: Penal Confinement and The Restraint of Crime; Oxford University Press on Demand: Oxford, UK, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Shavell, S. A model of optimal incapacitation. Am. Econ. Rev. 1987, 77, 107–110. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes, R.C. Imprisonment and the right to freedom of movement. In Rethinking Punishment in The Era of Mass Incarceration; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2017; pp. 89–104. [Google Scholar]
- Ashenden, S. Policing perversion: The contemporary governance of paedophilia. Cult. Values 2002, 6, 197–222. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Habib, J. Cyber crime and punishment: Filtering out Internet felons. Fordham Intell. Prop. Media Ent. LJ 2003, 14, 1051. [Google Scholar]
- Wermink, H.; Apel, R.; Nieuwbeerta, P.; Blokland, A.A. The incapacitation effect of first-time imprisonment: A matched samples comparison. J. Quant. Criminol. 2013, 29, 579–600. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Visher, C.A. Incapacitation and crime control: Does a “Lock’em up” strategy reduce crime? Justice Q. 1987, 4, 513–543. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cohen, J. Incapacitation as a strategy for crime control: Possibilities and pitfalls. Crime Justice 1983, 5, 1–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Petrich, D.M.; Pratt, T.C.; Jonson, C.L.; Cullen, F.T. Custodial sanctions and reoffending: A meta-analytic review. Crime Justice 2021, 50, 353–424. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Apel, R.; Nagin, D.S. General deterrence: A review of recent evidence. Crime Public Policy 2011, 4, 411–436. [Google Scholar]
- Osgood, J.M. Is revenge about retributive justice, deterring harm, or both? Soc. Personal. Psychol. Compass 2017, 11, e12296. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tappolet, C. Emotion, motivation, and action: The case of fear. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion; OUP Oxford: Oxford, UK, 2010; pp. 325–345. [Google Scholar]
- Paternoster, R. The deterrent effect of the perceived certainty and severity of punishment: A review of the evidence and issues. Justice Q. 1987, 4, 173–217. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kobrin, S.; Lubeck, S.; Hansen, E.; Yeaman, R. The Deterrent Effectiveness of Criminal Justice Sanction Strategies: Final Report; University of Southern California: Los Angeles, CA, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Murphy, K.; Bradford, B.; Jackson, J. Motivating compliance behavior among offenders: Procedural justice or deterrence? Crim. Justice Behav. 2016, 43, 102–118. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paternoster, R. How much do we really know about criminal deterrence. J. Crim. L. Criminol. 2010, 100, 765. [Google Scholar]
- Donohue, J.J.; Wolfers, J. Uses and abuses of empirical evidence in the death penalty debate. Stanf. Law Rev. 2006, 58, 791–845. [Google Scholar]
- Lamperti, J.; Marshall, J.; Nixon, R.M. Does Capital Punishment Deter Murder. 1994. Available online: https://chance.dartmouth.edu/teaching_aids/books_articles/JLpaper.pdf (accessed on 17 February 2023).
- Mauer, M. The impact of mandatory minimum penalties in federal sentencing. Judicature 2010, 94, 6. [Google Scholar]
- Hofer, P.J. Review of the US Sentencing Commission’s Report to Congress: Mandatory Minimum Penalties in the Federal Criminal Justice System. Fed. Sentencing Rep. 2012, 24, 193–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bottoms, A.E. The suspended sentence in England, 1967–1978. Br. J. Criminol. 1981, 21, 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Roberts, J.V. The role of criminal record in the sentencing process. Crime Justice 1997, 22, 303–362. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bailey, V. The Rise and Fall of the Rehabilitative Ideal, 1895–1970; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Sherman, L.W. The use and usefulness of criminology, 1751–2005: Enlightened justice and its failures. Ann. Am. Acad. Political Soc. Sci. 2005, 600, 115–135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Howard, J. The State of the Prisons in England and Wales; W. Eyres: Hope Valley, UK, 1780. [Google Scholar]
- Robinson, G. Late-modern rehabilitation: The evolution of a penal strategy. Punishm. Soc. 2008, 10, 429–445. [Google Scholar]
- Emener, W.G. Futuristic perspectives and recommendations for the National Rehabilitation Association. J. Rehabil. 1986, 52, 65. [Google Scholar]
- Durkheim, E. Two laws of penal evolution. Econ. Soc. 1973, 2, 285–308. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kaempf, A. Punishment and Culture. Psychiatr. Serv. 2009, 60, 852. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Garland, D. Punishment and social solidarity. In The SAGE Handbook of Punishment and Society; SAGE: Newcastle upon Tyne, UK, 2013; pp. 23–39. [Google Scholar]
- Tallgren, I. The Durkheimian Spell of International Criminal Law? Rev. Interdiscip. D’études Juridiques 2013, 71, 137–169. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hakeem, F.B. An Examination of The Socio-Economic Determinants of Punishment Using Abductive Polynomial Networks; City University of New York: New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Carvalho, H.; Chamberlen, A. Why punishment pleases: Punitive feelings in a world of hostile solidarity. Punishm. Soc. 2018, 20, 217–234. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mastrobuoni, G.; Terlizzese, D. Rehabilitating rehabilitation: Prison conditions and recidivism. Einaudi Inst. Econ. Financ. EIEF Work. Pap. Ser. 2014. No 1413. Available online: https://conference.iza.org/conference_files/riskonomics2015/mastrobuoni_g3754.pdf (accessed on 20 May 2023).
- Johnson, L.M. A Place for Art in Prison: Art as A Tool for Rehabilitation and Management. Southwest J. Crim. Justice 2008, 5, 100–180. [Google Scholar]
- Clements, P. The rehabilitative role of arts education in prison: Accommodation or enlightenment? Int. J. Art Des. Educ. 2004, 23, 169–178. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tett, L.; Anderson, K.; McNeill, F.; Overy, K.; Sparks, R. Learning, rehabilitation and the arts in prisons: A Scottish case study. Stud. Educ. Adults 2012, 44, 171–185. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Spark, C.; Harris, A. Vocation, vocation: A study of prisoner education for women. J. Sociol. 2005, 41, 143–161. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Coates, S. Unlocking Potential: A Review of Education in Prison; Ministry of Justice: London, UK, 2016.
- Rentzmann, W. Prison philosophy and prison education. J. Correct. Educ. 1996, 47, 58–63. [Google Scholar]
- Esperian, J.H. The effect of prison education programs on recidivism. J. Correct. Educ. 2010, 61, 316–334. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, F.H. Prisoners’ Work and Vocational Training; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Vacca, J.S. Educated prisoners are less likely to return to prison. J. Correct. Educ. 2004, 55, 297–305. [Google Scholar]
- Van den Haag, E. Could successful rehabilitation reduce the crime rate. J. Crim. L. Criminol. 1982, 73, 1022. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cullen, F.T. Rehabilitation: Beyond nothing works. Crime Justice 2013, 42, 299–376. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weisburd, D.; Farrington, D.P.; Gill, C. What works in crime prevention and rehabilitation: An assessment of systematic reviews. Criminol. Public Policy 2017, 16, 415–449. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schrink, J.; Hamm, M.S. Misconceptions concerning correctional counseling. J. Offender Couns. Serv. Rehabil. 1990, 14, 133–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bagaric, M. Scientific proof that humans enjoy punishing wrongdoers: The implications for punishment and sentencing. IJPS 2005, 1, 98. [Google Scholar]
- Dressler, J. Hating Criminals: How Can Something That Feels So Good Be Wrong? Mich. Law Rev. 1990, 88, 1448–1473. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Clutton-Brock, T.H.; Parker, G.A. Punishment in animal societies. Nature 1995, 373, 209–216. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miethe, T.D.; Lu, H. Punishment: A Comparative Historical Perspective; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Gibbs, J.P. Crime, punishment, and deterrence. Southwest. Soc. Sci. Q. 1968, 48, 515–530. [Google Scholar]
- Arandjelović, O. On the value of life. Int. J. Appl. Philos. 2022, 35, 227–241. [Google Scholar]
- Honderich, T. Punishment, the new retributivism, and political philosophy. R. Inst. Philos. Suppl. 1984, 18, 117–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Laxminarayan, M.; Bosmans, M.; Porter, R.; Sosa, L. Victim satisfaction with criminal justice: A systematic review. Vict. Offenders 2013, 8, 119–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barton, C. Empowerment and retribution in criminal justice. Prof. Ethics Multidiscip. J. 1999, 7, 111–135. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Klimchuk, D. Retribution, restitution and revenge. Law Philos. 2001, 20, 81–101. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gromet, D.M.; Okimoto, T.G.; Wenzel, M.; Darley, J.M. A victim-centered approach to justice? Victim satisfaction effects on third-party punishments. Law Hum. Behav. 2012, 36, 375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Guillot, J. Reentry support in community legal access points: A lawyer’s perspective. Tepsis Pap. 2016. Available online: https://www.prison-insider.com/files/f70b48cf/tp_19_guillot_v2.pdf (accessed on 20 May 2023).
- Phelps, M.S. Rehabilitation in the punitive era: The gap between rhetoric and reality in US prison programs. Law Soc. Rev. 2011, 45, 33–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Schaefer, L. Correcting the “correctional” component of the corrections officer role: How offender custodians can contribute to rehabilitation and reintegration. Corrections 2018, 3, 38–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacKenzie, D.L. Criminal justice and crime prevention. In Preventing Crime: What Works, What Doesn’t, What’s Promising; US Department of Justice: Washington, DC, USA, 1997; pp. 82–89. [Google Scholar]
- Toch, H. Prison walls do a prison make: The untimely demise of visitation rights. Crim. Law Bull. 2003, 39, 647–658. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas, R.; Matusitz, J. Pet therapy in correctional institutions: A perspective from relational-cultural theory. J. Evid.-Inf. Soc. Work 2016, 13, 228–235. [Google Scholar]
- Marti, I. A ‘home’or ‘a place to be, but not to live’: Arranging the prison cell. In The Prison Cell: Embodied and Everyday Spaces of Incarceration; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2020; pp. 121–142. [Google Scholar]
- Charles, A. Is Prison an Effective Form of Punishment? 2021. Available online: https://www.law.ac.uk/resources/blog/is-prison-effective/ (accessed on 20 May 2023).
- Bradley, G.V. Retribution and the secondary aims of punishment. Am. J. Juris. 1999, 44, 105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Miller, S. Is torture ever morally justifiable? Int. J. Appl. Philos. 2005, 19, 179–192. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, G.E. On the permissibility of torture. J. Med. Ethics 1980, 6, 11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- McMahan, J. Torture in Principle and in Practice. Public Aff. Q. 2008, 22, 91–108. [Google Scholar]
- Shue, H. Torture. In The Routledge Handbook of Global Ethics; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2015; pp. 125–138. [Google Scholar]
- Gross, O. The Prohibition on Torture and the Limits of the Law. 2004. Available online: https://ssrn.com/abstract=485043 (accessed on 20 May 2023).
- Allhoff, F. A defense of torture: Separation of cases, ticking time-bombs, and moral justification. Int. J. Appl. Philos. 2005, 19, 243–264. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bagaric, M.; Allan, J. The vacuous concept of dignity. J. Hum. Rights 2006, 5, 257–270. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Quervain, D.J.F.; Fischbacher, U.; Treyer, V.; Schellhammer, M.; Schnyder, U.; Buck, A.; Fehr, E. The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Science 2004, 305, 1254–1258. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Knutson, B. Sweet revenge? Science 2004, 305, 1246–1247. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Prooijen, J.W. The Moral Punishment Instinct; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Van Ginneken, E.F.; Hayes, D. ‘Just’ punishment? Offenders’ views on the meaning and severity of punishment. Criminol. Crim. Justice 2017, 17, 62–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Seron, C.; Pereira, J.; Kovath, J. How citizens assess just punishment for police misconduct. Criminology 2006, 44, 925–960. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Samuel, W.; Moulds, E. The Effect of Crime Severity on Perceptions of Fair Punishment: A California Case Study. J. Crim. L. Criminol. 1986, 77, 931. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gwin, J.S. Juror sentiment on just punishment: Do the Federal Sentencing Guidelines reflect community values. Harv. L. Pol’y Rev. 2010, 4, 173. [Google Scholar]
- Maxfield, L.D.; Martin, W.; Kitchens, C. Just Punishment: Public Perceptions and The Federal Sentencing Guidelines; US Sentencing Commission: Washington, DC, USA, 1996.
- Cavender, G. Justice, sanctioning, and the justice model. Criminology 1984, 22, 203–213. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pickering, M. Kant on Why Criminal Offenders Must Be Punished. South. J. Philos. 2022, 60, 637–663. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Carlsmith, K.M.; Darley, J.M.; Robinson, P.H. Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2002, 83, 284. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Drago, F.; Galbiati, R.; Vertova, P. Prison conditions and recidivism. Am. Law Econ. Rev. 2011, 13, 103–130. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hart, H.L. The presidential address: Prolegomenon to the principles of punishment. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society; Wiley: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1959; Volume 60, pp. 1–26. [Google Scholar]
- Benn, S.I. An approach to the problems of punishment. Philosophy 1958, 33, 325–341. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Flew, A. The justification of punishment. Philosophy 1954, 29, 291–307. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zaibert, L. Punishment and Retribution; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Hanna, N. Say what? A critique of expressive retributivism. Law Phil. 2008, 27, 123. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wringe, B. Must punishment be intended to cause suffering? Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2013, 16, 863–877. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Njoku, F.O. HLA Hart on Philosophical and Legal Conception of Punishment. Int. J. Theol. Reform. Tradit. 2012, 4, 220–235. [Google Scholar]
- Bilz, K. The puzzle of delegated revenge. BUL Rev. 2007, 87, 1059. [Google Scholar]
- Willett, J.B.; Sayer, A.G. Using covariance structure analysis to detect correlates and predictors of individual change over time. Psychol. Bull. 1994, 116, 363. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arandjelović, O. On the subjective value of life. Philosophies 2023, 8, 23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sheldon, K.M. Positive value change during college: Normative trends and individual differences. J. Res. Personal. 2005, 39, 209–223. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Armon, C. Adult moral development, experience and education. J. Moral Educ. 1998, 27, 345–370. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Whitehead, A.N. Process and Reality; Simon and Schuster: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Jang, S.J.; Johnson, B.R. Religion and Rehabilitation as Moral Reform: Conceptualization and Preliminary Evidence. Am. J. Crim. Justice 2022, 2022, 1–27. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Akunesiobike, C.A. The Role of Religious Groups in Offender Reformation: A Study of the Port Harcourt Prison in Rivers State, Nigeria. J. Pan Afr. Stud. 2016, 9, 104–121. [Google Scholar]
- Chui, W.H.; Cheng, K.K.Y. Self-perceived role and function of Christian prison chaplains and Buddhist volunteers in Hong Kong prisons. Int. J. Offender Ther. Comp. Criminol. 2013, 57, 154–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Liebling, A.; Maruna, S. The Effects of Imprisonment; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Alexander, L. Retributivism and the Inadvertent Punishment of the Innocent. Law Philos. 1983, 2, 233–246. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lippke, R. Punishing the guilty, not punishing the innocent. J. Moral Philos. 2010, 7, 462–488. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Giallombardo, R. Social roles in a prison for women. Soc. Probl. 1966, 13, 268–288. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodstein, L.; Wright, K.N. Inmate adjustment to prison. In The American Prison. Law, Society and Policy; Springer: Boston, MA, USA, 1989; pp. 229–251. [Google Scholar]
- Liebling, A.; Ludlow, A. Suicide, distress and the quality of prison life. In Handbook on Prisons; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2016; Volume 224. [Google Scholar]
- Kolber, A.J. The subjective experience of punishment. Columbia Law Rev. 2009, 109, 182–236. [Google Scholar]
- Bukstel, L.H.; Kilmann, P.R. Psychological effects of imprisonment on confined individuals. Psychol. Bull. 1980, 88, 469. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Haney, C. The psychological impact of incarceration: Implications for post-prison adjustment. In Prisoners Once Removed: The Impact of Incarceration and Reentry on Children, Families, and Communities; University of California: Santa Cruz, CA, USA, 2003; Volume 33, p. 66. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, A.P.; Rozelle, R.M.; Chang, W.C. Perceived punishment and reward values of supervisor actions in a Chinese sample. Psychol. Stud. 1990, 35, 1–10. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, J. Corporal punishment revisited. Camb. J. Educ. 2002, 32, 409–416. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Scarre, G. Corporal punishment. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2003, 6, 295–316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Newman, G.R. Just and Painful: A Case for the Corporal Punishment of Criminals; Macmillan New York: New York, NY, USA, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Smullyan, R.M. Who Knows?: A Study of Religious Consciousness; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Arandjelović, O. Crime and Punishment: A Rethink. Philosophies 2023, 8, 47. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030047
Arandjelović O. Crime and Punishment: A Rethink. Philosophies. 2023; 8(3):47. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030047
Chicago/Turabian StyleArandjelović, Ognjen. 2023. "Crime and Punishment: A Rethink" Philosophies 8, no. 3: 47. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030047
APA StyleArandjelović, O. (2023). Crime and Punishment: A Rethink. Philosophies, 8(3), 47. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030047